Skip to main content
Log in

Public epistemic trustworthiness and the integration of patients in psychiatric classification

  • S.I.: Responsible Research and Innovation
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Psychiatric classification, as exemplified by the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM), is dealing with a lack of trust and credibility—in the scientific, but also in the public realm. Regarding the latter in particular, one possible remedial measure for this crisis in trust lies in an increased integration of patients into the DSM revision process. The DSM, as a manual for clinical practice, is forced to make decisions that exceed available data and involve value-judgments. Regarding such decisions, public epistemic trustworthiness requires (1) that these value-judgments should be representative of those of the affected public, and (2) that the public has a reason to believe such a representation to be realized. Due to the long tradition of (public) distrust in psychiatry, such a reason can in this case best be provided by an actual integration of patients into the decision-making process, rather than by their representation through scientific experts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The DSM is produced and used primarily in the USA, while most other countries use the International Classification of Diseases (ICD) of the World Health Organization (WHO). However, as these nosologies strive for compatibility and are revised in hindsight of each other, the DSM’s impact extends beyond the North American context. This is even more so as much research on psychopathologies is being done in the USA and thus based on DSM diagnoses shaping study populations. The latest ICD revision (ICD-11) has just been released and many of the controversial issues surrounding the DSM-5 now stir up again. Similar to the DSM (see below), the WHO had also published a draft version of the revised ICD online and invited public comments. Due to the DSM’s central state in the current philosophical debate, I will focus on the latest DSM revision here.

  2. I am not arguing here that all of the mentioned critics are correct or fair (although I consider many of them to be reasonable concerns); rather, this section aims to illustrate the widespread nature of distrust in the DSM, thereby providing evidence for a current crisis. The term “crisis” may be considered as too strong by some; I use it because of the ubiquity of DSM-critiques and controversies (for a discussion of whether it is justified to speak more specifically of a crisis in a Kuhnian sense, cf. Poland and Tekin 2017b, Pouncey 2017).

  3. Although I do not have the space to argue for it here, I would like to mention that I strongly support this call for a greater taxonomic pluralism in psychiatric classification. One of the central problems of the DSM is that it is supposed to be a scientific as well as clinical and administrative tool and, as such, faces different and sometimes incompatible requirements (cf. also Tsou 2015). The RDoC therefore may be most fertile if it continues to target research instead of aiming to replace the DSM in all contexts.

  4. I will use the term “patient” here rather than other options such as “service user” or even “client”, as the latter two (for me) connote that the use of mental health care is a voluntary decision one might also refrain from, which is not representative of the reality of many of those who live with mental illness. Moreover, not all patients may be able to speak for themselves, wherefore the integration discussed here also extends to the people caring for them.

  5. To completely spell out such a proceduralist framework of scientific epistemic trustworthiness specifically tailored to the revision of psychiatric taxonomies is certainly a worthwhile (and demanding) task for future research (cf. also Sadler 2002 for some further proposals of procedural improvements). Here, I will however concentrate on the integration of patients as an additional procedural criterion of public epistemic trustworthiness.

  6. Most of these decisions might very well be in principle empirically underdetermined; for example, whether a certain condition is a disorder or rather a normal variation (see below). At the very least, it seems unlikely that all of these questions will just be unequivocally solved by future empirical evidence. It is therefore important to keep in mind that even if the RDoC succeeds in explaining mental disorders as dysfunctions in brain circuits, this would not by itself remedy the need for value-laden decisions (and thereby make patients’ inputs in taxonomic decision-making obsolete).

  7. For instance, current criteria include possible symptoms such as “often fails to give close attention or makes careless mistakes in schoolwork, at work, or during other activities”; “often does not follow through on instructions and fails to finish schoolwork, chores, or duties in the workplace”; “often leaves seat in situations where remaining seating is expected” (e.g., in the classroom) (APA 2013, p. 59 f.). It seems plausible that such behaviors constitute problems and thus qualify as symptoms relative to a certain socio-cultural context (which is, however, compatible with the possibility that ADHD does in fact result from a certain dysfunction or pathology).

