Skip to main content
Log in

Accentuate the Negative

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Our interest in this paper is to drive a wedge of contention between two different programs that fall under the umbrella of “experimental philosophy”. In particular, we argue that experimental philosophy’s “negative program” presents almost as significant a challenge to its “positive program” as it does to more traditional analytic philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, we will take as our target philosophical intuitions as they are standardly conceived of in current practice. According to this conception, philosophical intuitions are propositional attitudes generated in response to hypothetical cases in philosophy which are “minimally foundational” (a person may appeal to them as evidence without having to provide evidence for them), non-inferential, and fallible. We also think that most of these arguments will go through mutatis mutandis for other conceptions of such judgments and their place in philosophical methodology (see, for example, Williamson 2004, 2005, 2007; Alexander and Weinberg 2007).

  2. The terms “negative” program and “positive” program are now in common use. We are unsure of their origin though they may have been introduced by Farid Masrour.

  3. For additional discussions of experimental philosophy’s positive and negative programs, see Alexander and Weinberg (2007); Kauppinen (2007); Nadelhoffer and Nahmias (2007); and Weinberg (2007).

  4. One notable exception is the recent work of Stotz and Griffiths (2004). They document the varying intuitions of specialist populations regarding the concept of the gene, and they have a good reason for restricting their populations of interest. Moreover, there are a number of interesting examples of experimental philosophy that do not particularly concern intuitions (see, e.g., Nichols 2002, Schwitzgebel in press), and that our arguments do not target.

  5. See Nadelhoffer and Nahmias (2007) for an earlier but different elucidation of forms of positive experimental philosophy.

  6. Perhaps some form of relativism or contextualism could be attempted. Different relativizations might have different degrees of plausibility (for example, see Glasgow 2008 on relativism and the concept of race). While such moves may be appropriate in some instances, we suspect that they will not prove generally attractive. For a discussion of why epistemic contextualism might not be particularly helpful, see Swain et al. 2008. For a discussion of relativizing intuitions about reference, see Mallon et al. 2009.

  7. See, e.g., Johnson (2008). Note though that lexical semanticists might offer some resources that philosophers would find useful if the factivity of “knows” or other epistemologically-interested verbs was under discussion.

  8. In addition to its original home in linguistics, the distinction has also done important work in other parts of cognitive science, e.g., in the developmental folk psychology literature (Surian and Leslie 1999; Bloom and German 2000; Scholl and Leslie 2003).

  9. It also presupposes at a minimum that it will be possible to decompose the relevant cognition into mechanisms with individually discernible functions. We note this commitment without taking issue with it here.

  10. To our knowledge, no one has explored “physical breakdown” as a candidate source of performance errors in positive experimental philosophy.

  11. We grant here, for the sake of discussion, that they have correctly characterized the way their experimental materials map into these distinctions.

  12. See Scholl (2007) for a positive example of using implicit measures in experiments in the philosophical domain of the metaphysics of objects.

  13. For further elaboration on this point, see Mallon (2007).

  14. Hauser et al. make this same move more explicitly when they exclude gender as a relevant explanatory dimension, writing that “we find it clear that some distinctions (e.g., the agent’s gender) do not carry any explanatory weight” (Hauser et al. 2007, p. 131). Here again, they make judgments that reflect a judgment about what sort of considerations are properly considered moral ones. But there seems little reason to think evolution would have respected such niceties in constructing us, so it is not clear why such exclusions are relevant to our underlying functional organization.

  15. Scholl provides some excellent suggestions as to how philosophers and psychologists could do a better job of getting a handle on the mechanisms underlying various intuitions. However, it is not clear how to use his suggestions to help with the deeper sorts of problems discussed here. For example, he writes, “understanding the origins of our metaphysical intuitions in various psychological mechanisms could help us understand when they are worth revising or forfeiting in our philosophical theories, especially if there is reason to think that those psychological mechanisms may yield unreliable results in the particular contexts in which they are being asked to operate” (Scholl 2007, p. 586). But without knowing the proper domain of those mechanisms, it stands as an open question just what will count as reliable or unreliable operation.

  16. Wittgenstein (1953), Part II, section xiv.

References

  • Adams, F., and A. Steadman. 2004a. Intentional action in ordinary language: core concept or pragmatic understanding? Analysis 64: 173–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., and A. Steadman. 2004b. Intentional action and moral considerations: still pragmatic. Analysis 64: 268–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, J., and J. Weinberg. 2007. Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass 2: 56–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P., and T.P. German. 2000. Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition 77: B25–B31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. 2007. Epistemology of disagreement: the good news. The Philosophical Review 116: 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. 1998. Reflection on reflective equilibrium. In Rethinking intuition, ed. M. DePaul, and W. Ramsey, 113–128. Lantham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. 1999. Moral competence. In Philosophy and linguistics, ed. K. Murasugi, and R. Stanton, 169–190. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. 2006. Reflection and disagreement. Nous 41: 478–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. 2006. Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In Epistemology futures, ed. S. Heatherington. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., and F. Warfield. 2007. Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. 2003. The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glasgow, J. 2008. On the methodology of the race debate: conceptual analysis and racial discourse. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76: 333–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., and J. Pust. 1998. Philosophical theory and intuitional evidence. In Rethinking intuition, ed. M. DePaul, and W. Ramsey, 179–200. Lantham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. 2003. From neural “is” to moral “ought”: what are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4: 847–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., R. Sommerville, L. Nystrom, J. Darley, and J. Cohen. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293: 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1999. Moral philosophy and linguistics. In Proceedings of the 20th World Congress of Philosophy, vol. I: Ethics, ed. K. Brinkmann, 107–115. Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M., L. Young, and F. Cushman. 2007. Reviving rawls’ linguistic analogy: Operative principles and the causal structure of moral actions. In Moral psychology, volume 1: The evolution of morality: Adaptations and innateness, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong. Cambridge: MIT (Bradford Books).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1998. From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. 2008. An overview of lexical semantics. Philosophy Compass 3: 119–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. 2007. The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10: 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. 2005. The epistemic significance of disagreement. In Oxford studies in epistemology, vol. 1, ed. J. Hawthorne, and T. Gendler Szabo, 167–196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. 2007. Peer Disagreements and Higher Order Evidence. In Disagreement, ed. R. Feldman, and T. Warfield. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. 2008. Disagreement, dogmatism, and belief polarization. The Journal of Philosophy 105: 611–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2003a. Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63: 190–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2003b. Intentional action in folk psychology: an experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology 16: 309–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2004. Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64: 181–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2007a. Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance. Philosophical Explorations 10: 119–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2007b. Reason explanation in folk psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 90–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1970. How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67: 426–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. 2008. The folk concept of intentional action: philosophical and psychological issues. Mind & Language 23: 165–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. 2009. Doing without concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., S. Lindquist, and P. Griffiths. 2009. The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind & Language 24: 605–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., R. Mallon, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2004. Semantics, Cross-cultural style. Cognition 92: B1–B12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. 2007. Reviving rawls inside and out. In Psychology, volume 2: The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 145–155. Cambridge: MIT (Bradford Books).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., and S. Nichols. in press. Moral reasoning, moral rules, and moral dilemmas. In The Oxford handbook of moral psychology, ed. J. Doris, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mallon, R., E. Machery, S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2009. Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79: 332–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, M. 1980. Theory of syntactic recognition for natural languages. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. 1982. Vision. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

  • Mikhail, J. 2000. Rawls’ linguistic analogy: A study of the ‘generative grammar’ model of moral theory described by John Rawls in ‘A theory of justice’. Ph.D. Thesis. Cornell University, Ithaca.

  • Nadelhoffer, T. 2004a. On praise, side effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 196–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. 2004b. Blame, badness, and intentional action: a reply to Knobe and Mendlow. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24: 259–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T., and E. Nahmias. 2007. The past and future of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10: 123–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., S. Morris, T. Nadelhoffer, and J. Turner. 2005. Surveying freedom: folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical Psychology 18: 561–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., S. Morris, T. Nadelhoffer, and J. Turner. 2006. Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 28–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. 2002. On the genealogy of norms: a case for the role of emotion in cultural evolution. Philosophy of Science 69: 234–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. 2006. Imaginative blocks and impossibility: An essay in modal psychology. In The architecture of the imagination, ed. S. Nichols, 237–255. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., S. Stich, and J. Weinberg. 2003. Metaskepticism: Meditations in ethno-epistemology. In The skeptics: Contemporary debates, ed. S. Luper, 227–247. Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., and R. Mallon. 2006. Moral rules and moral dilemmas. Cognition 100: 530–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., and J. Knobe. 2007. Moral responsibility and determinism: the cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous 41: 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., and J. Ulatowski. 2007. Intuitions and individual differences: the Knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language 22: 346–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., and P. O’Neill. 1996. Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology 17: 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., P. O’Neill, and M. Jorgensen. 1993. An empirical study of moral intuitions: toward an evolutionary ethics. Journal of Personality and Social Research 64: 467–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. 1951. Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60: 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. 2007. Object persistence in philosophy and psychology. Mind & Language 22: 563–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B., and A. Leslie. 2003. Minds, modules, and meta-analysis. Child Development 72: 696–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. in press. Do ethicists steal more books. Philosophical Psychology.

  • Sperber, D. 1994. The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representation. In Mapping the mind, ed. L. Hirchfeld, and S. Gelman, 39–67. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K., and R. West. 2000. Individual differences in reasoning: implications for the rationality debate. Behavior and Brain Sciences 23: 645–726.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K., and P. Griffiths. 2004. Genes: philosophical analyses put to the test. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 26: 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surian, L., and A. Leslie. 1999. Competence and performance in false belief understanding: A comparison of autistic and normal 3-year-old children. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 17: 141–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., J. Alexander, and J. Weinberg. 2008. The instability of philosophical intuitions: running hot and cold on truetemp. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76: 138–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulatowski, J. 2008. How many theories of act individuation are there? Ph.D. Thesis. University of Utah, Salt Lake City.

  • Uhlmann, E., D. Pizzaro, D. Tannenbaum, and P. Ditto. 2009. The motivated use of moral principles. Judgment and Decision Making 4: 476–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. 2007. How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31: 318–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., S. Nichols, and S. Stich. 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29: 429–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. 2005. Epistemic permissiveness. Philosophical Perspectives 19: 445–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2004. Philosophical ‘intuitions’ and scepticism about judgments. Dialectica 58: 109–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2005. Armchair philosophy, metaphysical modality and counterfactual thinking. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105: 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2007. The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the participants in the 2008 Society for Philosophy and Psychology Workshop on Experimental Philosophy; the members of the Experimental Epistemology Laboratory (EEL) at Indiana University, especially Cameron Buckner and Chad Gonnerman; and two anonymous referees for this journal for valuable feedback on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Alexander.

Additional information

Each author contributed equally to the project; authors are listed alphabetically

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Alexander, J., Mallon, R. & Weinberg, J.M. Accentuate the Negative. Rev.Phil.Psych. 1, 297–314 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-009-0015-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-009-0015-2

Keywords

Navigation