Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-08T13:18:20.164Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE SOCIAL CONTEXT OF HOBBES'S POLITICAL THOUGHT*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2014

JAMES J. HAMILTON*
Affiliation:
Alexandria, Virginia E-mail: james_hamilton55@yahoo.com

Abstract

The social context of Hobbes's political thought is ripe for reassessment in light of advances in the social history of seventeenth-century England in the past half-century. The evidence does not support C. B. Macpherson's claim that England had a “possessive market society” which became the social model for Hobbes's political theory, nor the case that Hobbes was a bourgeois ideologist. A new examination of his social theory, his social identity, his social prejudices and his understanding of what we today call social class instead produces a picture of an intellectual of the “middle sort” with strong aristocratic, pro-court sentiments. A clearer understanding of his social views would probably have prevented the current controversy over his political sentiments or channeled it in a different direction. The issues make a strong case for more social contextualization at the macro level of analysis in intellectual history.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I wish to thank Duncan Kelly and an anonymous reader for helping make this article possible.

References

1 Macpherson, C. B., The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (Oxford, 1962; repr. 2011), 9106Google Scholar. Also Arendt, Hannah, “Expansion and the Philosophy of Power,” Sewanee Review, 54 (1946), 601–16, 609–10Google Scholar; Strauss, Leo, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes, trans. Sinclair, Elsa M. (Chicago, 1963), 58Google Scholar; Hill, Christopher, Puritanism and Revolution (New York, 1964), 278Google Scholar. Macpherson's thesis still has its enthusiasts. Townsend, Jules, C. B. Macpherson and the Problem of Liberal Democracy (Edinburgh, 2000), 3161CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Macpherson, Political Theory, 162.

3 Berlin, Isaiah, “Hobbes, Locke and Professor Macpherson,” Political Quarterly, 35 (1964), 444–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Letwin, William, “The Economic Foundations of Hobbes’ Politics,” in Cranston, Maurice and Peters, Richard S., eds., Hobbes and Rousseau (Garden City, NY, 1972), 143–64Google Scholar; Tully, James, An Approach to Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1993), 7195CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, Alan, “Hobbes and Individualism,” in Rogers, G. A. J. and Ryan, Alan, eds., Perspectives on Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, 2002), 80–105, 81Google Scholar, 100–4.

4 Thomas, Keith, “The Social Origins of Hobbes’ Political Thought,” in Brown, K. C., ed., Hobbes Studies (Oxford, 1965), 185–236, 186Google Scholar.

5 Ibid., 189, also 191, 202–3.

6 Ibid., 229.

7 Burgess, Glenn, “Contexts for the Writing and Publication of Hobbes's Leviathan,” History of Political Thought, 9 (1990), 675702Google Scholar; Sommerville, Johann P., “Lofty Science and Local Politics,” in Sorell, Tom, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes (Cambridge, 1996), 246–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tuck, Richard, “Introduction,” in Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge, 1996)Google Scholar, xliii–xliv; Malcolm, Noel, “General Introduction,” in Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Malcolm, Noel, 3 vols. (Oxford, 2012), 1: 24–5Google Scholar; Hamilton, James J., “Hobbes the Royalist, Hobbes the Republican,” History of Political Thought, 30 (2009), 411–54Google Scholar.

8 Martel, James, Subverting the Leviathan: Reading Thomas Hobbes as a Radical Democrat (New York, 2007), 1618CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Liberal theorists also sometimes argue that Hobbes had democratic or republican sympathies. For example Herb, Karlfriedrich, “Au-delà de la citoyenneté: Hobbes et le problème de l'autorité,” Rivista di storia della filosofia, 59 (2004), 219–25, 220Google Scholar.

