Skip to main content
Advertisement
Browse Subject Areas
?

Click through the PLOS taxonomy to find articles in your field.

For more information about PLOS Subject Areas, click here.

  • Loading metrics

Preserved intention understanding during moral judgments in schizophrenia

  • Lisa Kronbichler ,

    Roles Formal analysis, Investigation, Methodology, Visualization, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing

    li.kronbichler@gmail.com

    Affiliations Neuroscience Institute, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria, Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience and Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria, Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy & Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria

  • Renate Stelzig-Schöler,

    Roles Investigation, Supervision

    Affiliation Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy & Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria

  • Melanie Lenger,

    Roles Investigation

    Affiliation Department of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy, Medical University of Graz, Graz, Austria

  • Stefanie Weber,

    Roles Investigation

    Affiliation Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy & Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria

  • Brandy-Gale Pearce,

    Roles Investigation

    Affiliation Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy & Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria

  • Luise-Antonia Reich,

    Roles Investigation

    Affiliation Department of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry, Psychotherapy, and Psychosomatics, University Medical Center Hamburg-Eppendorf, Hamburg, Germany

  • Wolfgang Aichhorn,

    Roles Conceptualization, Resources, Supervision

    Affiliation Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy & Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria

  • Martin Kronbichler

    Roles Conceptualization, Funding acquisition, Methodology, Project administration, Supervision, Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing

    Affiliations Neuroscience Institute, Christian-Doppler University Hospital, Paracelsus Medical University, Salzburg, Austria, Centre for Cognitive Neuroscience and Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg, Salzburg, Austria

Abstract

Introduction

Although there is convincing evidence for socio-cognitive impairments in schizophrenia spectrum disorder (SSD), little evidence is found for deficient moral cognition. We investigated whether patients with SSD showed altered moral judgments in a story task where the protagonist either had a neutral or malicious intention towards another person. This paradigm examined whether SSD relates to altered moral cognition in general or specifically to impaired integration of prior information (such as beliefs) in moral judgments.

Methods

23 patients and 32 healthy controls read vignettes created in a 2 x 2 design. The protagonist in each story either had a neutral or negative intention towards another person which, as a result, either died (negative outcome) or did not die (neutral outcome). Participants rated the moral permissibility of the protagonist’s action. Standard null hypothesis significance testing and equivalent Bayes analyses are reported.

Results

Schizophrenia patients did not differ significantly in permissibility ratings from healthy controls. This finding was supported by the Bayes analyses which favoured the null hypothesis. Task performance was not related to symptom severity or medication.

Conclusions

The current findings do not support the notion that moral judgments are deficient in schizophrenia. Furthermore, the current study shows that patients do not have observable difficulties in integrating the protagonist’s belief in the rating of the moral permissibility of the action-outcome.

1.Introduction

Schizophrenia-spectrum disorders (SSD) are characterized by altered social cognition [1,2], which plays a fundamental role in everyday functional outcome [3,4]. A prominent factor of such socio-cognitive functions is Theory of Mind (ToM), which is the ability to recognize the intentions and beliefs of others and to predict their behavior based on an understanding of their minds [5]. While there is broad agreement in behavioral and neuroimaging research that ToM processes are impaired in schizophrenia [6,7], there is one related aspect that has received relatively little attention and which yields mixed findings, namely moral cognition. Moral cognition describes the thinking about (culture-specific) sets of values and behavior that guide socially accepted manners. It is reflected in research on for example harm and pro- or anti-social behavior [8,9]. On the neuronal level, moral cognition is related to activation in regions that are involved in ToM processes such as TPJ, PFC and precuneus, but also the orbitofrontal cortex and the amygdala [10,11].

Due to their impairments in ToM and empathy, a common assumption is that patients with SSD make more utilitarian choices [12] in moral dilemma tasks. Making utilitarian choices means that one chooses the action that will result in the greatest good for the most, thereby justifying the means (e.g., killing one person to save a group; [13,14]). This idea is supported by the finding that SSD patients show alterations in the prefrontal cortex [7], which is related to moral goal pursuit [15] and that damage in this area is linked to stronger utilitarian thinking [16]. Behavioral studies reveal mixed results, showing fragile effects that often depend on question probe and perspective [14,1719]. Furthermore, common tasks such as Kohlberg’s Moral Judgment Interview require verbal abilities ([2022]) and abstract reasoning, both of which are impaired in SSD [2022]. In general, psychiatric research on moral cognition is not yet conclusive. First, the number of available studies is small, thus more research is needed to allow for conclusive meta-analyses. Second, the comparability of published studies is limited since not all experiments examine the same dimension of morality, which is assumed to consist of a) the moral decision itself, b) the moral judgment about how appropriate the action is and c) the moral inference describing how a person is perceived based on his/her action and additional information about the person [23]. Studies on SSD revealed evidence for impaired [13,14,17,22] as well as intact moral decision-making [13,1719]). There is some evidence for impaired moral judgment in SSD [14,24,25], however, a more recent examination merely found prolonged but otherwise intact moral judgments in patients [14]. Concerning moral inference, there are several studies on healthy controls showing that information about the acting person alters moral permissibility ratings [2628] and that this process is related to activation in ToM areas [28]. To our knowledge, there is no study on moral inference in SSD available yet. However, prior information about the other person’s intention or reliability [29,30] plays a critical role in real-life moral judgment. To illustrate, intentionally killing someone by knowingly putting poisonous granules in the other person’s coffee versus unintentionally killing someone by putting granules in their coffee (believing it is sugar) are two morally distinct actions, although the physical action and the outcome remain the same in both scenarios (example taken from [29]).

