Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-09T19:09:15.692Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Abortion Access and the Benefits and Limitations of Abortion-Permissive Legal Frameworks: Lessons from the United Kingdom

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2023

Elizabeth Chloe Romanis*
Affiliation:
Centre for Ethics and Law in the Life Sciences, Durham Law School, Durham University, Durham, UK Edmond and Lily Safra Center for Ethics and Petrie-Flom Center for Health Law Policy, Biotechnology and Bioethics at Harvard Law School, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper argues that abortion access is an important subject for bioethics scholarship and reflects on the relationship between legal frameworks and access to care. The author uses the example of the United Kingdom to examine the benefits and limitations of abortion-permissive legal frameworks in terms of access. These are legal frameworks that enable the provision of abortion but subject to restrictions. An abortion-permissive regime—first in Great Britain and then in Northern Ireland—has gone some way to improving access to care over time. However, aspects of the regime (that lead to its description as permissive rather than supportive of abortion) have the potential to endanger abortion access in the future and so legal reform is necessary.

Type
Special Section: Quo Vadis Abortion: Is Reasonableness an Option?
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

The enactment of the Abortion Act 1967 (AA 1967) meant abortion became legally accessible in a wider range of circumstances in Great Britain (England, Wales, and Scotland).Footnote 1 The AA 1967 remains the basis of abortion provision in Great Britain today, and there have been few attempts to modernize it. Amendments have only been made twice in 1990Footnote 2 and 2022Footnote 3 (and only one of these can be described as a progressive change). Interpretation of the AA 1967, however, has liberalized increasingly since its inception, meaning that abortion has become increasingly accessible to British people.Footnote 4 In Northern Ireland, in contrast, abortion was only lawful where necessary to save a pregnant person’s life/to avoid very serious harmFootnote 5 until 2019 when abortion was partially decriminalized.Footnote 6 Even since decriminalization, and the introduction of new abortion regulations,Footnote 7 abortion has remained inaccessible for many abortion-seekers in Northern Ireland, many of whom are still having to travel to England for care.Footnote 8 There are no rights to abortion in the United Kingdom (UK). Although abortion remains a criminal offense across Great Britain, and in limited circumstances in Northern Ireland, conditions of abortion access have continued to improve over the last decade.

In this paper, I explore the relationship between abortion rights and abortion access, using the UK as a case study. First, I set out the importance of access to abortion. I suggest that bioethics has a role to play in advocating for abortion access. Abortion is clearly necessary and important, and bioethics should be working through how people can have the best abortion possible—with minimal legal risk. Second, I outline the law in the constituent parts of the UK to illustrate the differences. Third, I make some observations about how access has been facilitated (or not) across the UK. I argue that, although legal rights to abortion are important, access without legal risk is more important. I do not mean to suggest that legal rights are unimportant, but that rights without access achieves less good than access without rights. Finally, I reflect on some of the problems with legal frameworks for abortion without legal rights to abortion, using the UK as an example. I argue that the UK can only be described as an “abortion-permissive” legal framework, as opposed to “abortion-supportive.” Legal reform is necessary to secure access for the future. Access matters and good legal frameworks can better guarantee access for the long term.

Abortion Is Essential

Abortion is the most common gynecological procedure, and is one of the most common procedures in all of healthcare, performed worldwide.Footnote 9 Approximately 73 million pregnancies end in abortion every year.Footnote 10 In England and Wales, 214,869 abortions were performed (18.6 per 1,000 women)Footnote 11 in 2021.Footnote 12 It is widely reported that one in three women in the UK will have an abortion within their lifetime.Footnote 13 People have abortions for a variety of reasons, but fundamentally it is because they want their pregnancy to end.Footnote 14 All reasons for wanting an abortion are important to the person experiencing an unwanted pregnancy. For some, it is a matter of preserving their life and health. For others, the reasons relate to not becoming a biological parent. Abortion-seekers often explain that their abortion, for whatever reason—including those that are sometimes described as “social reasons”—was not a choice for them, but a necessity.Footnote 15 The reasons for abortion will always be there. People have abortions regardless of its legal status.Footnote 16 However, abortion is much safer in jurisdictions where it is lawful because people are much more likely to have access to quality care.Footnote 17 Although abortion medications have significantly improved the safety of self-managed abortion,Footnote 18 the associated legal risks can make it much more unsafe because people feel unable to access emergency medical care in the rare event that there are complications.Footnote 19 Restrictions on abortion kill people in a variety of ways, whether because they were unable to access medical support or because healthcare professions are precluded from performing (or feel too scared to perform) abortions when they are necessary to save people’s lives.Footnote 20

Against this context, the World Health Organization (WHO) has consistently reiterated the importance of safe access to abortion and, in 2022, recommended against the use of legal and procedural barriers—including the use of the criminal law—to regulate abortion.Footnote 21 The United Nations (UN) has also come close to recognizing abortion as a human right. Although there is no reference to a right to abortion in any of its treaties, there are provisions that can be interpreted as such. As Zoe Tongue has observed, international bodies continuously develop human rights standards to recognize the importance of access to abortion in a growing number of circumstances.Footnote 22 The UN Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women is explicit that people have the right to control their reproduction (“the same rights to decide freely and responsibly on the number and spacing of their children and to have access to the information, education, and means to enable them to exercise these rights”).Footnote 23 This could be, and has been, interpreted to be inclusive of abortion.

Despite growing recognition from the international community and the WHO of the need for abortion access, the bioethics literature has remained focused on debating the “wrongs” and “rights” of abortion: “about the idea of abortion more than the experience of abortion.”Footnote 24 These debates are completely acontextual and inherently of little use, particularly for those people who experience unwanted pregnancy. The reality is that abortion happens, and it happens often; abortion is both necessary and common. There would be much more utility in a bioethics literature that is more attentive to the issues surrounding abortion and redirects its focus to the ethical, social, and legal issues that surround a pressing problem: access to abortion. Even in countries where legal frameworks are abortion-permissive, there are often considerable barriers to access. These can be legal barriers, for example, procedural requirements that can delay care, or extra-legal barriers that can equally delay care or make it impossible to access through formal channels at all, for example, the cost of care (pertinent in countries without free-at-the-point-of-access healthcare) and/or associated with care (such as travel, time off work, or childcare).Footnote 25 These access barriers often have the greatest impact on people who are marginalized within society, for example, people who are socioeconomically disadvantaged or people with disabilities.Footnote 26 Nathan Emmerich notes that thinking about abortion as basic healthcare, and thus I argue issues of access

[does] not deny that abortion is seen as having a moral dimension. Rather, it is to make clear that any moral concerns should be seen as secondary to ensuring the proper provision of services… Almost all medical interventions raise ethical concerns in at least some cases. Nevertheless, no one supposes that these call provision itself into question. Termination of pregnancy should be treated in the same way.Footnote 27

Katie Watson has explicitly made the case for bioethics interrogating the barriers abortion-seekers face in accessing abortion. She argues that “framing the need for abortion care as an issue of health disparities shifts us from the ethics of the act of abortion to the ethics of access to abortion care.”Footnote 28 A bioethics literature that is attentive to the healthcare needs of individuals would pay greater attention to context, and the problems of access and disparate access to abortion, rather than conceptualizing abortion itself as a problem.

Although feminist bioethical literature that chooses to take this approach is sometimes criticized as political, it is also a political stance to frame abortion as a problem and ignore contemporary issues in provision and access. As I have argued elsewhere with Horn, it is a considerable problem in the bioethics literature that

[A]uthors who take the position that abortion is in need of some greater justification beyond that of respecting the importance of a private choice of termination are less frequently subject to challenge for their starting position than those who approach ethico-legal issues from the starting point of abortion as healthcare.Footnote 29

For this reason, it can be very difficult to publish bioethics scholarship that looks at ethical issues in the provision of care (as Emmerich suggested should be a primary focus) and disparities of care (as Watson suggests is a priority). The conventions of bioethics as a field of scholarship, in promoting conversation that moralizes abortion as a choice rather than those that seek to examine ethical issues in barriers to care and disparities in access, must shift. In this paper, I will continue to examine the relationship between the ethical problem of disparity in access to abortion and the relationship between legal rights and abortion access.

Abortion Law in the United Kingdom

Abortion remains a criminal offense in Great Britain. In England and Wales, this is by virtue of the Offences Against the Person Act 1861,Footnote 30 which criminalizes the procurement of miscarriage (this also applied in Northern Ireland until 2019), and the Infant Life (Preservation) Act 1929, which criminalizes child destruction.Footnote 31 In Scotland, abortion remains a crime under the common law.Footnote 32 Across Great Britain, the AA 1967 is in effect and renders abortion lawful when abortion is performed in compliance with conditions set out in section one of the AA 1967Footnote 33 relating to the why, when, where, and how of abortion.Footnote 34 Conversely, any ending of pregnancy done with the intent to procure miscarriage outside the conditions of the AA 1967 is unlawful and the pregnant person, and any health professional/other person who assists, risks life imprisonment. Per the Offences Against the Person Act 1861, a person who was seeking abortion will only have committed the actus reus of criminal miscarriage if they were actually pregnant at the time of the attempted abortion. A doctor or other assisting person commits the actus reus if they act with intent to procure miscarriage even if the person is not pregnant at the time of the attempt. Abortion is lawful where two doctors, forming their opinion in good faith, determine that the abortion-seeker meets one of the following conditions:

  1. 1) s.1(1)(a) pregnancy has not exceeded 24 weeks and continuing the pregnancy would present greater risk than if the pregnancy were terminated to the pregnant person’s physical or mental health or any existing children of their family. (The Act specifies that in determining whether pregnancy poses a risk to a person’s health “account must be taken of the pregnant woman’s actual or reasonably foreseeable environment.”)Footnote 35

  2. 2) s.1(1)(b) abortion is necessary to prevent grave, permanent injury to the physical or mental health of the pregnant person.

  3. 3) s.1(1)(c) continuing the pregnancy would be a greater risk to the life of the pregnant person than termination.

  4. 4) s.1(1)(d) there is a substantial risk that the fetus suffers from a physical or mental abnormality that means that, if it were born alive, it would be “seriously handicapped.”

In addition to meeting one of the above conditions, abortions must be prescribed by a doctor (rather than any other health professional who is qualified to prescribe other medications) and performed in a hospital, clinic, or other approved place.Footnote 36 Since changes to the law made temporarily in 2020 during the COVID-19 pandemicFootnote 37 that have since become permanent, before 10 weeks’ gestation, a person can be provided with both abortion medications, mifepristone and misoprostol, to be administered at their “usual place of residence” in England and Wales.Footnote 38 In Scotland, approval orders issued during the pandemic to enable abortion medications to be administered at home remain in effect on a rolling basis. Abortion medications can be provided to a person for use in their home in Scotland until 11 weeks, 6 days’ gestation.Footnote 39

The framing of the AA 1967, and the conditions it places on the reason for abortion and under what circumstances, is highly medicalized. Essentially, who can have an abortion is entirely subject to medical control,Footnote 40 and this is by design. Although the campaign for legal change had been led by the Abortion Law Reform Association since the late 1930s, the medical profession had considerable influence in shaping the AA 1967.Footnote 41 The AA 1967 was introduced as a public health measureFootnote 42: to address the high incidence of mortality and morbidity resulting from clandestine abortion. However, there were also other relevant motivations that shaped the framing of abortion provision. Sally Sheldon argues that the AA 1967 was also intended to curb the ongoing “de facto female resistance to the law” evident in the routine seeking and performance of clandestine abortion.Footnote 43 Politicians wanted to control who was having abortions and under what circumstances and this was much easier to do with regulation permitting abortion in situations they see as justifiable, monitored by the medical profession, than in completely prohibiting the practice (except where necessary to save a pregnant person’s life)Footnote 44 as had been the status quo. The AA 1967 was written for medical professionals, not only to assist them by reducing the number of people needing treatment following clandestine abortion or in controlling who had abortions, but also to offer them some certainty about the legality of the abortions they were already readily performing for (usually) wealthier people.Footnote 45 The Royal Medico-Psychological Association was explicitly in favor of the AA 1967 because “many medical men were inhibited from advising or performing abortion through fear of the law.”Footnote 46 Although the AA 1967 might be described by some as some sort of compromise—allowing access to abortion while affording some respect to the fetus—it does no such thing; it only protects doctors.Footnote 47 The medicalization of abortion was a mechanism that enabled the practice to be somewhat depoliticized and more palatable to politicians, making room for legislation that enabled access.

Although the AA 1967 was passed in Great Britain, and with it access to legal abortion for more people, no such changes were introduced in Northern Ireland where the political climate was even more complex. Consequently, the criminal provisions in the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 remained those that governed the provision of abortion. People in Northern Ireland thus had no access to terminations unless necessary to save their lives/serious risk to health (where doctors were willing to help them) or they were able to travel to England and shoulder the costs themselves (even though their taxes would contribute to NHS-funded access for women in Great Britain).Footnote 48 Since 2017, abortions in Great Britain have been NHS-funded for people who traveled from Northern Ireland.Footnote 49 This did not, however, eliminate other associated costs, however, such as taking time off work, travel, and potentially childcare. Abortion was partially decriminalized in 2019 with the relevant criminal offenses in the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 ceasing to apply in Northern Ireland. New regulations were introduced to govern abortion provision. These regulations can be described as somewhat more progressive than the AA 1967Footnote 50; the criminal offense they establish of providing abortion care outside of the terms of the regulations cannot be used to prosecute pregnant persons themselves,Footnote 51 the regulations enable abortion on demand until 12 weeks,Footnote 52 and they permit nurse prescription of abortion medications.Footnote 53 Despite these improvements, the regulations “continue to embody an approach [to care] that enables non-medically indicated interference” in people’s abortion decisions.Footnote 54 For example, the regulations do not enable home use of the first abortion medication, mifepristone. Mifepristone must still be administered in a clinic and then misoprostol can be provided for home use.Footnote 55 People in Northern Ireland, therefore, must (unlike people in Great Britain) attend a clinic in-person to have an early medical abortion. The framing of abortion in these regulations remains steeped in medicalization and exceptionalism.

Abortion-seekers from Northern Ireland have been traveling to England since the enactment of the AA 1967.Footnote 56 It was hoped that partial decriminalization and the new regulations would enable care closer to home. Although the number of people traveling to England has declined since the regulations have passed (371 in 2020; 161 in 2021),Footnote 57 this has not been wholly attributable to the availability of care locally. The Department of Health and Social Care in England noted that “[t]he large decrease in the number of abortions for residents outside of England and Wales may be explained by travel restrictions in place throughout 2021 due to the COVID-19 pandemic” as well as changes to the law.Footnote 58 Although abortion is more available in Northern Ireland than it was pre-2019, Northern Ireland’s Department of Health did not immediately commission a service rollout of funded abortion care. This meant people carried on traveling to England or turning to local activist groups that help individuals obtain abortion medications for home use.Footnote 59 In December 2022, the Westminster Northern Ireland Secretary commissioned local services,Footnote 60 and some information is available on how to access care locally.Footnote 61

Access to Abortion

In Great Britain, the wording of the AA 1967 provisions leaves considerable discretion for healthcare professionals.Footnote 62 The first ground for abortion (before 24 weeks and on the basis that risk of pregnancy is greater than termination) is often called the “social ground” for abortion.Footnote 63 Parliament was clear, during the debates surrounding the AA 1967, that none of its provisions were intended to enable “abortion on demand.”Footnote 64 However, healthcare professionals’ interpretation of the “social ground” for abortion became gradually more liberal in the few decades after 1968,Footnote 65 especially with the advent of medication abortion.Footnote 66 The ground is interpreted, in practice and in legal scholarship alike, as meaning that abortion is always legal early in a pregnancy because abortion is very safe and, especially early in a pregnancy, safer than birthing.Footnote 67 The British Medical Association endorses this interpretation.Footnote 68 Consequently, the consensus is that every pregnancy can be legally terminated under 24 weeks.Footnote 69 Where people are able to make contact with abortion provider early in a pregnancy, abortion can thus be provided under the AA 1967 conditions.