9 Collins, James R., The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, 2005), 116–18Google Scholar.

10 Fukuda, Arihiro, Sovereignty and the Sword (Oxford, 1997), 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 6, 38–40, 60–61; Hoekstra, Kinch, “The de facto Turn in Hobbes's Political Philosophy,” in Sorell, Tom and Foisneau, Luc, eds., Leviathan after 350 Years (Oxford, 2004)Google Scholar, 33–73, 45, 48; Parkin, Jon, Taming the Leviathan (Cambridge, 2007), 8590CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Skinner, Quentin, Hobbes and Republican Liberty 1640–1700 (Cambridge, 2008), 179Google Scholar.

11 Wrightson, Keith, “Mutualities and Obligations: Changing Social Relationships in Early Modern England,” Proceedings of the British Academy, 139 (2006), 157–94Google Scholar; Walter, John, “The Social Economy of Dearth in Early Modern England,” in Walter and Schofield, eds., Famine, Disease and the Social Order in Early Modern Society (Cambridge, 1991), 75128Google Scholar, 96.

12 French, Henry and Barry, Jonathan, “Introduction,” in French and Barry, eds., Identity and Agency in England, 1500–1800 (Basingstoke, 2004), 137, 21CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Wrightson, “Mutualities,” 168, also 186; Walter, “Social Economy,” 113; Barry, Jonathan, “Bourgeois Collectivism? Urban Association and the Middling Sort,” in Barry, Jonathan and Brooks, Christopher, eds., The Middling Sort of People: Culture, Society and Politics in England, 1550–1800 (Basingstoke, 1994), 95CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Muldrew, Craig, Food, Energy and the Creation of Industriousness (Cambridge, 2011), 84–112, 287CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thomas, Keith, The Ends of Life (Oxford, 2009), 192Google Scholar; Goldie, Mark, “The Unacknowledged Republic: Office-Holding in Early Modern England,” in Harris, Tim, ed., The Politics of the Excluded, c.1500–1850 (Basingstoke, 2001), 159–94Google Scholar.

14 Aubrey, John, Brief Lives, ed. Barber, Richard (Woodbridge, 1982), 148Google Scholar; Hobbes, Thomas, Six Lessons to the Savilian Professors of the Mathematics, in SirMolesworth, William, ed., The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (EW), 11 vols. (London, 1839–45), 7: 181356Google Scholar, 355.

15 Rogow, Arnold A., Thomas Hobbes: Radical in the Service of Reaction (New York, 1986), 20Google Scholar.

16 Oxford Dictionary of National Biography, s.v. “Hobbes, Thomas.”

17 Aubrey, Brief Lives, 148.

18 Ibid., 149–50; Malcolm, Noel, Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford, 2002), 23CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Ibid., 53–79.

20 Levy Peck, Linda, “Hobbes on the Grand Tour: Paris, Venice, or London?Journal of the History of Ideas, 57 (1996), 177–83, 180Google Scholar; Martinich, A. P., Hobbes: A Biography (Cambridge, 1999), 28–9Google Scholar, 43, 58, 60.

21 Hobbes to Clifton, 23 November[/3 December] 1632; Hobbes to Newcastle, 26 January[/5 February 1634], both in The Correspondence of Thomas Hobbes, ed. Noel Malcolm, 2 vols. (Oxford, 1997), 1: 18–19; Martinich, Hobbes, 27–8, 57, 59.

22 Hobbes to Newcastle, 29 July/8 August 1636, in Correspondence, 1: 33. Also Stone, Lawrence, The Crisis of the Aristocracy 1558–1641 (Oxford, 1965), 415Google Scholar, 453; Hobbes, Thomas, Verse Autobiography, in Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Curley, Edwin (Indianapolis, 1994), lxiiiGoogle Scholar.

23 Martinich, Hobbes, 121.

24 Hobbes, Thomas, Behemoth or The Long Parliament, ed. Seaward, Paul (Oxford, 2010), 269Google Scholar.

25 Hobbes to Scudamore, 2/12 April 1641, in Correspondence, 1: 114–15.

26 Thomas Hobbes, Considerations upon the Reputation, Loyalty, Manners, and Religion of Thomas Hobbes, in EW, 4: 409–40, 415.

