Introduction

Human germline genome editing (HGGE) has piqued the scientific community’s interest over the past 3–4 yearsFootnote 1 and is gaining traction in the public sphere. Experts who are deeply attentive to the technology’s possible uses disagree on whether it should be used in humans at all, but generally agree that CRISPR,Footnote 2 an example of a genome-editing technique, has the potential to be transformative. When asked about what possible applications seem likely, many experts believe that CRISPR has great potential to cure and prevent serious genetic diseases. The most obvious category of disease is those caused by monogenic mutations in the human DNA (Lockyer 2016). This expected application may be especially poignant for members of the rare disease community, many of whom are diagnosed with monogenic diseases that come with high morbidity and mortality rates, and lack broad representation within the literature surrounding genome editing. While it is of course true that rare disease patients’ experiences are not generalizable, the literature on rare disease does offer some commonalities that may be instructive. We begin the manuscript by providing a brief overview of the Canadian legal and policy context surrounding HGGE, which provides an excellent starting point for a discussion about why broader societal dialogue should be encouraged. We then analyze the social science literature on rare diseases and look at the possibilities HGGE may hold for some members of this community. This manuscript seeks to contribute to the search for community engagement by arguing that commonalities found within the experiences of rare disease groups could add an important angle to the ongoing discussions and debates. Furthermore, these experiences could provide us with insight as to the potential desirability of HGGE for the treatment and prevention of serious or life-threatening genetic diseasesFootnote 3 and where the line should be drawn, if at all. We certainly do not wish to engage in a broad discussion about whether all rare disease patients share the same perspective. Rather, we wish to draw attention to the possibility that some members of the rare disease community, as a result of their many shared experiences, may perceive HGGE as particularly promising for themselves and their broader disease-specific communities.

The law of genome editing in Canada

Genome editing is a technique used to make precise modifications to the DNA within a cell or an organism (e.g., bacteria, plants, animals, and humans). These modifications can be made to either somatic cells (i.e., limited to the individual) or to germ cells (i.e., heritable) (Ma et al. 2014). Applications of human genome editing can be for research purposes, therapeutic purposes, or non-therapeutic purposes (i.e., enhancement). In the context of this paper, we will focus on the human applications of HGGE and the potential opportunities that it offers for the prevention and treatment of disease, more specifically monogenic rare diseases.

In the midst of an active global dialogue about the merits and drawbacks of permitting the editing of human DNA in clinical settings, Canada is an example of a high-profile country that continues to have a criminal ban on HGGE (Isasi et al. 2016; Knoppers et al. 2017). Not alone in this position, a restrictive, statutory approach is most commonly used to address the concerns associated with HGGE. The 2004Assisted Human Reproduction Act (AHRA) governs human reproduction and related research and classifies HGGE as a criminal offense. The AHRA specifically states that “[n]o person shall knowingly […] alter the genome of a cell of a human being or in vitro embryo such that the alteration is capable of being transmitted to descendants” (s 5(1)(f)). Those who violate this provision may be guilty of an offense and subject to a fine up to $500,000 and/or 10 years in prison (s 60).

Canadian academics and clinicians engaging in the dialogue about whether to lift the criminal ban have an opportunity to inform the global debate despite Canadian clinician-researchers potentially falling behind their global colleagues based on the interpretive uncertainty surrounding the contextual application of the prohibition (i.e., research versus clinic) (Knoppers et al. 2017). Some researchers argue that this prohibition should only apply to reproductive uses of the technology, while allowing basic and pre-clinical research to move forward (Knoppers et al. 2017; Master and Bedford 2018). This would align with the Human Genome Editing Report that was released by the National Academies of Sciences, Engineering and Medicine, which stipulates that it may be permissible to move towards HGGE clinical trials one day, provided such trials be conducted for compelling reasons (e.g., prevention or treatment of serious or life-threatening diseases), meet a specific set of criteria, be subject to strict oversight, and be considered a “last” resort (i.e., no other reasonable alternatives exist) (National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine 2017). Similarly, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics’ 2018 report entitled “Genome editing and human reproduction: social and ethical issues” states that HGGE is not unacceptable in itself; that is, it may become morally acceptable in time (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2018). Recent statements on HGGE draw a clear distinction between research and clinical or reproductive purposes (de Lecuona et al. 2017; Federation of European Academies of Medicine (FEAM) 2017; National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine 2017; Ormond et al. 2017; Brokowski 2018; De Wert et al. 2018). Therefore, we must not foreclose discussion so that we may engage with a variety of stakeholders to work towards a responsible solution (Baltimore et al. 2018; Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2018).

