Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-30T11:56:35.062Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Defense of the Autonomy of Ethics: Why Value Is Not Like Water

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Eric H. Gampel*
Affiliation:
California State University - Chico Chico, CA 95929-0730, USA

Extract

There has recently been a revival of interest in ‘naturalizing’ ethics. A naturalization seeks to vindicate ethical realism — the idea that ethical judgments can be true reflections of a moral reality — without violating the naturalist constraint that science sets the limits of ontology. The recent revival has been prompted by examples of successful scientific reduction (e.g. temperature, water), and by the emergence of new, nonreductive naturalist strategies (e.g. for biological and mental properties). In this paper, I argue against such naturalist approaches to ethics. My argument builds on the traditional one offered by G.E. Moore, namely that a naturalization would fail to respect an existing difference between the meanings of moral and naturalistic terms. I defend this line of argument against the common claim that it cannot block ‘synthetic’ property identities, ones grounded not in meaning equivalences but in empirical discoveries (as in the cases of temperature and water). I then go on to show that the Moorean argument can make trouble even for recent revisionist and nonreductive naturalist approaches.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 I would like to thank Steve Darwall, Ted Hinchman, Brooke Moore, Peter Railton, Stephen Sullivan, Mark Timmons, and Steve Yablo for helpful comments on earlier drafts. I am especially indebted to Allan Gibbard and Andy Hyrcyna, for originally inspiring me to think about the disanalogies between ethics and science which led me to develop the arguments of this paper.

2 I follow the literature in restricting ‘naturalization’ to cognitive, realist accounts. This leaves out expressivism and emotivism, though they are usually also grounded in a naturalist world view.

3 See Nagel, Ernest The Structure of Science (London: Harcourt, Brace & World 1961)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 See Moore, G. E. Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1903) 15ffGoogle Scholar.

5 Moore advanced different versions of the argument, for instance sometimes asking of the natural property (rather than the thing) whether it was good. The version on which I focus above reflects Moore's main line of thought.

6 Velleman, DavidBrandt's Definition of “Good”,Philosophical Review 97 (1988) 359CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a similar recent criticism of Brandt, see Gibbard, Allan Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1990) 1822Google Scholar. Gibbard puts the point by saying Brandt's definitions lose the ‘recommending force’ of the original terms.

7 Copp, DavidMoral Realism: Facts and Norms,Ethics 101 (1991), 623CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Sayre-McCord, GeoffreyMoral Theory and Explanatory Impotence,’ in French, Peter Uehling, Theodore and Wettstein, Howard eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press 1988) 433-57Google Scholar.

8 For a recent discussion of the import of the open question argument, see Darwall, Stephen Gibbard, Allan and Railton, PeterToward Fin de Siècle Ethics: Some Trends,Philosophical Review 101 (1992) 115-25CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially 115-25 and 177-80.

9 Versions of this objection are pressed by Harman, Gilbert in The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press 1977)Google Scholar, and by Putnam, Hilary in Reason, Truth, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1981), 207CrossRefGoogle Scholar. There are other long-standing objections to the Moorean argument; for a recent attempt to reply to some of them, see Ball, StephenLinguistic Intuitions and Varieties of Ethical Naturalism,Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (1991) 138CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Kripke, Saul Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press 1980) 118119Google Scholar

11 For a recent statement of naturalism, see Papineau, David Philosophical Naturalism (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell 1993)Google Scholar. See also Brink, David Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press 1989) 182-97CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Brink defends his version of ethical naturalism by appealing to the role of ethical properties in causal explanations.

12 Stephen Ball has also appealed to a difference between natural and ethical kinds in order to resurrect Moore's anti-naturalist argument (Ball, 8-15). The difference he discusses concerns whether it is possible to explain a divergence between ordinary and theoretical conceptions of the kinds. For natural kinds, the explanation is that we ordinarily lack microscopic vision, while ‘there is no obvious analogy to the “molecular theory” in ethics’ (Ball, 13). But it seems to me that a naturalist could easily offer an analogy. For most utilitarians distinguish between two levels of moral thinking: the commonsense level of rules and particular intuitions, and the theoretical level provided by utilitarianism. Add a reductive definition of utility, and the difference between the approaches of commonsense and theory is explained. To block such a proposal requires showing the reduction would have to be backed by a referential intention that is not to be found, as I am arguing here.

13 Sklar, Lawrence Philosophy and Spacetime Physics (Berkeley: University of California Press 1985) 310-15Google Scholar

14 Harman, 20. See also Brandt, Richard A Theory of the Good and the Right (New York: Oxford University Press 1979) 1016Google Scholar, and Railton, PeterNaturalism and Prescriptivity,Social Philosophy and Policy (1989) 151-74CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 See Gibbard, Wise Choices; Stevenson, C.L. Facts and Values (New Haven: Yale University Press 1963)Google Scholar; and Velleman, ‘Brandt's Definition of “Good”.’

16 Copp, ‘Moral Realism,’ and Sayre-McCord, ‘Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence’

17 For a discussion of nonreductivism, see Kincaid, HaroldSupervenience and Explanation,Synthese 77 (1988) 251-81CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 There are definitional moves to be made here, such as that the torturer must torture primarily in order to feel pleasure (but what if the pleasure is moral satisfaction?). My aim is simply to show one can grant causal features are relevant to moral judgment, without thereby endorsing a reduction.

19 Sturgeon, NicholasHarman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts,The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24 Supp. (1986) 72-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 See Brink, 132, and Boyd, RichardHow to Be a Moral Realist,’ in McCord, Geoffrey Sayre ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press 1989) 181228, esp. 201Google Scholar.

21 Boyd and Brink may only be taking the causal/explanatory role of consequentialist properties to be one piece of evidence in favor of consequentialism. Yet it is not clear why causal/explanatory role should count as evidence at all, given the lack of Causal Specification in our referential intentions. Perhaps the thought is that a causal/explanatory role is something we'd like all properties to have, even if preexisting referential intentions do not incorporate that goal. But to take causal/explanatory role as a piece of evidence, potentially contrary to other evidence, is to pit causal/explanatory criteria against ordinary ethical ones; and as I argued above, in this contest the causal/explanatory criteria lose out to the ordinary ones (as they do in the case of up-down). So the causal/explanatory role of consequentialist properties has very little if any evidential bearing, given the wealth of data from ordinary moral thinking. (I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.)