Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T05:14:21.227Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“The Most Common Sickness of Our Time”: Tocqueville on Democratic Restlessness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2018

Abstract

In volume 1 of Democracy in America, Tocqueville argues that the energy unleashed by democracy is one of democracy's greatest benefits. In volume 2, his portrait of democracy turns darker, and he recasts the dynamism of American society as an expression of an underlying restlessness. In this paper, I argue that restlessness (inquiétude) is a key element of Tocqueville's mature view of democratic man. Whereas previous scholarship on Tocqueville's view of restlessness either treats the theme instrumentally, by subordinating it to other themes, or seeks to illuminate Tocqueville's debt to other thinkers, this paper examines Tocqueville's treatment of restlessness as an important theme in its own right. Treating this theme in full requires examining his discussions of materialism, envy, democratic morality, and democratic peoples’ experiences of literature and art. Through this examination we see how, in Tocqueville's view, democracy, for all its merits, obstructs the path to human happiness.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Jech, Alexander, “‘Man Simply’: Excavating Tocqueville's Conception of Human Nature,” Perspectives on Political Science 42 (2013): 8493CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kitch, Sarah Beth V., “The Immovable Foundations of the Infinite and Immortal: Tocqueville's Philosophical Anthropology,” American Journal of Political Science 60 (2016): 947–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zuckert, Catherine H., “Tocqueville's “New Political Science,’” in Tocqueville's Voyages: The Evolution of His Ideas and Their Journey Beyond His Time, ed. Henderson, Christine Dunn (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2014), 142–76Google Scholar.

2 Henary, Sara, “Tocqueville and the Challenge of Historicism,” Review of Politics 76 (2014): 469–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cooper, Laurence D., “Every Man a Socrates? Tocqueville and the Conceit of Modernity,” American Political Thought 1 (2012): 208–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Harvey C. Mansfield, “Intimations of Philosophy in Tocqueville's Democracy in America,” in Henderson, Tocqueville's Voyages, 202–41.

3 For an excellent elaboration of Tocqueville's own self-understanding in relation to philosophy, see Lawler, Peter Augustine, The Restless Mind: Alexis de Tocqueville on the Origin and Perpetuation of Human Liberty (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1993), 89108Google Scholar.

4 Tocqueville to Kergorlay, October 1847, in Selected Letters on Politics and Society, ed. Roger Boesche (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1985), 191. Hereafter SL.

5 de Tocqueville, Alexis, Democracy in America, trans. Goldhammer, Arthur (New York: Library of America Press, 2004)Google Scholar, Introduction, 15, 17. Hereafter DA.

6 DA, 1.2.6, 278.

7 Schleifer, James T., The Making of Tocqueville's “Democracy in America” (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2000), 349Google Scholar.

8 Tocqueville to Sophie Swetchine, February 1857, in SL, 348–49.

9 See Lawler, Restless Mind, 73–87; Jech, Alexander, “Tocqueville, Pascal, and the Transcendent Horizon,” American Political Thought 5 (2016): 109–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McLendon, Michael Locke, “Tocqueville, Jansenism, and the Psychology of Human Freedom,” American Journal of Political Science 50 (2006): 664–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mansfield, Harvey C., Tocqueville: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 53CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Alan Kahan, “Democratic Grandeur: How Tocqueville Constructed His New Moral Science in America,” in Henderson, Tocqueville's Voyages, 177–201.

10 Pascal, Blaise, Pensées, ed. Ariew, Roger (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2004), 38Google Scholar.

11 Ibid., 40.

12 Ibid., 45.

13 “Correspondance d'Alexis de Tocqueville et de Louis de Kergorlay,” in Œuvres complètes, vol. 13, ed. André Jardin and Jean-Alain Lesourd (Paris: Gallimard, 1977), 418.

14 Herold, Aaron L., “Tocqueville on Religion, Enlightenment, and the Democratic Soul,” American Political Science Review 109 (2015): 523–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kitch, “Immovable Foundations,” 947–57; Jech, “Tocqueville, Pascal, and the Transcendent Horizon,” 109–31.

15 Jaume, Lucien, Tocqueville: The Aristocratic Sources of Liberty, trans. Goldhammer, Arthur (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013), 161CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16 Cf. McLendon, “Tocqueville, Jansenism, and the Psychology of Human Freedom,” 669.

17 For more on the differences between Pascal and Tocqueville, see Kahan, “Democratic Grandeur,” 186–90; Jech, “Tocqueville, Pascal, and the Transcendent Horizon,” 119–21.

18 Another thinker who influenced Tocqueville's views on restlessness was Montesquieu. For an excellent exploration of the role of restlessness in Montesquieu's thought, and how it influenced Tocqueville, see Rahe, Paul A., Soft Despotism, Democracy's Drift: Montesquieu, Rousseau, Tocqueville, and the Modern Prospect (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2009), esp. 3259Google Scholar and 156–85.