The momentum seems to be building in Canada for the criminal provisions in the AHRA to be reconsidered. There are other approaches to regulating research using HGGE that are less rigid than the current criminal prohibitions (Knoppers et al. 2017; Bubela et al. 2019; Knoppers and Kleiderman 2019). A principled approach could be adopted, for example, that is informed by evidence rather than driven by hype. This approach could allow policy to remain nuanced and as flexible as possible, when appropriate (Knoppers et al. 2017). Discussions about what this new regulatory framework would look like should be inclusive so as to have representation from various stakeholders, including the duly informed public (Knoppers et al. 2017; National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine 2017; Rosenbaum 2019).

Understanding rare disease

Rare disease patient organizations have been actively involved in the discussion about genome editing in Europe and the UK through organizations such as the European Organisation for Rare Diseases (European Parliament, the Council and the Commission 2012; EURORDIS 2017, 2018) and the Genetic Alliance UK; European Organisation for Rare Diseases (Genetic Alliance 2015; Genetic Alliance 2016; EURORDIS 2017; Luxner 2018). In Canada, on the other hand, the rare disease community has been rather quiet to date about genome editing. The definition of a rare disease varies by country, but it is typically based on the prevalence of a disease. For example, the Orphan Drug Act defines a rare disease as any condition that affects fewer than 200,000 people in the USA (Orphan Drug Act 1983, H.R. 5238 (97th)). Although very few people may have any given rare disease, many people will have a rare disease in their lifetime (Dodge et al. 2011). The Canadian Organization for Rare Disorders (CORD) estimates that rare diseases affect 1 in 12 Canadians and that approximately 7,000 rare diseases have been identified, many of which are genetic in origin. These numbers are growing as genetic testing becomes more ubiquitous in diagnostic medicine and as our understanding of disease becomes more precise.

Countries are also beginning to pay more attention to rare diseases within their healthcare systems (Dharssi et al. 2017). Unfortunately, the government of Canada has not yet adopted an official definition of what qualifies as a rare disease, nor has it implemented a comprehensive policy framework to attend to the needs of this community. Some political will existed in the past (CORD 2012), but it suffered a “kiss of death” in late 2017 when Health Canada removed its statement of intent to proceed with a regulatory framework from its website (Forrest 2017).

In part, conversations about HGGE reinforce a medical model of disability. The medical model considers disease as comprising categories of abnormality measured against the typical normalcy of a healthy human. For some, the prospect of allowing HGGE may represent a needless perpetuation of this medical model, whereas for others, HGGE may represent their only hope of having a healthy child (Polcz and Lewis 2016). Therefore, the goal of HGGE must be viewed, at least in part, as the fulfillment of parental desires of creating a healthy child through a medical intervention. We will return to this point later, after considering what the social model of disability can teach us about rare diseases.

The social model asks us to think of rare diseases as being more than mere differences from statistical norms, and to listen to the stories of individuals who experience rare diseases in order to locate those stories within the broader healthcare context (Newman 2014). In this context, disability and its associated harms are seen as the result of society’s organization (e.g., lack of available resources, stigma). The social model focuses on ways to further understand the barriers that limit life choices for disabled individuals so as to provide them with independence and control over their lives and options (Scope 2018). Sara Newman (2014) argues that the social model is a better approach for us to adopt in our efforts to understand rare diseases:

[…] advocacy groups use the social model to consider rare diseases within their broader contexts; by including the voices of those with rare diseases, and offering these materials online, these sites educate a wider public about the ways in which actual people experience these often diverse and complicated conditions (p. 53).