27 Hobbes to Sorbière, [24 September/]4 October 1646, in Correspondence, 1: 138–9; Malcolm, “General Introduction,” 1: 53.

28 Ibid., 1: 96–100.

29 Nicholas to Hyde, 1/11 January 1651/52, in The Nicholas Papers, ed. George F. Warner (London, 1886), 284.

30 Aubrey, Brief Lives, 154. Also Hobbes, Considerations, 424–5.

31 Aubrey, Brief Lives, 155.

32 Sorbière to Hobbes, [21 June/]1 July 1664, in Correspondence, 2: 619.

33 Schuhmann, Karl, Hobbes: Une chronique (Paris, 1998), 195Google Scholar. Hobbes dedicated Behemoth to Arlington, a sign of Arlington's patronage.

34 Correspondence, 2: 818; Hobbes to Charles II, n.d., in ibid., 2: 774.

35 Schuhmann, Chronique, 210.

36 Rogow, Hobbes, 112; Grassby, Richard, The Business Community of Seventeenth-Century England (Cambridge, 1995), 76CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 261–2; Hill, Puritanism, 181. He was also receiving 12li per annum in interest on a loan, plus room, board and a clothing allowance while living with the Cavendishes. The salary of 50li appears to have been additional to the annual net yield of five holdings on a manor granted to him by William (II) Cavendish in 1628. Malcolm, “General Introduction,” 1: 77 n. 300.

37 Ibid.; Hobbes, Verse Autobiography, lxiii.

38 “Condita hic sunt ossa Thomae Hobbes Malmesburiensis, qui per multos annos servivit Duobus Devoniae comitibus, Patri et Filio. Vir Probus, et Fama Eruditionis Domi Forisque bene cognitus.”

39 Heal, Felicity and Holmes, Clive, The Gentry in England and Wales 1500–1700 (Stanford, 1994), 30Google Scholar.

40 Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan (London, 1651), 29Google Scholar. (All references are to this edition unless otherwise specified.)

41 Ibid., 47.

42 Hobbes, Thomas, The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, ed. Tönnies, Ferdinand (New York, 1969), 30Google Scholar.

43 Hobbes, Thomas, Critique du “De Mundo” de Thomas White [Anti-White], ed. Jacquot, Jean and Jones, Harold Whitmore (Paris, 1973), 415–16Google Scholar.

44 Hobbes, Leviathan, 34.

45 Ibid., 38.

46 Hobbes, Anti-White, 415–18.

47 Hobbes, Elements, 169. Also Hobbes, Leviathan, 86.

48 Hobbes, Thomas, De Cive: The Latin Version, ed. Warrender, Howard (Oxford, 1983), 232Google Scholar.

49 Hobbes, Leviathan, 41, 188–9.

50 Ibid., 44–45. Also Hobbes, Elements, 87–8.

51 Ibid., 35. The value of women was usually derivative of that of men. Women, Hobbes says, are “more accustomed” than men “to measure their power by the power and love of others that protect them” such as fathers and husbands. Ibid., 42–3.

52 Hobbes, Leviathan, 42, also 127; Hobbes, Elements, 35.

53 Alexandra Shepard, “Honesty, Worth and Gender in Early Modern England, 1560–1640,” in French and Barry, Identity and Agency, 87–105, 90–91, 99; Craig Muldrew, “Class and Credit: Social Identity, Wealth and the Life Course in Early Modern England,” in French and Barry, Identity and Agency, 147–77, 149.

54 Hobbes, Elements, 48.

55 Hobbes, Leviathan, 77. Also Hobbes, De Cive, 113.

56 Hobbes, Leviathan, 41. Nobility is honorable not, as most people thought, because one inherits the honor of one's ancestors by blood, but because it reflects their power and “laudable actions.” Ibid., 48; Hobbes, Elements, 35.