In the current study, we examine how information about the intention of the actor influences how permissibly the action is perceived by healthy participants and patients with SSD. Although we do not directly assess how the actor itself is perceived, an examination of the relationship between prior information about the acting person and moral judgment will provide first insights into the interplay of these two factors.

Since patients with SSD often show deficient mentalizing abilities, we assume that they should reveal problems with integrating the protagonist’s belief into their moral judgments (details below). Evidence for this assumption comes from patients with autism as well as patients with frontotemporal dementia and frontal stroke, who overly rely on action-outcome (utilitarian approach), thus judging accidental harms as less permissible and attempted but failed harms as more permissible [29,31].

Healthy controls and patients with SSD rate the moral permissibility of scenarios that are designed in a 2x2 way: The protagonist in each story can either hold a negative (intention to kill someone) or a neutral belief (no murderous intentions) about his action which then leads to a negative (the other person dies) or neutral outcome (the other person does not die).

If our SSD sample has difficulties understanding the intention and belief of the protagonist, we should find that patients mostly rely their ratings on the action outcome since the intention of the protagonist (to harm or not to harm the other person) is not informative to them.

This should lead to pronounced group differences especially in conditions where the protagonist’s intention is in conflict with the situation outcome (e.g. Accidental Harm Condition: The protagonist unintentionally kills the other person. Attempted Harm Condition: The protagonist aims to kill the other person but does not succeed).

Given that the utilitarian approach holds true for patients with SSD, we expect them to show stricter ratings in the Accidental Harm condition and more tolerant ratings in the Attempted Harm condition.

However, as mentioned above, moral judgment tasks show mixed results concerning moral impairments in schizophrenia, therefore raising the possibility that patients with SSD might not reveal alterations at all. If this is the case, we will nonetheless provide post-hoc t-tests for each condition, since the critical alterations might be reflected in group differences in single conditions only [29]. Furthermore, we will also include Bayes analyses to tackle the actual support for the null over the alternative hypothesis.

2. Methods

Written informed consent was provided by each participant (see below). The study was approved by the local ethics committee Ethikkomission Salzburg, Austria (415-E/981/2-2008).

2.1 Participants

Participants in the patient group were 23 male adults, who had received a formal ICD-10 diagnosis (which was verified before study participation by certified psychiatrists using the Mini-International Neuropsychiatric Interview [32] in combination with the ICD-10 Diagnostic Checklist for Schizophrenia [33]) in the schizophrenia spectrum group (F20) or the schizoaffective disorders spectrum group (F25). Exclusion criteria for both patients and healthy controls were psychiatric disorders other than schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorders, current or past neurological insults like head trauma, and current substance abuse. Controls were screened for mental and physical health and were excluded if met the criteria for psychiatric disorders or exhibited a family history of psychiatric illness. All patients were recruited from the outpatient and inpatient units of the Department of Psychiatry, Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, Christian-Doppler Medical Centre, PMU, Salzburg, Austria. All patients received antipsychotic medication. Patients were clinically stable with relatively mild symptoms at the time of assessment (PANSS [34]). Healthy control participants were 32 male adults. Efforts were made to recruit a healthy male control group that matched the SSD group in demographics and education. Thus, advertisements for HCs specified that we were particularly interested in participants who finished high school, but that did not necessarily attend or complete college. Subjects were remunerated for participation and all participants provided written informed consent. Only participants who were authorized to give informed consent themselves (>18 years, not under external custody) were included in the study. Furthermore, patient recruitment was exclusively done by an experienced team of psychiatrists. Demographic data and clinical rating are listed in Table 1.

thumbnail
Table 1. Demographic data and clinical ratings of patients with SSD and controls.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.t001

2.2 Socio-cognitive tasks

Moral judgment was examined using a translated (German) paper-pencil version of the moral judgment task [29]. Participants read 24 short vignettes in a 2 x 2 design (intention, outcome). To give an example: Grace and her friend are visiting a chemical plant. Grace gets them coffee and puts a white substance (presumably sugar) into her friend’s coffee. The storyline is varied in terms of Grace’s intention and the outcome of her action: She can either hold a neutral intention (putting the white substance into her friend’s coffee assuming it is sugar) or a negative intention (putting the white substance into the coffee knowing it is poison). Subsequently, her friend either dies (negative outcome) or does not die (neutral outcome). This results in four conditions:

  1. Accidental Harm (neutral intention, negative outcome): Grace accidentally puts poison into the coffee believing it is sugar. Her friend dies.
  2. Neutral Acts (neutral intention, neutral outcome): Grace puts sugar into the coffee, believing it is sugar. Her friend does not die.
  3. Attempted Harm (negative intention, neutral outcome): Grace puts sugar into the coffee, but she believes it is poison. Her friend does not die.
  4. Intended Harm (negative intention, negative outcome): Grace knowingly puts poison into the coffee. Her friend dies.

Two full example stories are provided in the supplementary material. Participants rate the moral permissibility (seven-point Likert scale; 1 = completely morally forbidden, 7 = completely morally permissible) of the action. Note that each participant only receives one version of each of the 24 stories. This test exists in four parallel variants which were assigned randomly to our participants and which are described and evaluated in Moran et al (2011).

Since levels of empathy are supposed to relate to utilitarian moral decision-making [35], we examined overall empathy using the Empathy Quotient (EQ) [36] in order to examine the role of empathy during moral judgments in SSD.

2.3 Basic cognition

Basal cognitive abilities were estimated using the Screen for Cognitive Impairment in Psychiatry (SCIP) and the multiple-choice vocabulary test (MWT = Mehrfachwahl‐Wortschatz‐Test).

2.4 NHST analyses

A repeated measures ANOVA including the factors Intention (neutral x negative), Outcome (neutral x negative) and Group (SSD x healthy controls) was conducted. Post-hoc t-tests were performed examining group differences for each condition separately. Additionally, Monte-Carlo-Simulation tests were done to examine the replicability of the t-test results. All (but the permutation test) analyses were implemented in JASP (JASP Team, 2018; [37,38]). Monte-Carlo Simulations were conducted using SPSS’s exact package. Details are described in the Supplementary Material.

2.5 Bayesian analyses

For Bayesian hypothesis testing [39,40] we relied on Bayes Factors (BF). BF reflects the change from prior to posterior odds for specific hypotheses and models given the data. In other words, the BF is the probability of obtaining the data under the alternative hypothesis relative to the probability of obtaining the data under the null hypothesis. In this way, the BF reflects the strength of the evidence for one hypothesis/model compared to another and can also be used to quantify the evidence for the null hypothesis compared to the alternative in light of the data. For example, in Bayesian ANOVAs BFs can reflect the strength of evidence for inclusion compared to the exclusion of different factors and effects from the model [41].

3. Results

Mean permissibility ratings are illustrated in Fig 1. Demographic data, medication and cognitive measures are listed in Table 1. Descriptives and results of the ANOVA and t-tests are listed in Table 2.

thumbnail
Fig 1. Tukey Box-plots depict permissibility ratings on a 7-point Likert scale.

Controls (HC) are depicted in grey, patients with SSD in white. Bold horizontal lines indicate the group median, bold crosses show the group mean. End of whiskers indicate the first and third quartile.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.g001

Pearson Correlations indicate that symptom severity (PANSS) and medication (Chlorpromazine equivalent) were not related to task performance (rs < .38, ps > .09). Illness duration was moderately related to permissibility ratings in Intended Harm scenarios (r = .41, p = .052).

3.1 NHST analyses

3.1.1 Moral judgment task.

Negative Intentions and negative Outcomes were rated as significantly less permissible compared to neutral intentions and neutral outcomes, respectively (Fs(1,53) > 94, ps < .001). These main effects for Intention and Outcome were qualified by an Outcome-by-Intention interaction (F(1,53) = 24.14, p < .001) since accidental harms were rated as more permissible than intended harms. No main effect of Group (F(1,53) = .03, p = .855) and no interaction with the factor Group were observed (Fs(1,53) < .08, ps > .37). Post-hoc t-tests reveal no significant differences between patients and controls in neither condition (Table 1). The findings of the post hoc t-test are supported by our permutation tests, which do not reveal significant group differences in any condition, and which are listed in detail in S1 File. Accordingly, the data do not show evidence for group differences in moral permissibility ratings between healthy controls and SSD patients.

3.1.2 Additional questionnaires.

Patients with SSD showed significantly decreased performance on the EQ compared to healthy controls ((t = 2.6, p = .012). Furthermore, patients scored significantly lower on the SCIP (t = 4.17, p < .001) but showed normal performance on the MWT (t = 1.34, p = .185).

3.2 Bayesian analyses

Although our analyses demonstrate a lack of group differences between healthy and SSD participants, this type of analysis does not allow us to examine the extent to which the null hypothesis outperforms the alternative hypothesis (as would be suggested by non-significant group effects). The Bayesian analyses provided in this section offer a promising approach to quantify the support for the null hypothesis [40,4245].