A third model that has been proposed by Savulescu and Kahane (2011) is the welfarist approach to disability. This approach incorporates aspects from both the medical and social models with a focus on the impact of a disease or condition on the well-being of the individual (Savulescu and Kahane 2011). As such, disease is perceived as relative to both the person and the circumstances (i.e., context matters) (Savulescu and Kahane 2011). If we wish to speak of rare diseases as a broad yet unified class of diseases, then the welfarist approach may offer a more inclusive lens through which to do this, than either the medical or social model taken independently.

Some, but not all, of the many challenges and experiences that connect rare disease patients can be found below in Table 1. Although this list has been compiled on the basis of a broad review of the literature, it is not exhaustive or comprehensive, and each item does not necessarily apply to every patient and/or family. It is also important to note that the way we have chosen to categorize and present the challenges and experiences within the table is simply to provide a general overview. These are not watertight compartments, and we recognize that the challenges and experiences presented in one category can, and often do, crossover into other categories.

Table 1 Connecting challenges and experiences for rare disease patients

Germline genome editing through a rare disease lens

Roughly 7 million of the 130 million babies born worldwide each year have serious inherited genetic disorders (Church 2017). It is estimated that approximately 80% of those disorders are caused by a single gene mutation and “effective therapies for these diseases are themselves comparatively rare” (p. 681) (Boycott et al. 2013). The prevalence of rare monogenic disorders can vary depending on founder effect,Footnote 4 geographic or cultural isolation, and genetic drift (Christianson et al. 2006), but the challenge of rare disease is global in its reach. It is therefore important to fully interrogate what the rare disease community’s perspective on germline editing might be.

Generally, somatic editing is seen as ethically acceptable, with several approved gene therapy clinical trials underway or expected to begin shortly (LePage 2017; Mullin 2017), whereas germline editing is more contentious. In August 2017, a highly anticipated study using CRISPR to correct a serious, heritable condition in human embryos made headlines. It was labeled a “landmark” study, being the first to successfully correct genes in viable human embryos with little to no off-target mutations or mosaicism (i.e., unexpected mutations or incomplete edits) which are some of the primary concerns surrounding germline editing, albeit in a research context (Ma et al. 2017). These findings are notable as they begin to address the relevant safety and efficacy issues related to germline editing and its potential future therapeutic applications. The possibility to repair mutations and prevent the reproductive transmission of heritable diseases is promising, especially for people with severe monogenic diseases that can cause significant morbidity or premature death. However, further research to confirm and continue to improve the safety and efficacy of the technology is still needed.

The reluctance to permit HGGE stems partly from the fact that preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) is able to address many of the issues that might otherwise be addressed using this technology. PGD can reduce the risk of transmitting a heritable genetic mutation by screening and selecting against embryos that contain the mutation(s) in question. Although PGD is a valid option in the context of screening for healthy embryos, there are situations where PGD is simply not an option. For one, PGD cannot be used to make permanent changes to the germline that may edit out a hereditary genetic mutation. As such, PGD would not be a viable solution in rare cases where it can be expected that all embryos will necessarily carry a significant mutation, such as the case when one parent is homozygous for a dominant disorder (e.g., Huntington’s disease) or both parents are homozygous for a recessive disorder (e.g., cystic fibrosis) (Dance 2017; Hyun and Osborn 2017; Klipstein 2017).

Furthermore, people with rare monogenic disorders may never have access to effective therapies, proper care, or sufficient social support. The notion that PGD and somatic cell editing are sufficient solutions to the problem of monogenic rare disease seems to be driven by a medical model that concerns itself simply with eliminating disease while neglecting to consider impacts beyond the patient (i.e., the patient’s descendants). This approach pays inadequate attention to the social and cultural factors involved, the everyday challenges faced by rare disease patients and their families, and the implications of the disease on future generations. In this sense, PGD would remain the clinical standard, while HGGE could serve as an alternative approach that may enable couples to have a genetically related and healthy child when all other options fail (Cavaliere 2017).

