Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-06-03T18:05:58.398Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Between Mathematics and Physics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Michael D. Resnik*
Affiliation:
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Extract

The distinction between mathematical and physical objects has probably played a greater role shaping the philosophy of mathematics than the distinction between observable and theoretical entities has had in defining the philosophy of science. All the major movements in the philosophy of mathematics may be seen as attempts to free mathematics of an abstract ontology or to come to terms with it. The reasons are epistemic. Most philosophers of mathematics believe that the abstractaess of mathematical objects introduces special difficulties in accounting for our ability to know them, to refer to them and even to entertain beliefs about them. These difficulties—supposedly absent even in the case of the most theoretical physical objects—make mathematical objects especially problematic and philosophically unattractive.

Few have questioned this epistemic thesis or the ontic distinction it presupposes. LaVerne Shelton (1980) challenged the abstract-concrete distinction some years ago in an unpublished APA address.

Type
Part IX. Mathematical and Physical Objects
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1991

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank Susan Hale and Geoffrey Sayre-McCord for their helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References

Dood, J.E. (1984), The Ideas of Particle Physics: An Introduction for Scientists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1980), Science Without Numbers: A Defense of Nominalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hale, S.C. (1988a), Against the Abstract-Concrete Distinction. Unpubished Ph.D. Dissertation, University of North Carolina.Google Scholar
Hale, S.C. (1988b), “Spacetime and the Abstract/Concrete Distinction”, Philosophical Studies 53:85102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellman, G. (1989), Mathematics Without Numbers. Oxford: Clarendon Press,Google Scholar
Horgan, T. (1987), “Science Nominalized Properly”, Philosophy of Science 54:281-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, M.D. (1985), “How Nominalist is Hartry Field’s Nominalism?”, Philosophical Studies 47:163181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, M.D. (1981), “Mathematics as a Science of Patterns: Ontology and Reference”, Nous 15:529-50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Resnik, M.D. (1988), “Mathematics from the Structural Point of View”, Revue Internationale de Philosophie 42:400-24.Google Scholar
Resnik, M.D. (1989), “Computation and Mathematical Empiricism”, Philosophical Topics 17:129-44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelton, L. (1980), “The Abstract and the Concrete: How Much Difference Does This Distinction Make?” Unpublished paper delivered at the American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division Meetings.Google Scholar
Shimony, A. (1989), “Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics” in The New Physics, Davies, Paul (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Teller, P. (1990), “Prolegomenon to a Proper Interpretation of Quantum Field Theory”, Philosophy of Science 57:594618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Will, C. (1989), “The Renaissance of General Relativity” in The New Physics, Davies, Paul (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar