Systems biology and the integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2013.06.002Get rights and content

Highlights

  • Discusses the integration of mechanistic and mathematical styles of explanation.

  • Analyzes several case studies from systems biology.

  • Presents qualitative phenomena whose explanation requires a quantitative account.

  • Draws conclusions for a broader ontological conception of mechanisms.

Abstract

The paper discusses how systems biology is working toward complex accounts that integrate explanation in terms of mechanisms and explanation by mathematical models—which some philosophers have viewed as rival models of explanation. Systems biology is an integrative approach, and it strongly relies on mathematical modeling. Philosophical accounts of mechanisms capture integrative in the sense of multilevel and multifield explanations, yet accounts of mechanistic explanation (as the analysis of a whole in terms of its structural parts and their qualitative interactions) have failed to address how a mathematical model could contribute to such explanations. I discuss how mathematical equations can be explanatorily relevant. Several cases from systems biology are discussed to illustrate the interplay between mechanistic research and mathematical modeling, and I point to questions about qualitative phenomena (rather than the explanation of quantitative details), where quantitative models are still indispensable to the explanation. Systems biology shows that a broader philosophical conception of mechanisms is needed, which takes into account functional-dynamical aspects, interaction in complex networks with feedback loops, system-wide functional properties such as distributed functionality and robustness, and a mechanism’s ability to respond to perturbations (beyond its actual operation). I offer general conclusions for philosophical accounts of explanation.

Introduction

Current philosophical accounts of integration and integrative explanations can be seen as a philosophical alternative to reduction and reductive explanation (Brigandt, 2013a, Brigandt and Love, 2010, Brigandt and Love, 2012b, Plutynski, 2013). By assuming that the knowledge from several fields can be logically deduced from a more fundamental (lower-level) theory, the model of theory reduction proved unable to capture the complex relations among biological ideas. Initial accounts of integration conceptualized the non-reductive yet systematic relations among fields as being provided by particular theories (so called interfield theories; Darden and Maull, 1977, Maull, 1977), but nowadays broader accounts are available, which do not require theories to be central epistemic units for all of biology (Brigandt, 2010, Leonelli, 2013, O’Malley, 2013). One approach is to use the notion of a mechanism, which is currently popular in philosophy of science (Craver and Darden, 2005, Glennan et al., 2002, Machamer et al., 2000).

For various branches of experimental biology, including molecular biology, cell biology, and neuroscience, accounts of mechanistic explanation have proven fruitful, among other things because they are able to articulate the nature of multifield, multilevel explanations—as opposed to purely reductive explanations—given that different disciplines can contribute to the elucidation of a mechanism and mechanisms involve the interaction of entities on several levels of organization (Bechtel, 2006, Craver, 2007, Darden, 2005). Moreover, mechanisms are discovered in a piecemeal fashion, and mechanistic research may alternate between downward, reductive episodes and upward, integrative episodes (Bechtel, 2010, Bechtel, 2013, Craver, 2005). As a result, such philosophical accounts pay attention to discovery and the change of knowledge and research strategies and thereby address not only the product of science (e.g., a finished explanation) but also the practice and dynamic process of science (Brigandt, 2013a, Brigandt, 2013b, Gerson, 2013, Griesemer, 2013).

Systems biology is nowadays thriving, and it is clearly an integrative and interdisciplinary approach. It attempts to explain complex biological systems using a variety of conceptual and experimental resources. The focus is on system-wide behavior rather than the properties of a few isolated components or causal pathways of a system. Due to the availability of information about a plethora of molecular and cellular entities provided by functional genomics, proteomics, and metabolomics projects, systems biology nowadays has a clear molecular-mechanistic face. At the same time, the characteristic feature of systems biology is its reliance on mathematical models (Wolkenhauer & Muir, 2011). This may be at odds with philosophers’ conceptualization of mechanistic explanation as the explanation of a whole in terms of its physical parts, including the spatial organization of and qualitative interactions among parts. Philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation have usually been silent about how a mathematical model could contribute to an explanation at all; in fact, causal-mechanistic accounts have been developed as an alternative to traditional models of explanation as derivation from quantitatively formulated laws (Brigandt, 2013a, Craver, 2007). Yet systems biology does appear to explain using equations and quantitative models (Baetu, in press, Fagan, 2012).