Further concerns about HGGE arise due to its perceived negative ethical consequences. Some of the arguments raised in the literature are focused around human rights, including disability rights; social justice; intergenerational monitoring; human enhancement; and the need for greater public engagement. A brief outline of each of these will be presented below, along with possible responses that could be offered by the rare disease community.

To begin, we must address the disability rights literature. Originating from the expressivist objection to prenatal screening, advocates for people with disabilities (including people with rare diseases) have argued that prenatal screening and other selective reproductive technologies may cause further stigma (Asch 1999; Nelson 1998; Parens and Asch 2000; Wendell 2013). Selective reproductive technologies targeted at selecting against the birth of a disabled child perpetuate a certain hostility towards, and the discrimination faced by, individuals living with diseases and/or disabilities, as well as their families (Nelson 1998; Asch 1999; Parens and Asch 2000; Wendell 2013; Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2018). This same critique has also been leveled against the prospect of HGGE. It is argued that people with genetic diseases and/or disabilities “can have both high quality of life and value” (p. 1010) (Dance 2017), and eliminating particular diseases and/or disabilities suggests that “parents are unwilling to accept any significant departure from the parental dreams that a child’s characteristics might occasion” (p. S2) (Parens and Asch 1999). We must therefore consider the negative impact that eliminating genetic diseases and/or disabilities could have on the availability of social support and services for those who continue to need such resources (Dance 2017).

Some have also raised the importance of differentiating between disability and persons living with a disability, which puts into question the validity of the expressivist argument (Savulescu 2001). Essentially, the individual choice of parents (i.e., their reproductive freedom) to select or edit out a given disease in their future child should not be perceived as a general statement on or discrimination of people living with that disease (Savulescu 2001). Moving forward with HGGE could send a message that disability itself, and not societal discrimination against people with disabilities, is the problem to be solved. These disability rights arguments have been acknowledged in the HGGE literature and it is accepted that this tension between eliminating disease and respecting those who live with disabilities is one that we will likely never be able to fully resolve. Empirical work demonstrates that these concerns are real and that they do cause distress and offense to some people (Hofmann 2017; Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2018). That being said, the literature also suggests that “encouraging attempts to reduce the incidence of a genetic disease is compatible with continuing respect for those born with the disease and providing support for their distinctive needs” (p. 85) (Kitcher 1996). As such, it will continue to be important to engage in careful and open dialogue with stakeholders from the implicated disability communities about the social and moral implications of particular applications of the technology while we move towards the clinical use of genome editing.

The notion that the human genome represents the “heritage of humanity,” along with our general desire to prohibit activities that are contrary to human dignity, is enshrined in human rights principles (United Nations Educational and Scientific and Cultural Organization 1997). Under the Oviedo Convention, alterations to the human genome are permitted for “preventive, diagnostic, or therapeutic purposes” provided these changes are not made to the germline (Council of Europe 1997). As well, the notion of preventive health care is expressly included under the right to health found in article 35 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union (European Parliament and the Council and the Commission 2012; Nordberg et al. 2017). Because these modifications are heritable and permanent, they can lead to unexpected health, epigenetic, and social consequences for future generations (Harris 2015; Dance 2017). As such, a human rights approach merits reflection in this context, as it can serve as a common starting point for the development of both national and international consensus regarding a responsible path forward for HGGE (Boggio et al. 2019; Knoppers and Kleiderman 2019). As Juengst (2017) argues, “[a] human rights approach to gene-editing policy would reorient our conversation from policing science to governing society and would shift our focus from avoiding risks to protecting opportunities” (p. 21).

