Skip to main content
Log in

De Deliberatibus Disputandum est: A Response to Jürg Steiner

  • Debate
  • Published:
European Political Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article takes issue with Steiner's polemic against the usage of ‘deliberation’ in rational choice scholarship. I show (i) that the reproach that rationalists do not allow for preference change is mistaken; (ii) that Steiner does not sufficiently distinguish between normative and positive contributions and (iii) that he shields his preferred model against systematic comparisons with strategic models of deliberation. In my view, we need more competing model evaluations rather than misleading attacks against imagined heretics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The title of this article draws on the seminal article by Stigler and Becker (1977). I would like to thank Michael Bechtel and Jürg Steiner for their comments on an earlier version of this article.

  2. The rediscovery of the CJT is largely due to Duncan Black. See Grofman and Feld (1988), Young (1988) and Lada (1992).

  3. Condorcet was also a politician, architect of the ‘Girondain constitution’ and friend of Thomas Jefferson and other US politicians. McLean and Hewitt (1994) discuss Condorcet's (1785 [1972]) contributions to the social choice literature in more detail.

  4. The problem of whether or not individuals change their preferences endogenously or not is closely linked to the consistency criterion that rational choice modellers impose on their actors – the transitivity condition according to which the preference orders of individuals remain the same when they face equivalent decision-making problems. The only exception to this sensible rationality criterion I know of is mirrored in the erratic behaviour of former Bavarian Prime Minister Edmund Stoiber who had in 2005 major difficulties in figuring out whether he should go to Berlin as a ‘super minister’, hang on in Munich as ‘father’ of ‘his’ Land or retire to his provincial residence in Wolfratshausen. To the amusement of the wider audience and to the distress of his supporters, the changing preferences of Stoiber revealed severe forms of intransitivity. It should be added sadly that his more or less enforced retirement has made it much harder to explain the basics of (non)rational behaviour in a German classroom through illustrative examples.

References

  • Achen, C.H. (2002) ‘Toward a new political methodology: microfoundations and ART’, Annual Review of Political Science 5: 423–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Achen, C.H. (2005) ‘Let's put garbage can regressions and garbage can probits where they belong’, Conflict Management and Peace Science 22: 327–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1968) Traktat über die kritische Vernunft, Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D. and Banks, J.S. (1996) ‘Information aggregation, rationality and the Condorcet Jury Theorem’, American Political Science Review 90 (1): 34–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D. and Feddersen, T.J. (2006) ‘Deliberation, preference uncertainty and voting rules’, American Political Science Review 100 (2): 209–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. (1996) Accounting for Taste, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benabou, R. and Tirole, J. (2006) ‘Incentives and prosocial behavior’, American Economic Review 96 (5): 1652–1678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, S. (1993) ‘Condorcet's Jury Theorem, dependency among Jurors’, Social Choice and Welfare 10: 87–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (2007) Does Game Theory Work: The Bargaining Challenge, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M. and Tullock, G. (1962) The Calculus of Consent, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, J. A. N. de Caritat de Condorcet, Marquis de. (1785 [1972]) Essai sur l'Application de l'Analyse à la Probabilité des Decisions Rendues à la Pluralité des Voix, New York: Chelsea Publ. Co. (Original: Paris: Imprimerie Royale).

  • Coughlan, P.J. (2000) ‘In defense of unanimous Jury Verdicts: Mistrails, communication and strategic voting’, American Political Science Review 94: 375–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1992) ‘Arguing and Bargaining in the Federal Convention and the Assemblée Constituante’, in R. Malnes and Arild Underdal (eds.) Rationality and Institutions: Essays in Honour of Knut Midgaard, Oslo: Scandinavian University Press, pp. 13–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T. and Pesendorfer, W. (1998) ‘Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous Jury verdicts’, American Political Science Review 92: 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T. and Pesendorfer, W. (1999) ‘Perspectives – elections, information aggregation, and strategic voting’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 96 (1): 10572–10574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabel, M.J. and Shipan, C.R. (2004) ‘A social choice approach to expert consensus panels’, Journal of Health Economics 23 (3): 543–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (2008) ‘Deliberative lies’, European Political Science 7 (2): 194–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, B. and Feld, S. (1988) ‘Rousseau's general will: a Condorcetian perspective’, American Political Science Review 82 (2): 567–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarnaschelli, S., McKelvey, R.D. and Palfrey, T.R. (2000) ‘An experimental study of Jury decision rules’, American Political Science Review 94 (2): 407–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lada, K.K. (1992) ‘The Condorcet Jury Theorem, free speech, and correlated votes’, American Journal of Political Science 36: 617–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLean, I. and Hewitt, F. (1994) Condorcet: Foundations of Social Choice and Political Theory, Aldershot: Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, A. (2001) ‘Bringing constructivist theories of the EU out of the clouds: have they landed yet?,’ European Union Politics 2 (2): 231–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paroush, J. (1998) ‘Stay away from fair coins: a Condorcet Jury Theorem’, Social Choice and Welfare 15 (1): 15–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, G. (2008) ‘Qui a Peur de John Nash? Le choix rationnel dans les relations internationals et la science politique allemande’, in S. Saurugger and M. Delori (eds.) Pour un débat sur les apports et limites du choix rationnel en science politique, Rennes: Universite? de Rennes Presse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, J. (2008) ‘Concept stretching: the case of deliberation’, European Political Science 7 (2): 186–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, J., Bächtiger, A., Spörndli, M. and Steenbergen, M.R. (2005) Deliberative Politics in Action. Analyzing Parliamentary Discourse, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G.J. and Becker, G.S. (1977) ‘De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum’, American Economic Review 67 (2): 76–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, H.P. (1988) ‘Condorcet's theory of voting’, American Political Science Review 82 (4): 1231–1244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schneider, G. De Deliberatibus Disputandum est: A Response to Jürg Steiner. Eur Polit Sci 7, 199–206 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.eps.2210189

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.eps.2210189

Keywords

Navigation