In this paper, I argue that among its many other integrative aspects, systems biology is working toward an integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation, i.e., a kind of explanation that includes both reference to spatial parts and mathematical equations. This calls for a broader philosophical conception of what a mechanistic explanation is. My thesis is in line with Bill Bechtel’s and Adele Abrahamsen’s notion of ‘dynamic mechanistic explanation’ (Bechtel, 2011, Bechtel, 2012, Bechtel, 2013, Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 2010, Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 2011), but will go beyond previous accounts in two ways. First, given that mechanists such as Carl Craver (2007) have highlighted the difference between merely modeling and explaining a phenomenon, rather than just indicating that mathematical modeling plays some epistemic role, I specifically argue that mathematical models are indispensable ingredients of some explanations in molecular biology. In fact, while it is trivial that a mathematical representation is needed when accounting for the quantitative aspects or precise temporal dynamics of a system, I will point to several qualitative phenomena to be explained where a quantitative explanation is still required. Second, beyond the example of circadian rhythms discussed by Bechtel and Abrahamsen, I address systems biology as a larger domain and survey several cases that illustrate why equations can be explanatorily indispensable.

The following section gives a brief overview of systems biology. Section 3 provides a general account of how mathematical equations can have explanatorily relevance, but also of when a mathematical model can omit mechanistic detail and still be explanatory. Section 4 surveys several cases from systems biology that illustrate both that its mathematical models are developed and tested based on molecular-mechanistic information, and that there are qualitative explananda necessitating a quantitative explanation. In addition to drawing implications for philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation and explanation in general, the concluding section will also use the case studies to call for a broader ontological conception of mechanisms.

Section snippets

Systems biology

Systems biology is not so much a (single) field, but may better be described as an (interdisciplinary) approach. For systems biology studies a variety of phenomena from different domains, including biochemical systems (e.g., enzyme activity regulation and flux in metabolic pathways), cellular processes (e.g., gene regulation, protein transport, signaling pathways, the cell cycle, and apoptosis), cell–cell interaction such as cell–cell signaling, as well as cell differentiation and organismal

No dichotomy between mechanistic explanations and mathematical models

Philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation have been developed as an alternative to the traditional idea of scientific explanation as the derivation from laws, e.g., the deductive-nomological model (Brigandt, 2013a). In molecular biology and related areas, there are hardly laws, and instead research consists in the discovery of mechanisms, i.e., the breaking of a whole into its concrete structural parts (Bechtel & Richardson, 1993). Rather than being able to logically deduce an

Cases from systems biology: qualitative explananda requiring equations

I now present several case studies that illustrate the interplay of mechanistic explanation and mathematical modeling in systems biology. Apart from showing that such mathematical models are based on experimental data about molecular mechanisms and that they are causal by often capturing the effects of interventions internal to the system, some of the cases indicate that models in systems biology combine several levels of organization. While it is quite trivial that a quantitative explanandum

Toward a broader conception of mechanisms and explanation

Apart from illustrating how models in systems biology are developed based on and tested by molecular-mechanistic data, my case studies have focused on the explanatory relevance of mathematical models. Before returning to this and offering more general philosophical remarks on explanation, I extract points from the cases that mandate a broader philosophical conception of mechanisms. These may well be features that philosophers would not object to (and that biologists naturally take to be aspects

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Bill Bechtel, Arnon Levy, Maureen O’Malley, and an anonymous referee for detailed comments on previous versions of this paper. Fig. 1, Fig. 2 are reprinted from Eissing et al. (2004) with the permission of the copyright holder, the American Society for Biochemistry and Molecular Biology. Fig. 3 is reprinted from Salazar-Ciudad and Jernvall (2002) with the permission of the copyright holder, the National Academy of Sciences, USA. Fig. 4 is reprinted from Meinhardt (2009) with

References (167)

  • C.F. Craver

    Beyond reduction: Mechanisms, multifield integration and the unity of neuroscience

    Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2005)
  • J.W. Crawford et al.

    Towards an evolutionary ecology of life in soil

    Trends in Ecology and Evolution

    (2005)
  • L. Darden

    Relations among fields: Mendelian, cytological and molecular mechanisms

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2005)
  • J.S. Edwards et al.

    Systems properties of the Haemophilus influenzae Rd metabolic genotype

    Journal of Biological Chemistry

    (1999)
  • T. Eissing et al.

    Bistability analyses of a caspase activation model for receptor-induced apoptosis

    Journal of Biological Chemistry

    (2004)
  • D.A. Fell

    How can we understand metabolism?

  • J.E. Ferrell et al.