57 Stone, Crisis, 54–5, 65; Adamson, John, “The Tudor and Stuart Courts 1509–1714,” in Adamson, ed., The Princely Courts of Europe 1500–1750 (London, 1999), 95117Google Scholar, 109.

58 Hobbes, Leviathan, 46, also 44–6, 184.

59 James, Mervyn, Society, Politics and Culture (Cambridge, 1986), 308415CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

60 Hobbes, Leviathan, 43–4, also 42, 45–6, 92–3.

61 Hobbes, Elements, 180.

62 Hobbes, De Cive, 201.

63 Levy Peck, Linda, Consuming Splendor (Cambridge, 2005), 6Google Scholar. The social role of reputation in Hobbes's thought also entails hierarchy. Thomas, “Social Origins,” 193.

64 Hill, Christopher, Society and Puritanism in Pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1967), 262Google Scholar.

65 Hobbes, Leviathan, 49.

66 Ibid., also 44; Levy Peck, Splendor, 7; Thomas, Ends, 115–16.

67 French, H. R., The Middle Sort of People in Provincial England, 1600–1750 (Oxford, 2007)Google Scholar, 23–4. Also Keith Wrightson, “‘Sorts of People’ in Tudor and Stuart England,” in Barry and Brooks, Middling Sort, 28–51, 28–9, 33–4, 41, 45.

68 Hobbes, Behemoth, 110. Also Hobbes, Thomas, “To the Readers,” in Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, trans. Hobbes, Thomas, ed. Grene, David (Chicago, 1989), xxixxiv, xxiiiGoogle Scholar; Cust, Richard and Hughes, Ann, “Introduction: after Revisionism,” in Cust and Hughes, eds., Conflict in Early Stuart England (London, 1989), 1–46Google Scholar, 19; Heal and Holmes, Gentry, 274; Cust, Richard, “‘Patriots’ and ‘Popular’ Spirits: A Narrative of Conflict in Early Stuart Politics,” in Tyacke, Nicholas, ed., The English Revolution c.1590–1720 (Manchester, 2007), 51Google Scholar.

69 Hobbes, Behemoth, 141. Also Hobbes, Leviathan, 170–1.

70 Walter, “Social Economy,” 91; Muldrew, Craig, “Economic and Urban Development,” in Coward, Barry, ed., A Companion to Stuart Britain (Chichester, 2006), 148–65, 148–9Google Scholar.

71 Hamilton, “Hobbes,” 415–18.

72 Stone, Crisis, 403–49; Adamson, “Courts,” 95–117.

73 Hobbes, Leviathan, 42.

74 Hobbes, Elements, 34.

75 Hobbes, Leviathan, 86.

76 Ibid., 47. Also Stone, Crisis, 401.

77 Hobbes, Leviathan, 189.

78 Hobbes, Elements, 35.

79 Hobbes, Leviathan, 44.

80 Ibid., 41.

81 Hobbes, Elements, 84.

82 Hobbes, Thomas, De Homine (London, 1658), 66Google Scholar; Hobbes, De Cive, 213; Hobbes, Anti-White, 416–17.

83 Hobbes, Leviathan, 66.

84 Ibid., 75.

85 Peck, Linda Levy, “Benefits, Brokers and Beneficiaries: The Culture of Exchange in Seventeenth-Century England,” in Young Kunze, Bonnelyn and Brautigam, Dwight D., eds., Court, Country and Culture (Rochester, NY, 1992), 109–28, 112–13Google Scholar.

86 Hobbes, Leviathan, 166, added emphasis.

87 Ibid., 42.

88 Ibid., 389.

89 Hobbes, Behemoth, 192, original emphasis. Also Richard Cust, “Politics and the Electorate in the 1620s,” in Cust and Hughes, Conflict in Early Stuart England, 134–67, 150.

