Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-29T18:12:05.127Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Beyond Science Wars Redux: Feminist Philosophy of Science as Trustworthy Science Criticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Abstract

Bruno Latour is not the only scholar to reflect on his earlier contributions to science studies with some regret and resolve over climate skepticism and science denialism. Given the ascendency of merchants of doubt, should those who share Latour's concerns join the scientists they study in circling the wagons, or is there a productive role still for science studies to question and critique scientists and scientific institutions? I argue for the latter, looking to postpositivist feminist philosophy as exemplified by Alison Wylie and Lynn Nelson, among others, as a guide. Feminist philosophers of science who ground their analysis in a detailed understanding of scientific practice are not science's champions nor its antagonists, but they do stand in a distinct relationship to science. If not merchants of doubt, are they scientific gadflies or perhaps in scientific loyal opposition? Though these notions can underwrite useful approaches to science studies, neither captures the distinctive interdependency and interestedness of feminist philosophers and science. I suggest that we would be better served by the notion of trustworthy science criticism, building on the analyses of trust and trustworthiness by Annette Baier, among others, attendant to the dynamics of interdependency in trust relationships.

Type
Musing
Copyright
Copyright © 2019, Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baier, Annette. 1986. Trust and anti‐trust. Ethics 96 (2): 231–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, Annette. 1991. Trust. Tanner lectures on human values. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ceccarelli, Leah. 2011. Manufactured scientific controversy. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 14 (2): 195228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Harry. 2004. Interactional expertise as a third kind of knowledge. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3 (2): 1243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conkey, Margaret, and Gero, Joan. 1997. Programme to practice. Annual Review of Archeology 26: 411–37.Google Scholar
de Melo‐Martin, Inmaculada, and Intemann, Kristen. 2018. The fight against doubt. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Vrieze, Jan. 2017. Bruno Latour, a veteran of the “science wars”, has a new mission, Science, October 12.Google Scholar
Durkin, Mary, and Gay, Oonagh. 2006. Her Majesty's opposition. House of Commons Library SN/PC/3910.Google Scholar
Faulkner, Paul. 2007. Telling and trusting. Mind 116 (464): 875902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. 1978. Science in a free society. New York: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. 2010. Against method. 4th edition. New York: Verso Books.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerken, Heather. 2014. The loyal opposition. Yale Law Journal 123 (6): 16262133.Google Scholar
Gero, Joan. 1991. Genderlithics: Women's roles in stone tool production In Engendering archeology, ed. Gero, Joan and Conkey, M. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gross, Paul, and Levitt, Norman. 1994. Higher superstition. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Clive. 2014. The Anthropocene: Too serious for postmodernist games. Immanence, August 19.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Clive. 2017. Defiant earth: The fate of humans in the Anthropocene. Malden, Mass.: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, Donna. 1991. Simians, cyborgs, and women. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Intemann, Kristen. 2010. 25 years of feminist empiricism and standpoint theory. Hypatia 25 (4): 778–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Karen. 1996. Trust as an affective attitude. Ethics 107 (1): 425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koertge, Noretta, ed. 1998. A house built on sand. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kofman, Ava. 2018. Bruno Latour, post‐truth philosopher, mounts a defense of science. New York Times, October 25.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2015. Telling friend from foe in the time of the Anthropocene. In The Anthropocene and the global environmental crisis, ed. Hamilton, Clive, Bonneuil, Christophe, and Gemenne, François. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2017. Facing Gaia: Eight lectures on the new climate regime. Malden, Mass.: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth. 1993. Pre‐theoretic assumptions in evolutionary explanations of female sexuality. Philosophical Studies 69 (2–3): 139–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth. 1995. Objectivity and the double standard for feminist epistemologies. Synthese 104 (3): 351–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth. 1997a. Feyerabend, Mill, and pluralism. Philosophy of Science 64 (4): S396S407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth. 1997b. Science and anti‐science: Objectivity and its real enemies. In Feminism, science and the philosophy of science, ed. Hankinson Nelson, Lynnand Nelson, Jack. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elizabeth. 2005. The case of the female orgasm. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
MacKendrick, Norah. 2017. Out of the labs and into the streets. Sociological Forum 32 (4): 896902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michaels, David. 2008. Doubt is their product. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson, and Wylie, Alison. 1998. Coming to terms with the value(s) of science: Insights from feminist science scholarship. Workshop on Science and Values, University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
Oreskes, Naomi, and Conway, Erik. 2011. Merchants of doubt. New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Plaisance, Kathryn, and Kennedy, Eric. 2014. A pluralistic approach to interactional expertise. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 47: 6068.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whooley, Owen. 2018. A (partial) defense of (some) science. Sociological Forum 33 (1): 251–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolpert, Lewis. 1992. The unnatural nature of science. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wylie, Alison. 1992. The interplay of evidential constraints and political interests. American Antiquity 57 (1): 1535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, Alison. 1993. A proliferation of new archeologies: Beyond objectivism and relativism. In Archeological theory, ed. Yoffee, Norman and Sherratt, Andrew. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wylie, Alison. 1997a. The engendering of archeology: Refiguring feminist science studies. Osiris 12: 8099.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, Alison. 1997b. Good science, bad science, or science as usual? Feminist critiques of science. In Women in human evolution, ed. Hager, Linda. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wylie, Alison. 2002. Thinking from things: Essays in the philosophy of archeology. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar