Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T23:10:41.429Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The problem of low expectations and the principled politician

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2022

Sam Schmitt*
Affiliation:
UNC-Chapel Hill, Hamilton Hall, 358, Campus Box 3265, Chapel Hill, NC 27599, USA

Abstract

Nobel laureate James Buchanan downplays any theory of ethical politicians, focusing instead on rules which economize personal restraint, setting lower moral expectations. Through a constructive critique of James Buchanan’s work, I argue these lowered expectations come at a cost: degraded character in politicians, leading to constitutional decay. Buchanan lacks a theory to address choices between (a) action which furthers the politician’s self-interest and (b) action which protects some already accepted, good rule, but which does not further their self-interest. I generate a theory of the Principled Politician, an agent characterized by a prior commitment to fair play.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aldrich, J.H. 2011. Why Parties? A Second Look. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226012759.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aligica, P.D. 2018. Artefactual and artisanship: James M. Buchanan and Vincent Ostrom at the core and beyond the boundaries of public choice. In James M. Buchanan: A Theorist of Political Economy and Social Philosophy, ed. Wagner, R.E., 11051129. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.10.1007/978-3-030-03080-3_48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermeo, N. 2016. On democratic backsliding. Journal of Democracy 1, 519.10.1353/jod.2016.0012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Besley, T. 2006. Principled Agents: The Political Economy of Good Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blake, A. 2019. Thom Tillis’s remarkable flip-flop on Trump’s national emergency and 4 others who also backed off. The Washington Post, 14 March 2019. https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/2019/03/14/thom-tilliss-remarkable-flip-flop-trumps-national-emergency-others-who-also-backed-off/ Google Scholar
Boettke, P.J. 2012. Living Economics. Oakland, CA: The Independent Institute.Google Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. 1980. The Power to Tax: Analytical Foundations of a Fiscal Constitution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; reprinted in The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 9. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2000.Google Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. 1981. The normative purpose of economic science: rediscovery of an eighteenth century method. International Review of Law and Economics 1, 155166.10.1016/0144-8188(81)90013-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. 1985. The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; reprinted in The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 10. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2000.Google Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. 1988. Is public choice immoral? The case for the “Nobel” lie. Virginia Law Review 2, 179189. doi: 10.2307/1073142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, G. and Hamlin, A. 1995. Economizing on virtue. Constitutional Political Economy 6, 3556.10.1007/BF01298375CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1975. The Samaritan’s dilemma. In Altruism, Morality, and Economic Theory, ed. Phelps, E.S.. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation; reprinted in The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 1: The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty, 329345. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1999.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1979a. Politics without romance: a sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications. IHS Journal 3, B1–B11; reprinted in The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 1: The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty, 45–59. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1999.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1979b. Natural and artifactual man? In What Should Economists Do? Indianapolis: Liberty Fund; reprinted in The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 1: The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1999.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1983. The achievement and the limits of public choice in diagnosing government failure and in offering bases for constructive reform. In Anatomy of Government Deficiencies, ed. Hanusch, H., 1525. Berlin: Springer.10.1007/978-3-662-21610-1_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1986a. The constitution of economic policy. James M. Buchanan Jr. Prize Lecture. Lanham, MD: NobelPrize.org. Nobel Media AB. 8 December 1986. https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/economic-sciences/1986/buchanan/lecture/.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1987. The constitution of economic policy. American Economic Review 77, 243250.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1986b. Then and now, 1961–1986: from delusion to dystopia. Paper presented at the Institute for Humane Studies, 11–12.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 1993. How can constitutions be designed so that politicians who seek to serve “Public Interest” can survive and prosper? Constitutional Political Economy 4, 16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. 2005. Why I, too, am Not a Conservative: The Normative Vision of Classical Liberalism. Northampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Congleton, R. 1998. Politics by Principle, Not Interest. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511664816CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Tullock, G. 1962. The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Celis, K. and Childs, S. 2018. Good representatives and good representation. PS: Political Science & Politics 51, 314317.Google Scholar
Clark, D. 2019. ‘Dangerous.’ ‘abuse.’ ‘lawless’: bipartisan attack on Trump national emergency declaration. NBC News, 14 February 2019. https://www.nbcnews.com/politics/congress/dangerous-abuse-lawless-bipartisan-attack-trump-national-emergency-declaration-n971826.Google Scholar
Congleton, R. 2018. Toward a rule-based model of human choice: on the nature of Homo Constitutionalus . In James M. Buchanan: A Theorist of Political Economy and Social Philosophy, ed. Wagner, R.E., 11051129. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Costa, R. and Rucker, P. 2019. ‘It feels like a horror movie’: Republicans feel anxious and adrift defending Trump. The Washington Post, 28 October 2019. https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/it-feels-like-a-horror-movie-republicans-feel-anxious-and-adrift-defending-trump/2019/10/28/b4510698-f75f-11e9-a285-882a8e386a96_story.html.Google Scholar
Cox, G.W. and McCubbins, M.D. 2005. Setting the Agenda: Responsible Party Government in the U.S. House of Representatives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Lara, Y.G., Greif, A. and Jha, S. 2008. The administrative foundations of self-enforcing constitutions. American Economic Review 98, 105109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dovi, S.L. 2007. The Good Representative. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisen, N. 2019. The Democracy Playbook: Preventing and Reversing Democratic Backsliding. Governance Studies at the Brookings Institution.Google Scholar
Frey, B.S. 1997. A constitution for knaves crowds out civic virtues. Economic Journal 107, 10431053.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. 2018. It can’t be rational choice all the way down. In Buchanan’s Tensions: Reexamining the Political Economy and Philosophy of James M. Buchanan, eds Boettke, P. and Stein, S., 117145. Arlington, VA: Mercatus Center.Google Scholar
Hayek, F.A. 1944. The Road to Serfdom. The Collected Works of F.A. Hayek, Volume II, ed. Caldwell, B.. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, reprinted 2007.Google Scholar
Kelman, S. 1987. “Public choice” and public spirit. Public Interest 87, 8094.Google Scholar
Kirchgässner, G. 2014. The role of homo oeconomicus in the political economy of James Buchanan. Constitutional Political Economy 25, 217.10.1007/s10602-014-9157-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kogelmann, B. 2015. Modeling the individual for constitutional choice. Constitutional Political Economy 26, 455474.10.1007/s10602-015-9197-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, F.E. 2016. Insecure Majorities. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226409184.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leeson, P. and Subrick, J.R. 2006. Robust political economy. Review of Austrian Economics 19, 107111.10.1007/s11138-006-7342-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levitsky, S. and Ziblatt, D. 2018. How Democracies Die. New York, NY: Crown.Google Scholar
Mansbridge, J. 2014. A contingency theory of accountability. In The Oxford Handbook of Public Accountability, 5566. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayhew, D.R. 1974. Congress: The Electoral Connection. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Muirhead, R. 2014. The Promise of Party in a Polarized Age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munger, M. 2018. 30 years after the Nobel: James Buchanan’s political philosophy. Review of Austrian Economics 31, 151167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Munger, M. 2020. Moral community and moral order: Buchanan’s theory of obligation. Public Choice 183, 509521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ostrom, V. 2000. The Meaning of Democracy and the Vulnerability of Democracies. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Rohde, D.W. 1991. Parties and Leaders in the Postreform House. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabl, A. 2002. Ruling Passions: Political Offices and Democratic Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Severs, E. and Dovi, S. 2018. Why we need to return to the ethics of political representation. PS: Political Science & Politics 51, 309313.Google Scholar
Tillis, T. 2019. I support Trump’s vision on border security. But I would vote against the emergency. The Washington Post, 25 February 2019. https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2019/02/25/i-support-trumps-vision-border-security-i-would-vote-against-emergency/.Google Scholar
Tullock, G. 1984. A (partial) rehabilitation of the public interest theory. Public Choice 42, 8999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
United States Senate n.d. Oath of Office. Accessed 8 March 2020. https://www.senate.gov/artandhistory/history/common/briefing/Oath_Office.htm.Google Scholar
Vanberg, V. and Buchanan, J.M. 1988. Rational choice and moral order. Analyse und Kritik 10, 138160.10.1515/auk-1988-0202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weingast, B. 2005. The constitutional dilemma of economic liberty. Journal of Economic Perspectives 19, 89108.10.1257/089533005774357815CrossRefGoogle Scholar