90 Hobbes, Behemoth, 200. Also Hobbes, Leviathan, 166, 183; Hobbes, De Cive, 200–1.

91 Hobbes, Elements, 35. Also Heal and Holmes, Gentry, 137; Thomas, Ends, 128; Levy Peck, Splendor, 27.

92 Hobbes, Elements, 36.

93 Hobbes, Leviathan, 364. Also Heal and Holmes, Gentry, 338, 369; Thomas, Ends, 149, 152.

94 Hobbes, Elements, 71.

95 Ibid., 44.

96 Hobbes, Leviathan, 41. Also Thomas, Ends, 190–2.

97 Hobbes, Behemoth, 159. Also Hill, Christopher, God's Englishman (New York, 1970), 58–9Google Scholar.

98 Hobbes, Leviathan, 136.

99 Hobbes, Behemoth, 198. He is speaking of members of the Long Parliament.

100 Hobbes, Leviathan, 118; Heal and Holmes, Gentry, 41, 101.

101 Hobbes, Leviathan, 181, also 47.

102 Hobbes, De Cive, 191–2; Hobbes, Anti-White, 418–19; Hobbes, De Homine, 72–3; Hobbes, Behemoth, 276; Grassby, Business, 199.

103 Hobbes, Leviathan, 41. Also Hobbes, De Homine, 63–4.

104 Hobbes, Behemoth, 165, added emphasis. Also Grassby, Business, 31, 34, 38–9, 115, 293–4; Thomas, Ends, 160.

105 Hobbes, Behemoth, 299.

106 Hobbes, Leviathan, 47.

107 “Contemptus divitiarum (non maximarum) Pulchrum.” Hobbes, De Homine, 66.

108 Grassby, Business, 36.

109 Hobbes, Behemoth, 139.

110 Thomas, “Social Origins,” 219.

111 Muldrew, Food, 233, 282–3.

112 French, Middle Sort, 165. Also Hobbes, Behemoth, 276; Macpherson, Political Theory, 66, 94.

113 Hobbes, Leviathan, 44, also 179; Hobbes, Behemoth, 299.

114 Hobbes, Leviathan, 44. Also Muldrew, Food, 29; Muldrew, “Economic and Urban Development,” 154; Muldrew, “Class,” 149.

115 Muldrew, Food, 207, also 26, 36, 205.

116 Laslett, Peter, The World We Have Lost (New York, 1965), 51Google Scholar.

117 Hobbes, Leviathan, 179. Also Hobbes, De Cive, 191; Hobbes, De Homine, 64.

118 Hobbes, Leviathan, 44. Also Thomas, Ends, 164.

119 Hobbes, De Cive, 173. The context is the myth of Prometheus. Also Hobbes, Leviathan, 174.

120 Hobbes, Elements, 13.

121 Hobbes, Behemoth, 195, also 141, 197.

122 Hobbes, Elements, 65. When Hobbes says that “[t]he common sort of men seldome speak Insignificantly,” he is not praising the intelligence of common people, who just think in concrete images, but insulting the intelligence of the scholastics with a social slur. Hobbes, Leviathan, 39.

123 Hobbes, Leviathan, 183.

124 Ibid., 176–9.

125 Cust, “‘Patriots’,” 47–8, also 54–5.

126 Hobbes, Leviathan, 41, also 177–8; Hobbes, Elements, 182–3; Hobbes, De Cive, 200.

127 See chaps. 11, 12 and 13 of De Homine.

128 Heal and Holmes, Gentry, 8.

129 Hobbes, Leviathan, 166, 182; Hobbes, Thomas, A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England, ed. Cromartie, Alan (Oxford, 2005), 48–9Google Scholar.

130 Hobbes, Leviathan, 169–70.

131 Ibid., 168–9.

132 Ibid., 380.

133 Ibid., 42.

134 Hobbes, Behemoth, 146–7.

135 Hobbes, Leviathan, 48, also 49, 154, 185; Hobbes, Behemoth, 110.

136 Hobbes, Behemoth, 108; Hill, God's Englishman, 102–3.

137 Hobbes, Leviathan, 173. Also Baumgold, Deborah, Hobbes's Political Theory (Cambridge, 1988), 122Google Scholar; Hamilton, “Hobbes,” 450; Hobbes, Behemoth, 252, 373.