3.2.1 Moral judgment task.

A Bayesian Repeated Measures ANOVA with default prior scales including the factors Intention (neutral x negative), Outcome (neutral x negative) and Group (SSD x healthy controls) was conducted (Table 3). The model that received the most support compared to the null model is the two main effects and interaction model Intention + Outcome + Intention*Outcome (BF10 = 2858e+74). Adding the factor Group would decrease the model support by a factor of 4.5 (2858e74/6327e73), which therefore speaks in favour of the two main effects and interaction model. Overall, there is merely anecdotal support for any model including the factor Group or any interaction with Group (BFs10 < .21). Since our primary analysis features several candidate models, we examined the change from prior to posterior model plausibility. As evident from Table 4, averaged across all models, our data strongly support the inclusion of the factors Intention (BFincl = 8465e13), Outcome (BFincl = 8465e13) and Intention*Outcome (BFincl = 59.44). Again, weak support is found for models including the factor Group (BFincl < .11).

thumbnail
Table 3. Bayesian repeated measures ANOVA: Model comparison.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.t003

thumbnail
Table 4. Bayesian repeated measures ANOVA: Analysis of effects.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.t004

3.2.2 Additional questionnaires.

Bayesian Independent Samples t-tests reveal very strong evidence for the assumption that there is a difference in performance on the SCIP between controls and patients (BF10 = 137.03). Moderate evidence for a group difference is found for the EQ (BF10 = 6.54), and no (or anecdotal at best) support is evident for differences in the MWT (BF10 = 0.61). Order-restricted (controls > patients; comparable to one-sided t-testing in NHST) t-tests reveal similar findings, elevating the evidence for a group difference in the EQ to moderate-strong (BFs10: SCIP = 273.99; EQ = 13; MWT = 1.09). In sum, Bayes analyses suggest a decreased performance of patients on the SCIP and, slightly less pronounced, on the EQ. No substantial group differences are evident for the MWT.

4. Discussion

We examined the performance of patients with Schizophrenia Spectrum Disorder (SSD) on a recent moral judgment task [29] which requires the understanding of others’ intentions in order to adequately rate the moral permissibility of actions. We argued in the Introduction that sophisticated moral judgments about other people’s behavior requires the integration of their beliefs and intentions. Patients with SSD often show impairments in belief understanding, why we assumed that this task (compared to previous moral judgment tasks which did not require belief integration) might indicate moral judgment abnormalities more robustly. Response patterns of the healthy control participants replicate previous findings showing that scenarios with neutral intentions and neutral outcomes are judged as more morally permissible than negative outcomes and intentions. Accidental harms were rated more permissible than intended but failed harms, which is again in line with previous findings on that task [29].

Interestingly, neither the standard ANOVA nor the Bayesian approach show support for altered moral judgments in patients with SSD but reveal evidence for healthy-like considerations of intentions and outcome despite observable impairments in general cognition and empathy. In the following, we discuss several reasons which might account for our findings and discuss their explanatory potential given the data and the current literature.

Probably the most important consideration for a null effect is the statistical power of the study. Whereas posterior power calculations are under heavy critique [4648], an a priori power calculation might have been useful to estimate the necessary number of participants to detect a true effect. However, a priori power calculations require an estimation of the population effect size. Critically, this specific task is not implemented in SSD yet (and the required Cohens’ f does not generalize across task designs) and estimating the effect size in SSD based on the effect size for another psychiatric population (the original study is based on autistic patients) appears arbitrary and is beside the point. Furthermore, the effects of interest would have been reflected in interactions and estimating an ANOVA design in standard power tools can be tricky (but see [49]): Assuming that SSD patients have difficulties merging the actor’s intention with the situation outcome, they should have rated accidental harms as less permissible (or attempted harms as more permissible) compared to healthy controls, which both would have been reflected in a group-by-intention interaction. To nonetheless map the evidential strength of our results given the number of participants, we ran Bayes sequential robustness analyses which estimate the number of participants after which the Bayes factors become constant due to a convergence of updated prior distributions to posterior distributions (for details see [41]. In other words, this analysis shows upon which number of participants the group differences most likely will remain constant. As evident from S1S4 Figs in the supplementary material, we reach a constant level of anecdotal (Intentional Harm) and moderate (Attempted Harm, Neutral Acts, Accidental Harm) support for the null hypothesis in all four conditions after 40–50 participants in total. Since the overall number of datasets is 55, we do not assume that there would have been relevant shifts in the overall pattern of results if more datasets were acquired.

Another reason for the absence of group differences might be that all patients have a comparably mild form of SSD or that our sample is biased towards patients with a relatively short illness duration. A quick descriptive approach of the medical history of our patients shows that about 35% of our patients have an illness duration of more than 4 years, 17% between two and three years and 46% are diagnosed for one year. Although most of our patients report personal changes ~2 years before their first hospitalization, this distribution suggests a high number of first-episode patients in our sample. Illness severity (as measured with the PANNS) shows a mean percentile rank of 29 for positive symptoms and a mean rank of 25 for negative symptoms. Although our sample scores at the putatively lower range of psychiatric symptoms, they are in the average range of the norm (schizophrenic) sample. A similar picture emerges for SPQ and PNS-Q values, where our sample scores at the lower range of comparable psychiatric samples ([50,51]. Assuming that there exists a true alteration in moral judgments in SSD, the current data might be explained by either a task insensitivity to detect subtle changes or that alterations in moral judgment become evident only later in the course of illness or merely occur in more severe forms of SSD. However, neither symptom severity (rs(26) < .127, ps > .521) nor illness duration (rs(26) < .336, ps > .100) were related to task performance in our sample and currently available studies on moral judgment in SSD suggest a rather subtle dysfunction even in more severe forms of SSD [21,52].