One notable point about the operation of the AA 1967 and abortion provision in the UK is the “dominant role” that is played by abortion charities (Sheldon et al. describe this as “highly distinctive and significant aspect of the Abortion Act’s biography”).Footnote 70 The leading providers of abortion care are the British Pregnancy Advisory Service (BPAS) and MSI (formerly Marie Stopes International—now just MSI). Seventy-seven percent of abortions in England and Wales are performed by these clinics that have contracts with the NHS.Footnote 71 These services were established to ensure access in areas of the country where abortion provision was made difficult by medical gatekeepingFootnote 72 (BPAS began as the “Birmingham Pregnancy Advisory Service”Footnote 73) and have become an embedded feature of provision over time.Footnote 74 Abortions provided by these independent clinics are free at the point of access for people entitled to NHS treatment. In 2021, 99% of abortions performed in England and Wales were funded by the NHS.Footnote 75

Emmerich criticizes the fact that abortions are outsourced to independent providers as a feature of abortion exceptionalism. He argues that service provision by “third parties contributes to the idea that such services are unusual, different, or in some way out of the norm… such services should simply be brought ‘in house.’”Footnote 76 There is more nuance to the story than this, however. It is the case that abortion being predominantly delivered by third-party providers makes for a “structural weakness” in regulation (these independent providers can be more easily targeted with hostile measuresFootnote 77—at present, these providers are facing considerably more scrutiny that other healthcare providers surrounding their safeguarding obligations to patients, for example).Footnote 78 However, it is important to acknowledge that there are ways in which the independent providers have been integral to improving access. Sheldon et al. note that the role abortion charities have occupied, enabled by the AA 1967, has entrenched “the long-term sustainability of a permissive model of service provision” and equally it has enabled dedicated providers to become “a powerful voice for further liberalizing reform.”Footnote 79

At the level of the experience of the service user, people accessing abortion can directly contact an independent provider who specializes in providing this care (there is no need for a referral). This means that abortion-seekers need only interact with healthcare providers and support staff who have chosen to work in abortion services, which likely improves their experience. There is considerable stigma in the law, for example, in the labeling of abortion as a “crime”Footnote 80 (this will be reflected on later in more detail); however, this is not a stigma that many abortion-seekers experience since many are not aware that it is a crime.Footnote 81 I think it reasonable to suggest that this is because dedicated providers work to ensure that abortion-seekers are shielded from the stigmatizing elements of the regulation.

Independent providers have also been pivotal in campaigns for law reform. For example, they have successfully campaigned for several changes over the last 5 years that have made a considerable difference in improving the accessibility of abortion in Great Britain. First, independent providers were instrumental in the campaign for home use of misoprostol (the second abortion medication in the drug regimen recommended by the WHO), which eventually culminated in legal changes in 2017/2018.Footnote 82 Home use of misoprostol greatly improved the accessibility of abortion because it meant that people did not have to travel to a clinic twice for services, as well as enhanced the comfort and experience of abortion-seekers because they could miscarry in their own homes.Footnote 83 Second, the providers were also instrumental in the shift to and delivery of telemedical abortion—which became temporarily lawful in 2020 in Great Britain during the COVID-19 pandemic.Footnote 84 This greatly improved the accessibility of abortion because it meant people did not have to leave their homes during a public emergency, risking their safety, to access care.Footnote 85 There were people who (even before the pandemic) would have struggled to access care in a clinic for a variety of reasons: living in a rural area, no access to public transport, limited financial resources, disability, inability to find suitable childcare, or fear of a domestic abuser.Footnote 86 Abortion providers, with the data they had collected during the pandemic period showing the clear benefits,Footnote 87 led the campaign to make telemedicine permanent. Amendments were made to the AA 1967 by the Health and Social Care Act 2022, which became law in April 2022. Finally, BPAS’s “Back Off” campaign—which sought to introduce “buffer zones” around abortion clinics to prevent abortion-seekers from being harassed by anti-choice protestorsFootnote 88—culminated in a legal victory in October 2022. MPs passed an amendment to the Public Order Bill (expected to become law in early 2023) that creates buffer zones and criminalizes the violation of the zones in England and Wales.Footnote 89 This is also important for abortion access because it can ensure that in-person care, for people who want to attend a clinic, remains a possibility where people may otherwise have felt too intimidated to attend.

These examples all illustrate that abortion access in Great Britain is improving, but not without considerable effort by campaigning groups, including abortion providers, for legal reform.

Abortion Access Versus Abortion Rights

“Framing matters, but access matters more.”Footnote 90

Given the time sensitive nature of abortion care,Footnote 91 ensuring adequate and timely access to services is the most important aspect of service provision. The health and legal risks of later term abortions outside of formal healthcare channels mean that ensuring people have the abortions they need as soon as possible is the best way to guarantee quality and safe care. I have argued elsewhere that “[it] seems less important to have a formally declared constitutional right to services than it does to have access to them.”Footnote 92 This comment was made about the United States in its Roe era—at the time, precedent that understood the right to privacy as encompassing a right to abortion before viabilityFootnote 93 was still standing. Despite this, however, the foundations of the right to abortion had been so eroded that there were vast expanses of the country where people had practically no access to abortion at all.Footnote 94 Goodwin termed the abortion right a “mish-mash” because what it meant in practice was still governed by laws at the state level.Footnote 95 The legal framework established by Roe and subsequent case law (notably, Planned Parenthood v. Casey Footnote 96) enabled state regulation of abortion that was able to target both abortion providers and abortion-seekers to make abortion more difficult. Furthermore, federal law prohibiting the use of federal funds for abortion prohibited support for the poorest people.Footnote 97 Access to abortion in the United States was never “reflective of its widely acclaimed status as a constitutional right.”Footnote 98 This illustrates that declarations of abortion rights are meaningless if they are not made in terms that also ensure access (I will come back to this in the last section of this paper). The reproductive justice movement in the United States, led by Black and women of color feminists in organizations such as SisterSong,Footnote 99 has long criticized the emphasis placed on rights and choice in reproduction as a fundamental problem. Roberts emphasizes how “[t]he language of choice has proved useless for claiming public resources that most women need in order to maintain control over their bodies and their lives.”Footnote 100 Roe v. Wade was an empty promise for people living in anti-abortion states (who could choose termination but would struggle to get one). That is not to say that things are not likely worse now post-Roe, but just that having a right to abortion did not mean a person in Louisiana or Texas or Mississippi could get one.