138 Hobbes, Behemoth, 291 (my emphasis), also 325; Collins, Allegiance, 149–51.

139 Hobbes, Behemoth, 150.

140 For Hobbes's comments on “Tyrannies” of the major generals see ibid., 363–4.

141 For two examples see Hobbes, Leviathan, 93, 160–61.

142 I owe this term to an anonymous reader.

143 Skinner, Quentin, “Conquest and Consent: Thomas Hobbes and the Engagement Controversy,” in Aylmer, G. E., ed., The Interregnum (London, 1972), 7998CrossRefGoogle Scholar (subsequently revised).

144 Hobbes, Leviathan, 385.

145 Ibid., 390.

146 Sommerville, Johann P., “Hobbes, Behemoth, Church–State Relations, and Political Obligation,” Filozofski vestnik, 24 (2003), 205–22Google Scholar, 208.

147 Collins, Allegiance, 148–9, 156, 206.

148 Metzger, Hans-Dieter, Thomas Hobbes und die Englische Revolution 1640–1660 (Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt, 1991), 148–53Google Scholar.

149 Malcolm, “General Introduction,” 1: 77–8; Hamilton, “Hobbes,” 452.

150 Hobbes, Six Lessons, 7: 335 (my emphasis), also 7: 336; Hobbes, Leviathan, 395; Hobbes, Thomas, Vita, in SirMolesworth, William, ed., Opera philosophica quae Latine scipsit, 5 vols. (London, 1839–45), 1: 1516Google Scholar; Hobbes, Considerations, 4: 439.

151 Hobbes, Behemoth, 128.

152 For a contemporary reading of Behemoth portraying Cromwell as Tacitist see Malcolm, Noel, “Behemoth Latinus: Adam Ebert, Tacitism, and Hobbes,” Filozofski vestnik, 24 (2003), 85120Google Scholar.

153 Gross, Neil, Richard Rorty: The Making of an American Philosopher (Chicago, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Collins, Randall, The Sociology of Philosophies (Cambridge, MA, 1998)Google Scholar.

154 Mannheim, Karl, Ideology and Utopia, trans. Wirth, Louis and Shils, Edward (New York, 1936), 310Google Scholar (my emphasis).

155 Bourdieu, Pierre, The State Nobility, trans. Clough, Lauretta (Cambridge, 1998)Google Scholar; Foucault, Michel, Society Must Be Defended: Lectures at the Collège de France 1975–76, ed. Bentani, Mauro and Fontana, Alessandro, trans. Macey, David (New York, 2003), 8999Google Scholar.

156 Darnton, Robert, “In Search of the Enlightenment: Recent Attempts to Create a Social History of Ideas,” Journal of Modern History, 43 (1971), 113–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

157 Skinner, Quentin, Visions of Politics, 3 vols. (Cambridge, 2002), 1Google Scholar: 145.

158 Ibid., 87.

159 Skinner, Quentin, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1978)Google Scholar, 1: xi.

160 Skinner, Visions, 1: 179, and chap. 8.

161 Ibid., 1: 180.

162 Skinner, Hobbes, 179.

163 Brett, Annabel, “What is Intellectual History Now?” in Cannadine, David, ed., What Is History Now? (Basingstoke, 2004), 113–31Google Scholar, 124.

164 She is explicit about this in Liberty, Right and Nature (Cambridge, 2003), 7 n. 19. But this is also true of Brett, Annabel, “‘The Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common-wealth’: Thomas Hobbes and Late Renaissance Commentary on Aristotle's Politics,” Hobbes Studies, 23 (2010), 72102CrossRefGoogle Scholar.