Trends in Cognitive Sciences
Volume 6, Issue 8, 1 August 2002, Pages 339-344
Journal home page for Trends in Cognitive Sciences

Opinion
Re-representing consciousness: dissociations between experience and meta-consciousness

https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(02)01949-6Get rights and content

Abstract

A distinction is drawn between non-conscious (unexperienced), conscious (experienced), and meta-conscious (re-represented) mental processes. There is evidence for two types of dissociations between consciousness and meta-consciousness, the latter being defined as the intermittent explicit re-representation of the contents of consciousness. Temporal dissociations occur when an individual, who previously lacked meta-consciousness about the contents of consciousness, directs meta-consciousness towards those contents; for example, catching one's mind wandering during reading. Once meta-consciousness is triggered, translation dissociations can occur if the re-representation process misrepresents the original experience, such as when one verbally reflects on non-verbal experiences or takes stock of subtle or ambiguous experiences.

Section snippets

Dissociations between consciousness and meta-consciousness

Although it generally seems that we are aware of the contents of experience, various situations illustrate dissociations between having an experience and knowing that one is having that experience. Such dissociations are exemplified by the situation of suddenly realizing that your mind has wandered while reading. Although the contents of such mind-wandering episodes are certainly experienced, the explicit awareness that your mind has wandered appears temporarily absent, as evidenced by the

The relationship between non-conscious, conscious, and meta-conscious processes

Conscious and non-conscious cognitive activities occur continuously throughout our waking hours. Much of the monitoring of consciousness is carried out by non-conscious processes that track goals [8], select strategies [9], and modulate the contents of thought [10]. Periodically attention is directed towards explicitly assessing the contents of experience. The resulting meta-consciousness involves an explicit re-representation of consciousness in which one interprets, describes, or otherwise

Temporal dissociations

Temporal dissociations between consciousness and meta-consciousness are illustrated by cases in which the triggering of meta-consciousness causes one to assess aspects of experience that had previously eluded explicit appraisal.

Translation dissociations

If meta-consciousness requires re-representing the contents of consciousness, then, as with any recoding process, some information could get lost or become distorted in the translation. The likelihood of noise entering the translation process is particularly great when individuals (1) verbally reflect on inherently non-verbal experiences, and/or (2) assess ambiguous or subtle visceral signals.

Caveats and conclusions

Positing temporal and translation dissociations between experience and meta-consciousness can provide new perspectives on many phenomena. Nevertheless, at least some of the phenomena discussed here can, in principle, be explained without invoking meta-consciousness. For example, zoning-out during reading might occur because individuals forget the goal of understanding what they are reading. And subliminal priming of negative affect could alter the motivation to engage in mood repair rather than

Questions for future research

  • What is the relationship between language and meta-consciousness? Does meta-consciousness need to be verbal or in some symbolic form?

  • When are individuals completely unaware of the contents of their experience? Can experience sampling combined with self-reporting determine when individuals are most or least likely to be meta-conscious?

  • What situations prompt the induction of meta-consciousness? Is meta-consciousness cue-dependent or is there an inherent intermittent monitoring process?

  • Can people

Acknowledgements

The writing and research reported in this article was supported by a grant from the Fetzer Institute, through the Center for Consciousness Studies at the University of Arizona. The author wishes to thank Sonya Dougal, David Halpern, Erik Reichle, Charles Schreiber, Carmi Schooler, Lael Schooler and Nina Schooler for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this manuscript. This paper also benefited from extensive conversations with Daniel Gilbert, Timothy Wilson, and Daniel Wegner.

References (54)

  • A.I. Jack et al.

    Introspective physicalism as an approach to the science of consciousness

    Cognition

    (2001)
  • G.W. Farthing

    The Psychology of Consciousness

    (1992)
  • T.L. Kahan et al.

    Lucid dreaming as metacognition: implications for cognitive science

    Conscious. Cogn.

    (1994)
  • N. Block

    Paradox and cross purposes in recent work on consciousness

    Cognition

    (2001)
  • A.J. Marcel

    Slippage in the unity of consciousness

  • J.A. Bargh

    The automaticity of everyday life

  • L.M. Reder et al.

    Metacognition does not imply awareness: strategy choice is governed by implicit learning and memory

  • D.M. Wegner

    Ironic processes of mental control

    Psychol. Rev.

    (1994)
  • L.M. Giambra

    A laboratory method for investigating influences on switching attention to task-unrelated imagery and thought

    Conscious. Cogn.

    (1995)
  • A. Grodsky et al.

    The consistency across vigilance and reading tasks of individual differences in the occurrence of task-unrelated and task-related images and thoughts

    Imaging Cogn. Pers.

    (1990)
  • Schooler, J.W. et al. (in press) Zoning-out during reading: evidence for dissociations between experience and...
  • P.C. Cicogna et al.

    Consciousness during dreams

    Conscious. Cogn.

    (2001)
  • J. Tzelgov

    Automatic but conscious: that is how we act most of the time

    Am. Psychol.

    (1999)
  • J.F. Kihlstrom

    Hypnosis

    Annu. Rev. Psychol.

    (1985)
  • D. Spiegel et al.

    Disintegrated experience: the dissociative disorders revisited

    J. Abnorm. Psychol.

    (1991)
  • M. Csikszentmihalyi

    Flow: The Psychology of Optimal Experience

    (1990)
  • H. Moskowitz et al.

    Effects of marijuana on auditory signal detection

    Psychopharmacologia

    (1974)
  • Cited by (0)

    View full text