In contrast, people in the UK have no right to abortion at all. However, access to abortion has consistently improved over time. Although there is no law in the UK that is actively abortion-supportive (like declaring a right to abortion—or more meaningfully, to access abortion), people in Great Britain will have had a better experience of abortion than many of their counterparts in much of the United States. In many ways, the reason access continued to improve in Great Britain was a direct result of the medicalization of abortion that depoliticized provisionFootnote 101 that enabled charitable providers, and the committed healthcare providers that work for them, to make changes within the existing framework. This is why looking at how legal provisions come to operate in practice matters so much—on paper, one might have been forgiven for thinking that a Roe v. Wade United States was more abortion-supportive than the UK; however, that was far from the reality. The story from the UK is a much less tragic one than that of the United States; but, it is far from ideal. The story of improving access in the UK is not perfect, and there are important lessons to be learned. First, although medicalization may have had benefits in improving access, it also means that there is some fragility to abortion access. Second, abortion exceptionalism means that even within a system that enables access to abortion, limits are still placed on the quality of care.Footnote 102 These two themes are explored in the next section.

Problems with Abortion-Permissive Regulation

Although ensuring access is imperative, the fact that access is improving across the UK—due to the work of dedicated providers and activists against a hostile legal and regulatory environment—does not mean that there is not the need for fundamental legal reform. In fact, the current conditions exemplify the need for sweeping reform. The legal regime across the UK can be described as “abortion-permissive”—in that it has enabled access to abortion and even enabled some evolution in access over time (although many of the biggest changes required legal change). However, permissive regulation is not the same as supportive regulation, which we might consider to be a framework that solidifies the importance of access over time. The framing of the AA 1967 provisions, procedural requirements in the AA 1967 and the Northern Irish regulations, prevent more radical service evolution. They also embody the fundamental fragility of abortion access, given that it is rooted in medicalization. These two factors thus make it impossible to describe the UK framework as abortion-supportive. This potentially has implications for abortion access in the future.

The current legal framework has come under considerable scrutiny from legal scholars. First, in that the use of the criminal law, which still underpins provision in Great Britain, perpetuates abortion stigmaFootnote 103 and abortion exceptionalism.Footnote 104 Although there are few prosecutions of healthcare professionals for procuring miscarriage where they have not complied with the terms of the AA 1967, there have been prosecutions against abortion-seekers, usually when they have used abortion medications later in pregnancy.Footnote 105 In these cases, the people who have done so are often in very vulnerable circumstances and the use of the criminal law to respond has been strongly criticized.Footnote 106 In 2021, a new mother was charged with procuring miscarriage when doctors found what they believed to be misoprostol in her body while she was in hospital for delivery. She explained that she had been previously prescribed them and had accidentally taken them believing them to be thrush medications. Although the case was dismissed in 2022, with the judge noting that he was “flabbergasted” that the charges were pursued,Footnote 107 it illustrates both the expansiveness of the criminal provisions, and the willingness of prosecution services to pursue people for use of abortion medications. The criminal law thus remains a very real threat to abortion-seekers. This has been especially true since the introduction of telemedical abortion. There is concern that in all the benefits that telemedicine has, it also increases the likelihood of abortion-seekers, even acting in careful, safe, and responsible ways, inadvertently falling foul of the provisions that make the abortion lawful (strict conditions about the when, where, how, etc., of abortion).

Although the AA 1967 does provide circumstances for lawful abortion, it is heavily medicalized. Between the criminalization and medicalized exceptions, Maxine Lattimer explains that legally “[a]bortion is constructed as an unusual or abnormal act, undertaken for primarily medical reasons,”Footnote 108 which does not reflect abortion-seekers’ reality and reinforces stigma. As we have explored, the medicalization of abortion through law has had substantial benefits in securing and improving people’s access to abortion services; however, as Sheldon has warned, “it also poses substantial problems for that access, and these have been inadequately addressed.”Footnote 109 Fundamentally, the law provides no guarantee of abortion to abortion-seekers: within the law, “there is no basis for recognizing a woman’s right to choose at any stage in pregnancy.”Footnote 110 Abortions are contingent on doctors determining that abortion is appropriate in the person’s circumstances.Footnote 111 In being dependent on healthcare professionals’ opinions, rather than individuals own rights and decisions about their reproduction, access to abortion is innately fragile. It is highly unlikely, given the existence of dedicated providers, that there would be change within the profession that means that health providers are no longer willing to provide care, though conscientious objection in other healthcare environments, for example, GP clinics and hospitals, should not be discounted. Willing providers being vulnerable to hostile regulation, and people having no recourse if they are unable to access abortion, are significant weaknesses in the regime that leave abortion-seekers without any guarantee of care.

As has been evidenced, access has improved considerably in the UK. We have seen the introduction of measures that have enabled local care in Northern Ireland, and home use of abortion medications in Great Britain. On both counts, the privacy, autonomy, and comfort of abortion-seekers have been enhanced by reducing the need for travel in having an abortion. However, these success stories still exemplify issues. The legal framework across the UK remains deeply flawed, perpetuates stigma, and changes are difficult to make. Legal changes are necessary for structural changes in provision and have only occurred in the system usually after some involvement of external forces. In Northern Ireland, change resulted from internal pressure from activists but also strong criticism from the UN Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women.Footnote 112 In Great Britain, telemedicine and home use of both abortion medications resulted from the pressures of a pandemic—despite the evidence about the benefits and safety of telemedicine having existed long before.Footnote 113 Thus, reform is needed. Many scholars have argued that decriminalization is a necessary reform in the UK.Footnote 114 This would go some way toward the construction of an abortion-supportive legal framework. Decriminalization can begin the demystification and normalization of, and dismantling the stigma around, abortion.Footnote 115 Furthermore, if there were no criminal regulation of abortion, it would be much easier for providers to evolve their service provision in line with evidence about best practiceFootnote 116 from organizations like the WHO, without having to first campaign for legal change.

This leaves us with the question of what a better abortion-supportive legal framework looks like? Decriminalization is a start, but it also does not go far enough. For example, in Canada, which has had a complete decriminalization of abortion since the law was “struck down” by the Supreme Court in 1988,Footnote 117 there remain multiple structural barriers to accessing care.Footnote 118 Though, arguably, decriminalization would better secure structural changes that enable access, and better access, for abortion-seekers in the UK since there are established independent providers.Footnote 119 What exactly a comprehensive abortion-supportive regime might look like in the UK is a question that requires and deserves further reflection from bioethicists, in addition to the work being done by legal scholars, activists, and dedicated politicians.

Conclusion

Abortion access matters. Bioethics needs to redirect its focus from problematizing abortion to thinking about the experience of abortion and how this can be improved for abortion-seekers. Since abortion is common, how abortion is talked about should begin to reflect its normalcy. Abortion access remains a challenge because of the intersection of complex barriers that ought to be recognized as “structural violence.”Footnote 120 These barriers manifest for all abortion-seekers, but their effect is much greater among marginalized people. The story from the UK is one of the increasing liberalization of abortion regulation and improving access. However, the experience of abortion-seekers is made better, against what is fundamentally a hostile legal environment to abortion in hyper-regulation, by the work of charitable providers and their committed staff. Moreover, improvements to care at the individual level are often despite the legal framework, rather than because of it. Moreover, changes to service provision have always required legal change that takes time and resources and means that abortion-seekers do not get the best possible care while that process takes place. Although I have argued that access to abortion is the most important matter at hand, the UK example illustrates that legal frameworks must be better than abortion-permissive (they must be abortion-supportive) to secure abortion access in the long term.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares none.

References

Notes

1. AA 1967.

2. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Act 1990.

3. Health and Social Care Act 2022.

4. Sheldon S. Beyond Control: Medical Power and Abortion Law. London: Pluto Press; 1997, at 11; Lee, E. Tensions in the regulation of abortion in Britain. Journal of Law and Society 2003;30:533–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5. Offences Against the Person Act 1861; Re AMNH [1994] NIJB 1.

6. Northern Ireland (Executive Formation, etc.) Act 2019, s.9(2).

7. The Abortion (Northern Ireland) (No. 2) Regulations 2020.

8. McCormack J. Abortion: 161 women from NI travelled to England and Wales for services in 2021. BBC News 2022 June 21; available at https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-northern-ireland-61881352 (last accessed 13 Nov 2022).

9. Lerma, K, Blumenthal, P. Current and potential methods for second trimester abortion. Best Practice & Research Clinical Obstetrics & Gynaecology 2020;63:2436, at 24CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

10. Guttmacher Institute. Unintended Pregnancy and Abortion Worldwide; 2022 Mar; available at https://www.guttmacher.org/fact-sheet/induced-abortion-worldwide# (last accessed 14 Nov 2022).

11. I use “women” when referring to Department of Health and Social Care statistics, despite the fact that there are people with the capacity to become pregnant who are not women, because this is the language used in their collection and reporting of data.

12. Department of Health and Social Care. Abortion Statistics, England and Wales: 2021; 2022 Nov 17; available at https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/abortion-statistics-for-england-and-wales-2021/abortion-statistics-england-and-wales-2021 (last accessed 13 Nov 2022).

13. Stone, N, Ingham, R. Who presents more than once? Repeat abortion among women in Britain. Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 2011;37:209–15CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed, at 209.

14. Brerer, M. Making abortion a woman’s right worldwide. Reproductive Health Matters 2002;10:18 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 3.

15. Janiak, E, Goldberg, AB. Eliminating the phrase “elective abortion”: Why language matters. Contraception 2016;93:8992 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

16. Jackson, E. Regulating Reproduction: Law, Technology and Autonomy. Oxford: Hart Publishing; 2001, at 72 Google Scholar.

17. World Health Organization. Abortion Care Guideline; 2022 Mar 8; available at https://www.who.int/publications/i/item/9789240039483 (last accessed 13 Dec 2022), at 24.

18. Gomperts, RJ, Jelinska, K, Davies, S, Gemzell-Danielsson, K, Kleiverda, G. Using telemedicine for termination of pregnancy with mifepristone and misoprostol in settings where there is no access to safe services. British Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology 2008;9:1171–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19. Boyle, M, McEvoy, J. Putting abortion in its social context: Northern Irish women’s experiences of abortion in England. Health 1998;2:283304, at 297CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20. Schwartz M. You go to the labor ward, and you are treated like meat. The New Republic 2022 May 10; available at https://newrepublic.com/article/166342/poland-abortion-restrictions (last accessed 29 Aug 2022).