As shortly mentioned above, an alternative explanation might be that the task is not suitable to detect small alterations in moral judgments in SSD as compared to other clinical samples. In the original study[29], patients with ASD neglect the neutral intention of the actor in the accidental harm condition and rate the action as less morally acceptable compared to healthy controls. Although this might suggest an overreliance on action outcomes, it remains unclear why such alterations are not evident in other conditions as well (e.g., when autistic patients weigh the action-outcome stronger than the intention, they should rate attempted but not achieved harms as more morally acceptable, which they do not. For a detailed discussion on that topic see [53]). Accordingly, it might be that such tasks are suitable to detect alterations in ASD [29,54] and psychopathy [55] but are not sensitive enough to reveal the degree of alterations or the sub-aspect of ToM that is altered in SSD. Although ASD and SSD patients often reveal comparable behavioral ToM alterations[56], they are not necessarily caused by the same underlying malfunctioning mechanisms [57,58]. It is up to future replication studies to examine the sensitivity of this measure and to provide transdiagnostic analyses that will allow direct comparisons between clinical samples.

Although there is inconsistent evidence for a relation between antipsychotic medication and ToM performance in SSD [59,60], there remains the argument that behavioral alterations in SSD might be concealed by alleviating the effects of medication. To rule out an effect of antipsychotic medication on patients’ moral judgments, we correlated medication (standardized Chlorpromazine equivalent in mg/day; [61]) to task performance showing that moral judgments did not vary with the degree of antipsychotic medication.

At last, the current findings might support the notion that moral judgments are not (or minimally) impaired in SSD. This is well in line with several recent studies that reveal minimal support for a significant impairment in moral judgment in SSD [14,17], especially when judging moral dilemmas from the self-perspective. Another counter for the conception of schizophrenic patients as morally insensitive is provided by neuroeconomic studies revealing that patients react in similar manners to unfair behavior towards others [18,19]. Nonetheless, the findings that intention-based moral judgments are presumably preserved in SSD is puzzling, given the countless evidence for impaired ToM processes on the behavioral [6,7,62] and neural [7] level and the altered empathy processes evident in our sample. Although empathy and ToM are both crucial for interactions and share some overlapping cortical areas, both processes also relate to distinct regions [63]. Furthermore, a recent meta-analysis showed that moral judgments are closer linked to ToM-related cortical areas than empathy-related areas which seemingly disapproves of a significant role of affect sharing during moral decision making [64]. Accordingly, our patient sample might suffer from decreased empathy while showing healthy-like moral judgments. Furthermore, patients with SSD can reveal altered cortical activation during moral decision making in ToM-related networks but simultaneously show no signs for altered behavioral moral judgments [17], which might account for the robust deficits identified in ToM studies [7,62] but preserved moral judgment in the current sample.

The current study supports previous evidence that SSD is not characterized by pronounced impairments in moral judgments, even when other people’s intentions must be considered. This is well in line with recent meta-analyses showing that SSD patients do not engage in more immoral and violent behavior than the average person [65,66].

4.1 Limitations and outlook

Whereas neuroimaging and behavioral examinations of moral reasoning in psychiatric samples such as schizophrenia are undoubtedly important, they bear several pitfalls. First (and as shortly mentioned in the introduction), findings on moral reasoning in schizophrenic patients are inconsistent and not all findings support the notion of impaired moral decision making or ToM in patients [18,19,67]. Second, although current research allows a better understanding of impaired behavioral outcomes and neuroimaging studies provide interesting insight into the cortical regions involved, most studies focus on certain sub-aspects of moral reasoning which are rarely put into a more exhaustive framework or model [23] and future studies must show how these sub-aspects integrate into a full model of morality in psychiatry.

Furthermore, we are yet far from an exhaustive understanding of how altered activation, connectivity or brain structure in psychiatric patients is related to behavioral outcome [68,69]. Whilst this is an ongoing issue not only in psychiatric research, the examination of morality bears a high responsibility, since it strongly influences the perception of how capable psychiatric patients are to understand their own actions. This in turn has an immediate influence on whether a psychiatric patient can be made responsible for his or her own actions which is an inevitable question when it comes to legal jurisdictions [68]. Taken together, there is a strong need for a more integrative account of morality in SSD, not only for research but also for a more sophisticated treatment of psychiatric patients in legal jurisdiction.