19 Manent, Pierre considers restlessness in the course of examining the relationship between nature and democracy in Tocqueville and the Nature of Democracy, trans. Waggoner, John (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1996), 5562Google Scholar. Lawler treats it in connection with a broader meditation on Tocqueville's relationship to Pascal (Restless Mind, 36–44); and Rahe considers Tocqueville's view of restlessness with a view to its political implications, especially the threat of soft despotism (Soft Despotism, Democracy's Drift, 168–85). Herold and Kitch focus on its relation to religion; see Herold, “Tocqueville on Religion, Enlightenment, and the Democratic Soul,” 527–29; Kitch, “Immovable Foundations,” 951–52.

20 Schleifer, Making of “Democracy in America, 354–68; Mansfield, “Intimations of Philosophy,” 231–32; Lamberti, Jean-Claude, Tocqueville and the Two Democracies (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar; Drescher, Seymour, “Tocqueville's Two Démocraties,” Journal of the History of Ideas 25 (1964): 201–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Remarkably, parties to this debate have taken little notice of the change in his presentation of restlessness, save one brief allusion to it by Drescher, in “Two Démocraties,” 211.

21 DA, vol. 2, Preface, 479–80. See also Rahe, Soft Despotism, Democracy's Drift, 153.

22 Schleifer, Making of “Democracy in America, 37.

23 DA, vol. 2, Preface, 480.

24 Brogan, Hugh, Alexis de Tocqueville: A Life (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006), 344Google Scholar.

25 Pierson, George Wilson, Tocqueville in America (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1996), 118Google Scholar.

26 Pierson, Tocqueville in America, 118–19.

27 Schleifer, Making of “Democracy in America, 56.

28 A visit to French Canada, where the physical landscape was so similar to America's, and yet the mores so different, disabused him of the theory that the physical landscape was the primary determinant of national character. See Siedentop, Larry, Tocqueville (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), 5455Google Scholar.

29 DA,1.2.9, 328.

30 Schleifer, Making of “Democracy in America, 52.

31 Ibid., 53.

32 DA, 1.2.6, 278.

33 Tocqueville, Alexis de, “Political Activity in America,” in Democracy in America: Historical-Critical Edition of “De la démocratie en Amérique,” ed. Nolla, Eduardo (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2010), 4:1367CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Hereafter DLDA.

34 DA, 1.1.5, 103–4.

35 DA, 1.2.6, 277.

36 DA, 1.2.10, 466.

37 Lawler, Restless Mind, 40. See also the assessment of Mansfield and Winthrop: “Restiveness (inquiétude) is for [Tocqueville] the normal, and perhaps the highest, condition of the human soul” (de Tocqueville, Alexis, Democracy in America, ed. Mansfield, Harvey C. and Winthrop, Delba [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000], xxivCrossRefGoogle Scholar).

38 DA, 2.1.10, 523.

39 Ibid., 524.

40 DA, 2.2.13, 625–26.

41 Cf. Deneen, Patrick J., Democratic Faith (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), 222Google Scholar.

42 DA, 2.2.10, 617. On this point, see also Rahe, Soft Despotism, Democracy's Drift, 142.

43 DA, 2.3.17, 722–23.

44 DA, 2.3.13, 626.

45 Ibid.; see also Herold, “Tocqueville on Religion, Enlightenment, and the Democratic Soul,” 528.

46 Lawler reads Tocqueville to be expressing a strong preference for “restless materialism” over “a kind of decent materialism” that he feared might arise (Restless Mind, 41). But Tocqueville himself never suggests that “restless” materialism is better than “decent” materialism. Indeed, he does not distinguish between the two. American materialism, according to Tocqueville, is both restless and decent.

47 DA, 2.2.11, 621.

48 DA, 2.2.15, 635.

49 Ibid.

50 DA, 2.1.5, 503.

51 Kitch, “Immovable Foundations,” 951. “If I had to class the human miseries, I should put them in this order: 1. Illnesses. 2. Death. 3. Doubt” (Tocqueville's notebooks, October 14th, 1831, in The Tocqueville Reader: A Life in Letters and Politics, ed. Olivier Zunz and Alan S. Kahan [Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2002], 53).

52 Pascal, Pensées, 18.

53 DA, 2.2.12, 623.

54 DLDA, 3:935–36.

55 DA, 2.1.11, 530; DLDA, 3:935; Schleifer, Making of “Democracy in America, 55.

56 DA, 2.4.3, 794.

57 DA, 2.3.15, 717.

58 DA, 2.2.18, 642–43.

59 DA, 1.2.9, 359.

60 DA, 2.2.13, 627.

61 “In an aristocratic society a kind of serenity and even gaiety can be traced to people knowing exactly who they are. They are not subject to the torments of unsatisfied ambition” (Siedentop, Tocqueville, 76).

62 Manent, Tocqueville and the Nature of Democracy, 63.

63 DA, 2.2.13, 627.

64 DA, 2.2.20, 650–51.

65 DA, 2.2.13, 627.

66 DA, 2.3.16, 721.

67 Ibid., 720.

68 Œuvres complètes, 418.

69 de Tocqueville, Alexis, Memoir On Pauperism, trans. Drescher, Seymour (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 1997), 45, 49Google Scholar.

70 Ibid., 45.

71 Ibid., 48.

72 DA, 2.2.4, 593.

73 DA, 1.2.6, 277. Peter Lawler reads Tocqueville's account as quite dark: “Human beings, as they progress, become more powerful and knowledgeable, more anxious and dissatisfied, and, on the whole, more miserable” (Lawler, Peter, “The Human Condition: Tocqueville's Debt to Rousseau and Pascal,” in Liberty, Equality, Democracy, ed. Nolla, Eduardo [New York: New York University Press, 1992], 11Google Scholar). Tocqueville himself does not use such a strong tone.

74 DA, 1.2.6, 279; 2.2.5, 595–96.

75 DLDA, 4:1367.

76 DA, 2.2.13, 626.

77 DA, 1.2.6, 279.

78 DA, 1.2.10, 453.

79 DA, 1.2.2, 201–3; 2.2.14, 630–32; 2.3.21, 749–51.

80 Tocqueville Reader, 51. See also Danoff, Brian, Educating Democracy: Alexis de Tocqueville and Leadership in America (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2010), 17Google Scholar; Krause, Sharon R., Liberalism with Honor (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2002), 7882Google Scholar.

81 Kahan, “Democratic Grandeur,” 180.

82 Antoine, Agnès, “Democracy and Religion: Some Tocquevillian Perspectives,” in Reading Tocqueville: From Oracle to Actor, ed. Geenens, Raf and De Dijn, Annelien (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007), 137Google Scholar; Danoff, Educating Democracy, 16–18.

83 DA, 2.2.8, 611.

84 DA, 2.2.9, 614. Cf. McLendon, “Tocqueville, Jansenism, and the Psychology of Human Freedom,” 673: “Americans, [Tocqueville] thought, were at bottom creatures of vice.”

85 DA, 2.3.24, 775.

86 DA, 2.3.21, 750.

87 DA, 1.2.10, 464.

88 Wettergreen, John Adams, “Modern Commerce,” in Interpreting Tocqueville's “Democracy in America,” ed. Masugi, Ken (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991), 217Google Scholar.

89 Manent argues that the heroism of commerce stems principally from the experience of envy (Tocqueville and the Nature of Democracy, 61). But Tocqueville does not connect the two things. Rather, he argues that the American who shows heroism in commerce is “obeying the dictates of his nature” (DA 1.2.10, 465); cf. Avramenko, Richard, Courage: The Politics of Life and Limb (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011), 211–15Google Scholar.

90 DA, 2.3.8, 688–90.

91 DA, 1.2.9, 336–37.

92 DA, 2.3.10, 696.

93 Ibid., 697.

94 DA, 1.1.3, 59.

95 DA, 2.2.19, 645.

96 On the surprising affinity between Tocqueville and Marx on the modern democratic experience of leisure, see Pangle, Thomas L., “The Twofold Challenge for Democratic Culture in Our Time,” in Alexis de Tocqueville and the Art of Democratic Statesmanship, ed. Danoff, Brian and Hebert, L. Joseph Jr. (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2011), 331Google Scholar.

97 DA, 2.2.13, 626.

98 DA, 2.3.15, 718.

99 DA, 2.1.17, 557.

100 DA, 2.1.13, 542.

101 DA, 2.1.19, 566.

102 DA, 2.1.17, 558.

103 DA, 2.1.13, 542.

104 DA, 2.1.2, 490.

105 SL, 154.

106 DA, 1.2.9, 344.

107 de Tocqueville, Alexis, Souvenirs, in Œuvres complètes, vol. 12, ed. Monnier, Luc (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), 171Google Scholar.

108 DA, 2.2.13, 627.

109 DA, 1.2.9, 342.

110 SL, 63.

111 SL, 93.

112 de Tocqueville, Alexis, Alexis de Tocqueville and Gustave de Beaumont: Their Friendship and Their Travels, ed. Zunz, Olivier and Goldhammer, Arthur (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 2010), 603Google Scholar.

113 Ibid., 612.