We engage this same values discourse when we consider whether to eradicate diseases such as polio or measles. In the Western world, we have had the privilege of deciding that some diseases have no redeeming value and are worth eradicating because they can do incredible damage to the human race (So et al. 2017; Juengst et al. 2018). Many rare disease patients may argue that their diseases are more than mere differences, that they are solely harmful in nature, and that they have no redeeming value. Individuals born with Neonatal Onset Multisystem Inflammatory Disorder (NOMID), for example, must take an expensive immunosuppressant drug from birth if they wish to have a good chance of living into their teens. They must also be born in and continue to live in the right geographic location in order to have access to healthcare providers who understand their disease, can diagnose it, can prescribe and administer the necessary medication, and can conduct the ongoing testing needed in order to provide appropriate care. They would require sufficient health insurance to afford their medicine, there would need to be a specialty pharmacy where they live, and their insurance coverage would have to remain in place indefinitely. They may also have to reconsider their reproductive options/choice, factoring in the risk of bringing a child into this world who may experience the same challenges. Perhaps then, those very few people who live with a specific rare disease are in the best position to articulate what the eradication of their disease would signify to them. To date, the perspectives of various rare disease communities have not been sufficiently considered and responded to in the debates on HGGE. Yet, an emerging body of literature on the perspectives of people living with disabilities does exist and can be drawn on for guidance in the HGGE debate (Barnes 2014; Shakespeare 2015; Benjamin 2016; Saunders 2018). Such perspectives would undoubtedly add much depth to the conversation.

From a social justice standpoint, there is a concern that HGGE, if clinically available, would be expensive and limited to specialized centers. If so, then how would we determine who should have access and when? Should governments and insurers be required to guarantee equitable access (Dance 2017)? A rare disease patient might note that these inequities already exist and that they must live with them on a daily basis. In fact, healthcare inequities go much deeper than whether wealthy people are the only ones who have access to cutting-edge treatments. A person suffering from a monogenic rare disorder, for which there is no treatment, may already struggle daily with trying to grasp what justice the future holds for him or her and their family. It is reasonable to think that they would question the wisdom of banning HGGE on the basis of social justice concerns that ignore their own plight and the potential plight of their descendants.

A further concern is that current ethical guidelines for research involving humans do not account for the monitoring of individuals who are not part of the initial decision to participate in a study. Such monitoring would “expose future generations of the original participants’ families to potential abuse, exploitation, and psychological harms,” and raises concerns about the voluntary nature of their participation, protection of their privacy, re-identification, defining what “monitoring” would actually entail, and other unforeseeable risks (p. 1912) (Cwik 2017). Similar concerns arise with the introduction of any new or emerging medical technology, because a certain level of uncertainty is always present. If HGGE were eventually to become acceptable, it will be important to protect the welfare of children and future generations born from the technology, by ensuring proper ongoing follow-up and oversight, which in turn will require greater resources (Friedmann et al. 2015; National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine 2017). There is little precedent in clinical research ethics when it comes to this notion of intergenerational monitoring (Cwik 2017). It involves not only the current participant (i.e., unborn child) but also their descendants (i.e., multiple generations), which is a unique consideration of HGGE; hence, such an approach will raise its own share of ethical and logistical issues that go beyond the scope of this manuscript. This monitoring not only includes the health of the individual but takes on a more holistic approach that necessitates consideration of the societal implications as well (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2018).

The successful application of HGGE would have transgenerational benefits. Eradicating the single gene mutation from a family’s lineage reduces the risk of disease for their descendants (Gyngell et al. 2017). Concerns surrounding the difficulty of intergenerational monitoring arise, and they are reflective of a clinical research ethics system that needs to be updated in order to better account of the rise of genetics-based medicine (Cwik 2017; Hough and Ajetunmobi 2017; National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine 2017). Despite the fact that the genetic causes for many rare diseases have been identified, most patients do not have effective therapies available to them and likely never will. Children born with many rare diseases languish in a system and suffer from delayed diagnosis, inconsistent access to proper medical care, and a lower than average quality of life, among many other challenges. Rare disease patients suffer disproportionately in our healthcare systems and HGGE could potentially relieve some needless suffering in the future. Therefore, to rare disease families, the challenges of intergenerational monitoring may be acceptable, provided that they allow for hope of a better quality of life for their descendants.