Supporting information

S1 Fig. Sequential analysis Accidental Harm.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.s001

(TIF)

S2 Fig. Sequential analysis Attempted Harm.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.s002

(TIF)

S3 Fig. Sequential analysis Intentional Harm.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.s003

(TIF)

S4 Fig. Sequential analysis Neutral Acts.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0251180.s004

(TIF)

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Eva Reiter and Chelsea Hunt for their help with data acquisition and proofreading, respectively.

References

  1. 1. Green MF, Horan WP. Social Cognition in Schizophrenia. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2010;19: 243–248. pmid:20185539
  2. 2. Green MF, Leitman DI. Social cognition in schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2008;34: 670–672. pmid:18495642
  3. 3. Mehl S, Rief W, Mink K, Lüllmann E, Lincoln TM. Social performance is more closely associated with theory of mind and autobiographical memory than with psychopathological symptoms in clinically stable patients with schizophrenia-spectrum disorders. Psychiatry Res. 2010;178: 276–283. pmid:20494454
  4. 4. Fett A-KJ, Viechtbauer W, Dominguez M-G, Penn DL, van Os J, Krabbendam L. The relationship between neurocognition and social cognition with functional outcomes in schizophrenia: a meta-analysis. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2011;35: 573–588. pmid:20620163
  5. 5. Frith C, Frith U. Theory of mind. Curr Biol. 2005;15: R644–6. pmid:16139190
  6. 6. Sprong M, Schothorst P, Vos E, Hox J, van Engeland H. Theory of mind in schizophrenia: meta-analysis. Br J Psychiatry. 2007;191: 5–13. pmid:17602119
  7. 7. Kronbichler L, Tschernegg M, Martin AI, Schurz M, Kronbichler M. Abnormal Brain Activation During Theory of Mind Tasks in Schizophrenia: A Meta-Analysis. Schizophr Bull. 2017;43: 1240–1250. pmid:28575475
  8. 8. Guglielmo S. Moral judgment as information processing: an integrative review. Front Psychol. 2015;6: 1637. pmid:26579022
  9. 9. Christensen JF, Gomila A. Moral dilemmas in cognitive neuroscience of moral decision-making: a principled review. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2012;36: 1249–1264. pmid:22353427
  10. 10. Eres R, Louis WR, Molenberghs P. Common and distinct neural networks involved in fMRI studies investigating morality: an ALE meta-analysis. Soc Neurosci. 2018;13: 384–398. pmid:28724332
  11. 11. Sevinc G, Spreng RN. Contextual and perceptual brain processes underlying moral cognition: a quantitative meta-analysis of moral reasoning and moral emotions. PLoS One. 2014;9: e87427. pmid:24503959
  12. 12. Andreasen NC, Calarge CA, O’Leary DS. Theory of mind and schizophrenia: a positron emission tomography study of medication-free patients. Schizophr Bull. 2008;34: 708–719. pmid:18559406
  13. 13. Koelkebeck K, Kuegler L, Kohl W, Engell A, Lencer R. Social cognition in schizophrenia: The role of mentalizing in moral dilemma decision-making. Compr Psychiatry. 2018;87: 171–178. pmid:30415199
  14. 14. McGuire J, Brüne M, Langdon R. Outcome-focused judgements of moral dilemmas in schizophrenia. Conscious Cogn. 2017;52: 21–31. pmid:28454059
  15. 15. Carlson RW, Crockett MJ. The lateral prefrontal cortex and moral goal pursuit. Curr Opin Psychol. 2018;24: 77–82. pmid:30342428
  16. 16. Koenigs M, Young L, Adolphs R, Tranel D, Cushman F, Hauser M, et al. Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgements. Nature. 2007;446: 908–911. pmid:17377536
  17. 17. de Achával D, Villarreal MF, Salles A, Bertomeu MJ, Costanzo EY, Goldschmidt M, et al. Activation of brain areas concerned with social cognition during moral decisions is abnormal in schizophrenia patients and unaffected siblings. J Psychiatr Res. 2013;47: 774–782. pmid:23403281
  18. 18. Wischniewski J, Brüne M. Moral reasoning in schizophrenia: an explorative study into economic decision making. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. 2011;16: 348–363. pmid:21271414
  19. 19. Agay N, Kron S, Carmel Z, Mendlovic S, Levkovitz Y. Ultimatum bargaining behavior of people affected by schizophrenia. Psychiatry Res. 2008;157: 39–46. pmid:17916386
  20. 20. Torniainen M, Suvisaari J, Partonen T, Castaneda AE, Kuha A, Suokas J, et al. Cognitive impairments in schizophrenia and schizoaffective disorder: relationship with clinical characteristics. J Nerv Ment Dis. 2012;200: 316–322. pmid:22456585
