Skip to main content
Log in

That’s the Fictional Truth, Ruth

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Fictional truth is commonly analyzed in terms of the speech acts or propositional attitudes of a teller. In this paper, I investigate Lewis’s counterfactual analysis in terms of felicitous narrator assertion, Currie’s analysis in terms of fictional author belief, and Byrne’s analysis in terms of ideal author invitations to make-believe—and find them all lacking. I propose instead an analysis in terms of the revelations of an infelicitous narrator.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The concern is with truth in fiction as opposed to truth through fiction.

  2. See, e.g., Lewis (1978), Currie (1986, 1990), Byrne (1993), and Matravers (1995).

  3. Byrne’s (1993) invites this interpretation.

  4. Lewis’ (1978) analysis only roughly fits into this format.

  5. But see Krasner (2002), p. 265.

  6. Walton (1990, pp. 148-9) suggests that this sort of fictional “clutter” should simply be ignored.

  7. It is important to note that, despite being a hypothetical member of the author’s community, the fictional author is of a distinct ontological kind than the actual members of this community. In particular, she is explicitly fictional and, hence, of the same ontological kind as characters in the fictional story.

  8. Currie (1990), p. 80. An informed reader is someone who “knows the relevant facts about the community in which the work was written” (1990, p. 79).

  9. Of course, the fictional author of an inconsistent fiction could not tell it as known fact, at least not at a possible world.

  10. Of course, more subtle actors and storytellers might indicate unreliability other than by their manner of speaking. And the script or the story by itself might also suffice without the need for any ham acting.

  11. Currie’s view entails that mindless fictions—or, more generally, fictions which exclude a teller—are contradictory. Currie himself simply embraces this consequence:

    “[on] my theory mindless fiction generates a game of make-believe in which we are called upon to make believe contradictory things: that it is told as known fact and that there is no one there to tell it.” (1990, pp. 125-6).

  12. This is not meant to be a decisive objection to Byrne’s position. The point is simply, by appeal to the analogy with theatre, to draw attention to the unfamiliarity of (both Currie’s fictional author and) Byrne’s ideal author. Despite merely being an idealized version of the actual author, the ideal author is nevertheless a distinct figure and one for which we find no analogue in theatre.

  13. The considerations raised here pose a difficulty for an analysis of fictional truth in terms of invitations to make-believe made by the actual author as well as Byrne’s ideal author.

  14. Byrne (1993, p. 32, n. 31) endorses Currie’s (1990) account of sui generis fictive illocutions in his discussion of explicit invitations to make-believe.

  15. Currie (1990, pp. 14–5) does respond to Searle’s argument. But Hoffman (2004) has argued that Currie’s defense of his uniquely fictive illocution is ultimately unsatisfactory.

  16. Searle 1975. For more on this issue, see Alward 2009.

  17. Or, more generally, from the interplay between the conversational principles and what Byrnean fiction-tellers say.

  18. Alternately, Byrne might invoke very general maxims from which both the familiar Gricean maxims and the fiction-specific maxims follow.

  19. The fictional world embodied by a text is just the collection of fictional truths embodied by it.

  20. Arguably, however, readers often do not come to the table with a neat delineation between relevant and irrelevant background information; rather, they have to determine what background information counts as relevant by working out what kind of world the narrative informant is describing. This is addressed more fully in Section V below.

  21. Although I am committed to the utility of the “fictional worlds” idiom, I do not take it to have ontological import.

  22. It is, of course, theoretically possible that more than one theory will equally (and best) fit the evidence. In such circumstances, what a narrator reveals will have to be identified with what is entailed by all such best theories.

  23. See Byrne (1993) and Kania (2005).

  24. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this objection.

  25. An author may, of course, engage in imaginative activities of various kinds as part of the creative process but there is no requirement that she do so—failing to do so does not undercut her claim to be engaging in composition.

  26. Alward 2006. I would argue that engagement with oral fiction requires similar imaginative activity on the part of listeners.

  27. See Kania (2005), p. 52.

  28. Or, if her act of fiction-telling is written, she produces a manuscript she intends to be imagined to be authored by some such figure.

References

  • Alward, P. (2006). Leave me out of it: de re but not de se imaginative engagement with fiction. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 64(4), 451–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alward, P. (2009). Onstage illocution. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 67(3), 321–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (1993). Truth in fiction: the story continued. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 71, 24–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1986). Fictional truth. Philosophical Studies, 50, 195–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1990). The nature of fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, vol. 3: Speech Acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, S. (2004). Fiction as action: Currie and Searle on speech act theory and the nature of fiction. Philosophia, 31, 513–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kania, A. (2005). Against the ubiquity of fictional narrators. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63(1), 47–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krasner, D. (2002). Semantics and fiction. Erkenntnis, 57, 259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. (1996). Intention in interpretation and literature. In The pleasures of aesthetics: Philosophical essays (pp. 175–213). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15, 37–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). Postscript to “Truth in Fiction.” In Philosophical Papers, vol. 1 (pp. 277–280). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Matravers, D. (1995). Beliefs and fictional narrators. Analysis, 55, 121–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1975). The logical status of fictional discourse. New Literary History, 6, 319–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, G. M. (1997). Le grand imagier steps out: the primitive basis of film narration. Philosophical Topics, 25, 295–318.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Alward.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Alward, P. That’s the Fictional Truth, Ruth. Acta Anal 25, 347–363 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0071-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0071-3

Keywords

Navigation