21. See 17, World Health Organization 2022, at 24–9.

22. Tongue Z. Telemedical and self-managed abortion: A human rights imperative? European Journal of Health Law 2022. doi:10.1163/15718093-bja10092.

23. UN Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, Article 16(1)(e).

24. Watson, K. The ethics of access: Reframing the need for abortion care as a health disparity. American Journal of Bioethics 2022;22:2230 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 22.

25. Parsons, JA, Romanis, EC. Early Medical Abortion, Equality of Access and the Telemedical Imperative. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2021 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 43, 121.

27. Emmerich N. We should not take abortion services for granted. Clinical Ethics 2022. doi:10.1177/14777509221140746.

28. See 24, Watson 2022, at 23.

29. Romanis, EC, Horn, C. Artificial wombs and the ectogenesis conversation: A misplaced focus? Technology, abortion, and reproductive freedom. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2020;13:174–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 185.

30. Offences Against the Person Act 1861, ss.58 and 59.

31. Infant Life (Preservation) Act 1929, s.1.

32. Explanatory notes to the Scotland Act 1998.

33. Abortion Act 1967, s.5(2).

34. Romanis EC, Mullock A, Parsons JA. The excessive regulation of early abortion medication in the UK: The case for reform. Medical Law Review 2021;29:185–92.

35. Abortion Act 1967, s.1(2).

36. See 1, AA 1967, s.1(3) and (3A); (3C); (3D).

37. Parsons, JA, Romanis, EC. 2020 developments in the provision of early medical abortion by telemedicine in the UK. Health Policy 2021;125:1721 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

38. Abortion Act 1967, s.1(3B) as amended by the Health and Social Care Act 2002, s.178.

39. Scottish Government. The Abortion Act 1967 (Place for Treatment for the Termination of Pregnancy) (Approval) (Scotland); 2020 Mar 31; available at https://www.sehd.scot.nhs.uk/cmo/CMO(2020)09.pdf (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

40. See 4, Sheldon 1997; Sheldon, S. British abortion law: Speaking from the past to govern the future. Modern Law Review 2016;79:283316 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41. Abortion, Keown J., Doctors and the Law: Some Aspects of the Legal Regulation of Abortion in England from 1803 to 1982. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1988 Google Scholar, at 88.

42. See 4, Sheldon 1997; See 16, Jackson 2001, at 72; Sheldon, S. The medical framework and early abortion in the UK: How can a state control swallowing? In: Cook, R, Erdman, J, Dickens, B, eds. Abortion Law in Transnational Perspective: Cases and Controversies. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press; 2014 Google Scholar.

43. See 4, Sheldon 1997, at 24.

44. R v. Bourne [1939] 1 KB 687.

45. See 40, Keown 1988.

46. See 40, Keown 1988, at 108.

47. See 4, Sheldon 1997, at 42.

48. Sheldon S. The decriminalisation of abortion: An argument for modernisation. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 2015;1–32, at 8.

49. Government Equalities Office. Letter from Justice Greening on abortion in England; 2017 June 29; available at https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/623669/Letter_from_Justine_Greening_on_Abortion_in_England.pdf (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

50. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 23.

51. See 6, reg 11.

52. See 6, reg 3.

53. See 6, reg 3.

54. See 34, Romanis et al. 2021, at 190.

55. See 6, reg 8.

56. Fox, M, Horgon, G. The effects of decriminalisation in Northern Ireland. In: Sheldon, S, Wellings, K, eds. Decriminalising Abortion in the UK: What Would It Mean? Bristol: Policy Press; 2020, at 82 Google Scholar; Sheldon, S, Davis, G, O’Neill, J, Parker, C. The Abortion Act 1967: A Biography of a UK Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2022, at 191 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 194.

57. See 12, Department of Health and Social Care.

58. See 12, Department of Health and Social Care.

59. Chick K. Women in Northern Ireland still struggle to access abortion more than 2 years after decriminalisation. Time 2022 June 30; available at https://time.com/6192022/northern-ireland-abortion-access/ (last accessed 1 Dec 2022).

60. Full abortion services may not be ready in six months, doctor says. Derry Now 2022 Dec 4; available at https://www.derrynow.com/news/northern-ireland/979596/full-abortion-services-may-not-be-ready-in-six-months-doctor-says.html (last accessed 4 Dec 2022).

61. NI Direct Government Services. Abortion Services; available at https://www.nidirect.gov.uk/articles/abortion-services (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

62. Grubb, A. Abortion law in England: The medicalization of a crime. Law, Medicine and Health Care 1990;18:146–61, at 155CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63. Brazier, M, Cave, E. Medicine, Patients and the Law. Manchester: Manchester University Press; 2016, at 404 Google Scholar.

64. See 40, Keown 1988, at 128.

65. See 4, Sheldon 1997, at 2.

66. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021.

67. See 40, Keown 1988; Grubb A. The new law of abortion: Clarification or ambiguity? Criminal Law Review 1991;659–70; Jackson E. Abortion, autonomy and prenatal diagnosis. Social & Legal Studies 2000;9:467–94.

68. British Medical Association. First Trimester Abortion: A Briefing Paper by the BMA’s Medical Ethics Committee. London: British Medical Association; 2007.

69. Cook, R. Stigmatized meanings of criminal abortion law. In: Cook, R, Erdman, J, Dickens, B, eds. Abortion Law in Transnational Perspective: Cases and Controversies. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press; 2014 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

70. See 55, Sheldon et al. 2022, at 115.

71. See 12, Department of Health and Social Care.

72. McGuinness, S. A guerrilla strategy for a pro-life England. Law, Innovation and Technology 2015;7:283314 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 285.