  21. 21. McGuire J, Langdon R, Brüne M. Moral cognition in schizophrenia. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. 2014;19: 495–508. pmid:24963651
  22. 22. McGuire J, Barbanel L, Brüne M, Langdon R. Re-examining Kohlberg’s conception of morality in schizophrenia. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. 2015;20: 377–381. pmid:26084621
  23. 23. Yu H, Siegel JZ, Crockett MJ. Modeling Morality in 3-D: Decision-Making, Judgment, and Inference. Top Cogn Sci. 2019;11: 409–432. pmid:31042018
  24. 24. Benson AL. Morality of schizophrenic adolescents. J Abnorm Psychol. 1980;89: 674–677. pmid:7410728
  25. 25. Johnson DL. The moral judgment of schizophrenics. J Nerv Ment Dis. 1960;130: 278–285. pmid:14407434
  26. 26. Giner-Sorolla R, Chapman HA. Corrigendum: Beyond Purity: Moral Disgust Toward Bad Character. Psychol Sci. 2017;28: 1871. pmid:29043915
  27. 27. Giner-Sorolla R, Kupfer T, Sabo J. Chapter Five—What Makes Moral Disgust Special? An Integrative Functional Review. In: Olson JM, editor. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. Academic Press; 2018. pp. 223–289.
  28. 28. Kliemann D, Young L, Scholz J, Saxe R. The influence of prior record on moral judgment. Neuropsychologia. 2008;46: 2949–2957. pmid:18606175
  29. 29. Moran JM, Young LL, Saxe R, Lee SM, O’Young D, Mavros PL, et al. Impaired theory of mind for moral judgment in high-functioning autism. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2011;108: 2688–2692. pmid:21282628
  30. 30. Diaconescu AO, Mathys C, Weber LAE, Daunizeau J, Kasper L, Lomakina EI, et al. Inferring on the intentions of others by hierarchical Bayesian learning. PLoS Comput Biol. 2014;10: e1003810. pmid:25187943
  31. 31. Baez S, Couto B, Torralva T, Sposato LA, Huepe D, Montañes P, et al. Comparing moral judgments of patients with frontotemporal dementia and frontal stroke. JAMA Neurol. 2014;71: 1172–1176. pmid:25047907
  32. 32. Sheehan DV, Lecrubier Y, Sheehan KH, Amorim P, Janavs J, Weiller E, et al. The Mini-International Neuropsychiatric Interview (M.I.N.I): The development and validation of a structured diagnostic psychiatric interview for DSM-IV and ICD-10. J Clin Psychiatry. 1998;59: 22–33. pmid:9881538
  33. 33. Janca A, Hiller W. ICD-10 checklists—A tool for clinicians’ use of the ICD-10 classification of mental and behavioral disorders. Compr Psychiatry. 1996;37: 180–187. pmid:8732585
  34. 34. Kay SR, Opler LA, Lindenmayer JP. The Positive and Negative Syndrome Scale (PANSS): rationale and standardisation. Br J Psychiatry Suppl. 1989; 59–67. pmid:2619982
  35. 35. Gleichgerrcht E, Young L. Low levels of empathic concern predict utilitarian moral judgment. PLoS One. 2013;8: e60418. pmid:23593213
  36. 36. Baron-Cohen S, Wheelwright S. The empathy quotient: an investigation of adults with Asperger syndrome or high functioning autism, and normal sex differences. J Autism Dev Disord. 2004;34: 163–175. pmid:15162935
  37. 37. Morey RD, Rouder JN, Jamil T. BayesFactor: Computation of Bayes Factors for common designs. R package version 0.9. 12–4.2. Computer software] Retrieved from https://CRANR-projectorg/package=BayesFactor. 2018.
  38. 38. Rouder JN, Morey RD, Speckman PL, Province JM. Default Bayes factors for ANOVA designs. J Math Psychol. 2012;56: 356–374.
  39. 39. Wagenmakers E-J, Marsman M, Jamil T, Ly A, Verhagen J, Love J, et al. Bayesian inference for psychology. Part I: Theoretical advantages and practical ramifications. Psychon Bull Rev. 2018;25: 35–57. pmid:28779455
  40. 40. Wagenmakers E-J. A practical solution to the pervasive problems of values. Psychon Bull Rev. 2007;14: 779–804. pmid:18087943
  41. 41. Wagenmakers E-J, Love J, Marsman M, Jamil T, Ly A, Verhagen J, et al. Bayesian inference for psychology. Part II: Example applications with JASP. Psychon Bull Rev. 2018;25: 58–76. pmid:28685272
  42. 42. Dienes Z. Bayesian Versus Orthodox Statistics: Which Side Are You On? Perspect Psychol Sci. 2011;6: 274–290. pmid:26168518
  43. 43. Dienes Z. Using Bayes to get the most out of non-significant results. Front Psychol. 2014;5: 781. pmid:25120503
  44. 44. Morey RD, Rouder JN. Bayes factor approaches for testing interval null hypotheses. Psychol Methods. 2011;16: 406–419. pmid:21787084
  45. 45. Rouder JN, Speckman PL, Sun D, Morey RD, Iverson G. Bayesian t tests for accepting and rejecting the null hypothesis. Psychon Bull Rev. 2009;16: 225–237. pmid:19293088