    Modeling the cell cycle: Why do certain circuits oscillate?

    Cell

    (2011)
  • A. Goldbeter et al.

    Modeling the segmentation clock as a network of coupled oscillations in the Notch, Wnt and FGF signaling pathways

    Journal of Theoretical Biology

    (2008)
  • S. Green

    When one model is not enough: Combining epistemic tools in systems biology

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2013)
  • S.F. Greenbury et al.

    The effect of scale-free topology on the robustness and evolvability of genetic regulatory networks

    Journal of Theoretical Biology

    (2010)
  • J. Griesemer

    Integration of approaches in David Wake’s model-taxon research platform for evolutionary morphology

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences.

    (2013)
  • L. Herrgen et al.

    Intercellular coupling regulates the period of the segmentation clock

    Current Biology

    (2010)
  • C. Jørgensen et al.

    Simplistic pathways or complex networks?

    Current Opinion in Genetics & Development

    (2010)
  • J.R. Karr et al.

    A whole-cell computational model predicts phenotype from genotype

    Cell

    (2012)
  • U. Krohs et al.

    Data without models merging with models without data

  • S. Leonelli

    Integrating data to acquire new knowledge: Three modes of integration in plant science

    Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences

    (2013)
  • H.E. Abud

    Shaping developing tissues by apoptosis

    Cell Death & Differentiation

    (2004)
  • U. Alon

    An introduction to systems biology: Design principles of biological circuits

    (2007)
  • T. Baetu

    From mechanisms to mathematical models and back to mechanisms: Quantitative mechanistic explanations

  • J.E. Baggs et al.

    Network features of the mammalian circadian clock

    PLoS Biology

    (2009)
  • R.E. Baker et al.

    How can mathematics help us explore vertebrate segmentation?

    HFSP Journal

    (2009)
  • A.-L. Barabási et al.

    Network biology: Understanding the cell’s functional organization

    Nature Reviews Genetics

    (2004)
  • A.-L. Barabási et al.

    Network medicine: A network-based approach to human disease

    Nature Reviews Genetics

    (2011)
  • M. Barberis et al.

    Cell size at S phase initiation: An emergent property of the G1/S network

    PLoS Computational Biology

    (2007)
  • W. Bechtel

    Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology

    (2006)
  • W. Bechtel

    The downs and ups of mechanistic research: Circadian rhythm research as an exemplar

    Erkenntnis

    (2010)
  • W. Bechtel

    Mechanism and biological explanation

    Philosophy of Science

    (2011)
  • W. Bechtel

    Understanding endogenously active mechanisms: A scientific and philosophical challenge

    European Journal for Philosophy of Science

    (2012)
  • W. Bechtel et al.

    Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research

    (1993)
  • M.J. Behe

    Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution

    (1996)
  • U.S. Bhalla et al.

    Emergent properties of networks of biological signaling pathways

    Science

    (1999)
  • F.C. Boogerd et al.

    Emergence and its place in nature: A case study of biochemical networks

    Synthese

    (2005)
  • I. Brigandt

    Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology

    Erkenntnis

    (2010)
  • I. Brigandt

    Explanation in biology: Reduction, pluralism, and explanatory aims

    Science & Education

    (2013)
  • I. Brigandt

    Intelligent design and the nature of science: Philosophical and pedagogical points

  • I. Brigandt

    Evolutionary developmental biology and the limits of philosophical accounts of mechanistic explanation

  • I. Brigandt et al.

    Evolutionary novelty and the evo-devo synthesis: Field notes

    Evolutionary Biology

    (2010)
  • I. Brigandt et al.

    Conceptualizing evolutionary novelty: Moving beyond definitional debates

    Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution

    (2012)
  • Brigandt, I., & Love, A. C. (2012b). Reductionism in biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of...
  • Cited by (77)

    • Mathematical modelling of follicular growth and ovarian stimulation

      2022, Current Opinion in Endocrine and Metabolic Research
    • Organization needs organization: Understanding integrated control in living organisms

      2022, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science
      Citation Excerpt :

      For example, in the citric acid cycle, the product of a sequence of reactions is fed back as an input to a reaction at the beginning of the sequence. Since it is hard to keep track of such non-sequential interactions mentally so as to determine the phenomenon they will produce, Brigandt (2013) and Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2013) discuss how researchers often rely on computational modeling in their reconstructions of mechanisms. Such modeling often reveals how the mechanisms generate complex dynamical behavior.

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text