73. Humanist Heritage. British Pregnancy Advisory Service; available at https://heritage.humanists.uk/british-pregnancy-advisory-service/ (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

74. See 55, Sheldon et al. 2022, at 116.

75. See 12, Department of Health and Social Care.

76. See 27, Emmerich 2022.

77. See 71, McGuiness 2015, at 287.

78. Romanis, EC, Parsons, JA, Salter, I, Hampton, T. Safeguarding and teleconsultation for abortion. The Lancet 2021;398:555–8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

79. See 55, Sheldon et al. 2022, at 115.

80. See 68, Cook 2014.

81. See 4, Lee 2003, at 533.

82. Parsons, JA. 2017–19 governmental decisions to allow home use of misoprostol for early medical abortion in the UK. Health Policy 2020;124:679–83CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

83. See 81, Parsons 2020.

84. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021.

85. Romanis EC, Parsons JA, Hodson N. COVID-19 and reproductive justice in Great Britain and the United States: Ensuring access to abortion care during a global pandemic. Journal of Law and the Biosciences 2020;7:1-23. doi:10.1093/jlb/lsaa027.

86. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 31–56.

87. Aiken, ARA, Lohr, PA, , J Starling, J. Effectiveness, safety and acceptability of no-test medical abortion (termination of pregnancy) provided via telemedicine: A national cohort study. British Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology 2021;128:1464–74CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

88. British Pregnancy Advisory Service. Back Off; available at https://bpas-campaigns.org/campaigns/backoff/ (last accessed 15 Nov 2022).

89. Public Order Bill; available at https://bills.parliament.uk/publications/48041/documents/2332 (last accessed 15 Nov 2022).

90. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 165.

91. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 122.

92. Romanis EC. Is “viability” viable? Abortion, conceptual confusion and the law in England and Wales and the United States. Journal of Law and the Biosciences 2020;7:1-29. doi:10.1093/jlb/lsaa059.

93. Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).

94. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 42.

95. Goodwin, M. Policing the Womb: Invisible Women and the Criminalization of Motherhood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2020 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

96. Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 112 U.S. 2791 (1992).

97. Departments of Labor and Health, Education, and Welfare Appropriation Act of 1977 (“Hyde Amendment”).

98. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 56.

99. SisterSong; available at https://www.sistersong.net/mission (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

100. Roberts, D. Reproductive justice, not just rights. Dissent 2015;62:7982 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 80.

101. See 4, Sheldon 1997; see 16, Jackson 2001.

102. See 34, Romanis et al. 2021; see 17, World Health Organization 2022, at 24–9.

103. Halliday, S. Protecting human dignity: Reframing the abortion debate to respect the dignity of choice and life. Contemporary Issues in Law 2016;13:287322, at 300Google Scholar.

104. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 14–21.

105. See 47, Sheldon 2015.

106. Milne, E. Putting the fetus first—legal regulation, motherhood, and pregnancy. Michigan Journal of Gender & Law 2020;27:149211 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

107. Seaward T. CPS drops prosecution of Oxford mum accused of “procuring miscarriage”. Oxford Mail 2022 Dec 9; available at https://www.oxfordmail.co.uk/news/23181446.cps-drops-prosecution-oxford-mum-accused-procuring-miscarriage/ (last accessed 9 Dec 2022).

108. Lattimer, M. Hegemonic discourse in British abortion law. In: Lee, E, ed. Abortion Law and Politics Today. Basingstoke: MacMillan Press; 1998, at 60 Google Scholar.

109. See 4, Sheldon 1997, at 4.

110. See 55, Sheldon et al. 2022, at 194.

111. See 61, Grubb 1990, at 661.

112. UN Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women. Inquiry concerning the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland under Article 8 of the Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women: Report of the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women; 2018 Mar 6; available at https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/1480026?ln=en (last accessed 13 Dec 2022).

113. See 25, Parsons, Romanis 2021, at 130–42.

114. See 66, Jackson 2000; see 71, McGuiness 2015; see 47, Sheldon 2015; Halliday, S. Maintaining the criminal prohibition of abortion as a means of protecting women: Alternative facts and realities in reproductive law and policy. In: Sinn, A, Hauck, P, Nagel, M, Wörner, L, eds. Populismus und alternative Fakten. Tuebingen: Mohr Siebeck; 2020 Google Scholar; see 55, Sheldon, Wellings 2020.

115. Erdman, JN, Cook, RJ. Decriminalization of abortion—A human rights imperative. Best Practice & Research Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 2020;62:1124 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

116. Lohr P, Lord J, Rowlands S. How would decriminalisation affect women’s health? In: Sheldon, Wellings 2020 (see 55), at 43–4.

117. R v. Morgentaler [1988] 1 SCR 30.

118. Kaposy, C. Improving abortion access in Canada. Health Care Analysis 2010;18:1734 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed; Johnson BR, Keogh L, Norman W. What would be the likely impact of decriminalisation on the incidence, timing, provision and safety of abortion? In: Sheldon, Wellings 2020 (see 55).

119. Romanis, EC. Book Review: Sally Sheldon, and Kaye Wellings, (eds), Decriminalising Abortion in the UK: What Would It Mean? Medical Law Review 2021;29:18529 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 191.

120. Nandagiri, R, Coast, E, Strong, E. COVID-19 and abortion: Making structural violence visible. International Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 2020;46:83–9CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed, at 83.