  46. 46. Sun S, Pan W, Wang LL. Rethinking Observed Power. Methodology. 2011;7: 81–87.
  47. 47. Zhang Y, Hedo R, Rivera A, Rull R, Richardson S, Tu XM. Post hoc power analysis: is it an informative and meaningful analysis? Gen Psychiatr. 2019;32: e100069. pmid:31552383
  48. 48. Levine M, Ensom MH. Post hoc power analysis: an idea whose time has passed? Pharmacotherapy. 2001;21: 405–409. pmid:11310512
  49. 49. Lakens D, Caldwell AR. Simulation-Based Power-Analysis for Factorial ANOVA Designs. 2019. Available: https://psyarxiv.com/baxsf/download?format=pdf.
  50. 50. Rossi A, Daneluzzo E. Schizotypal dimensions in normals and schizophrenic patients: a comparison with other clinical samples. Schizophr Res. 2002;54: 67–75. pmid:11853980
  51. 51. Iancu I, Poreh A, Lehman B, Shamir E, Kotler M. The Positive and Negative Symptoms Questionnaire: a self-report scale in schizophrenia. Compr Psychiatry. 2005;46: 61–66. pmid:15714197
  52. 52. McGuire J, Brüne M, Langdon R. Judgment of moral and social transgression in schizophrenia. Compr Psychiatry. 2017;76: 160–168. pmid:28531645
  53. 53. Cushman F, Sheketoff R, Wharton S, Carey S. The development of intent-based moral judgment. Cognition. 2013;127: 6–21. pmid:23318350
  54. 54. Fadda R, Parisi M, Ferretti L, Saba G, Foscoliano M, Salvago A, et al. Exploring the Role of Theory of Mind in Moral Judgment: The Case of Children with Autism Spectrum Disorder. Front Psychol. 2016;7: 523. pmid:27148131
  55. 55. Young L, Koenigs M, Kruepke M, Newman JP. Psychopathy increases perceived moral permissibility of accidents. J Abnorm Psychol. 2012;121: 659–667. pmid:22390288
  56. 56. Stanghellini G, Ballerini M. What is it like to be a person with Schizophrenia in the social world? A first-person perspective study on Schizophrenic Dissociality—part 2: methodological issues and empirical findings. Psychopathology. 2011;44: 183–192. pmid:21412032
  57. 57. Dodell-Feder D, Germine LT. Common social cognitive impairments do not mean common causes: A commentary on Cotter et al. (2018). Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2018;92: 150–151. pmid:29885424
  58. 58. Sugranyes G, Kyriakopoulos M, Corrigall R, Taylor E, Frangou S. Autism spectrum disorders and schizophrenia: meta-analysis of the neural correlates of social cognition. PLoS One. 2011;6: e25322. pmid:21998649
  59. 59. Kucharska-Pietura K, Mortimer A. Can antipsychotics improve social cognition in patients with schizophrenia? CNS Drugs. 2013;27: 335–343. pmid:23533009
  60. 60. Savina I, Beninger RJ. Schizophrenic patients treated with clozapine or olanzapine perform better on theory of mind tasks than those treated with risperidone or typical antipsychotic medications. Schizophr Res. 2007;94: 128–138. pmid:17560766
  61. 61. Gardner DM, Murphy AL, O’Donnell H, Centorrino F, Baldessarini RJ. International consensus study of antipsychotic dosing. Am J Psychiatry. 2010;167: 686–693. pmid:20360319
  62. 62. Bora E, Yucel M, Pantelis C. Theory of mind impairment in schizophrenia: meta-analysis. Schizophr Res. 2009;109: 1–9. pmid:19195844
  63. 63. Vucurovic K, Caillies S, Kaladjian A. Neural correlates of theory of mind and empathy in schizophrenia: An activation likelihood estimation meta-analysis. J Psychiatr Res. 2020;120: 163–174. pmid:31689587
  64. 64. Bzdok D, Schilbach L, Vogeley K, Schneider K, Laird AR, Langner R, et al. Parsing the neural correlates of moral cognition: ALE meta-analysis on morality, theory of mind, and empathy. Brain Struct Funct. 2012;217: 783–796. pmid:22270812
  65. 65. Nielssen O, Large M. Rates of homicide during the first episode of psychosis and after treatment: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Schizophr Bull. 2010;36: 702–712. pmid:18990713
  66. 66. Fazel S, Gulati G, Linsell L, Geddes JR, Grann M. Schizophrenia and violence: systematic review and meta-analysis. PLoS Med. 2009;6: e1000120. pmid:19668362
  67. 67. McCabe R, Leudar I, Antaki C. Do people with schizophrenia display theory of mind deficits in clinical interactions? Psychol Med. 2004;34: 401–412. pmid:15259825
  68. 68. Bluhm R, Raczek G, Broome M, Wall MB. Ethical Issues in Brain Imaging in Psychiatry. In: Sadler JZ, Fulford KWM, van Staden W (C W)., editors. The Oxford Handbook of Psychiatric Ethics. Oxford University Press; 2015.
  69. 69. Eastman N, Campbell C. Neuroscience and legal determination of criminal responsibility. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2006;7: 311–318. pmid:16552416