There is a general consensus that HGGE should not be used for enhancement purposes at this time (either cognitive or physical) (Brokowski 2018). Rather, research into therapeutic applications should be prioritized. Studies demonstrate that the public is supportive of using genome editing to cure or prevent life-threatening or debilitating diseases (including in embryos, children, and adults), but that germline enhancement is unacceptable (Blendon et al. 2016; McCaughey et al. 2016; Gaskell et al. 2017; Scheufele et al. 2017). The point of contention appears to be the application (i.e., therapy versus enhancement), rather than the technology itself. This distinction may not be particularly helpful, however, as the definition of “enhancement” seems to be a moving target (Dance 2017; Gaskell et al. 2017). We may be able to address this point of contention by adopting a blended governance model that includes ethics education, codes of professional conduct, regulation, government oversight, enforcement, and punishment, in order to minimize concern about the technology being used for needless human enhancement (Knoppers and Kleiderman 2019). Instead of looking to establish broad societal consensus about HGGE in general, we might look for what we call “group-specific consensus” that is driven by the needs and experiences of different groups. All the while, noting that there may not be consensus even among rare disease patients as experiences can differ quite dramatically. This approach would place our focus squarely on constructive applications targeting the elimination of serious diseases or conditions. Decisions about what constitutes a “serious” condition would be further contextualized and would give appropriate weight and consideration to the experiences and opinions of individuals who have lived with specific genetic diseases in embodied ways that few others will ever understand. Although we must recognize that many of the challenges posed by disease are social in nature, there is also a subset of the rare disease community for whom the medical model of disability is the most poignant. We must, therefore, engage with those for whom a reduction of the social barriers to health may be insufficient to address their condition. Accordingly, it may not be possible to give proper weight to subjective disease-specific experiences if we are intent on proceeding with HGGE only if we have “broad societal consensus.”

It is also important to note that a disconnect exists in the public’s understanding of the terms being used in the genome-editing debate, and public opinion is often skewed by media representations that either overhype or push dystopian views (Blendon et al. 2016). As such, mechanisms are needed to improve education, dispel misconceptions and misinformation, build trust, and increase public engagement in the issues surrounding HGGE (Nordberg et al. 2017; van Mil et al. 2017). It is also important to educate disease-specific groups about HGGE and the issues that arise, particularly within the rare disease community, so that they can contribute to the conversation about whether it is possible to achieve consensus about the structural and governance parameters that should be adopted in order to guide our use of this technology. This contribution will ultimately allow for better alignment of such parameters with the needs and concerns of the rare disease community.

Finally, there has been a call for groups who are seriously concerned with the applications of the technology to “organize politically to force policymakers to take the steps needed to prevent this technology from being abused” (Foht 2018). We wish to encourage disease-specific groups to take public positions about the prospect of HGGE so that their voices can be heard in these important ongoing public debates.

Conclusion

Distinctive characteristics shared by members of rare disease communities make them uniquely positioned as a large group to take an active interest in the future of HGGE. Although some members of the rare disease community might object to HGGE for reasons that have been explored above, it is also clear that the burdens of rare disease can be multi-generational and devastating. Thus, some rare disease patients might challenge the consensus to oppose HGGE on the basis that this technology could provide them with hope of treatment, especially in cases where treatments or therapies are rare or nonexistent. The community is particularly well positioned to add a strong voice to the discussion that has yet to be heard. These discussions are timely and urgent, notably with the “CRISPR babies” scandal that shocked the international scientific and ethical communities in November 2018 (Kolata et al. 2018).

Even if the consensus is to not proceed with HGGE, the voice of the rare disease community can provide us with a great deal of insight as to the delineation of what may fall under the category of a serious disease worth eliminating. The real challenge in the discussion is sorting out whether and to what extent social conditions have a role in helping to define what qualifies as a “serious” disease—and whether the classification of “serious” is flexible depending on shifting social conditions and landscapes (e.g., if burdens are lessened through policies). There is a need to engage with the broader human community to help “guide and govern our technological futures” in a responsible and transparent manner, as decisions pertaining to HGGE belong to all of humanity (p. 135) (Hurlbut 2019).