  8. While it is plausible that the people concerned should be listened to regarding such decisions that are empirically underdetermined and have direct practical consequences, it is important to note here that patients are not a monolithic group. For example, some advocates have protested against the deletion of Asperger syndrome from the DSM-5, as this diagnosis has become central to the identity of many autistic individuals. Others, however, have welcomed and supported the introduction of an Autism Spectrum Disorder (with specifiers for severity as well as intellectual impairment) (Hacking 2013b). Integrating patients thus has to proceed carefully in order to represent dissent among patients themselves, too (see Sect. 5).

  9. Note that it also presumes the conditions of (social) objectivity to be adhered to. These include adherence to shared standards such as empirical adequacy. Therefore, this is not a case of introducing (patients’) values in the sense of wishful thinking or political correctness overriding empirical evidence, which would of course undermine both scientific and public epistemic trustworthiness. To avoid any danger of such an undermining, it is important to be clear and precise about where exactly value-laden decisions are made and patients’ perspectives can be helpful.

  10. From another angle, Hacking (2013b) argues that patient advocacy has long since played an essential role in shaping the understanding and classification of autism, as many scientific experts in this area have been personally connected to autistic people. Thus, the division between experts and advocates is not always clear-cut, as expertise in the field does not exempt one from the possibility of suffering from mental illness.

  11. The DSM-5′s inclusion of PMDD as an official diagnosis is a good example of a decision where patients’ and advocates’ perspectives could have served as a corrective means. Somewhat suspiciously, this inclusion occured at the same time as Prozac got re-patented as “Sarafem”, a pharmaceutical treatment for PMDD (a syndrome formerly known as PMS). The inclusion of PMS or PMDD as a mental disorder had met considerable resistance by feminists before (e.g., Caplan 1996; Chrisler and Johnston-Robledo 2002). One reason cited for its inclusion in the latest revision was that, apparently, the opposition had become tired of fighting. While there was considerable public reaction on other examples of inclusion or exclusion of diagnoses, there was not much feedback on PMDD (Zachar and Kendler 2013). One might interpret the DSM’s decision as being supported by a lack of public opposition here, thus as actually integrating laypersons’ perspectives. However, there might be many other reasons for this, such as a lack of media coverage. Thus, seeking diverse public perspectives on this matter might have served to forestall a premature consensus in this case and enhance the epistemic trustworthiness of the taxonomy (cf. also Solomon 2013).

  12. A similar point about this lack of accountability has been made by Sadler (2002) with regard to the DSM-IV (calling for critiques and feedback to published proposals, but never making transparent how such feedback has been dealt with and not explicitly answering it).

  13. To a certain extent, this seems to be already the case. Whooley (2010) finds a significant amount of intentional misdiagnoses in clinical practice, as clinicians ponder on the effects diagnoses can have for patients in terms of stigma versus access to health care. This need not mean that the DSM has low clinical utility, however. In fact, a certain leeway in diagnostics might even be considered a good thing in the light of possible consequences for individual patients, as long as it does not get too arbitrary.

References

  • Andreasen, N. C. (2006). DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: An example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 33, 108–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • APA. (1980). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, third edition: DSM-III. Arlington: APA.

    Google Scholar 

  • APA. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, fifth edition: DSM-5. Arlington: APA.

    Google Scholar 

  • APA. (04/12/2012). Principles for DSM-5 task force and work group members. http://web.archive.org/web/20120404114422/http://www.psych.org/MainMenu/Research/DSMIV/DSMV/BOTPrinciples.aspx. Accessed 18 March 2016.

  • Bonney, R., et al. (2016). Can citizen science enhance public understanding of science? Public Understanding of Science, 25, 2–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1976). What a theory of mental health should be. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 6, 61–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brotto, L. A. (2010). The DSM diagnostic criteria for hypoactive sexual desire disorder in women. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 39, 221–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (2015). The irreducibility of value-freedom to theory assessment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 49, 18–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueter, A. (forthcoming). Social epistemology and psychiatry. In: S. Tekin & R. Bluhm (Eds.), Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophy of Psychiatry. London: Bloomsbury Academic Press.

  • Bueter, A., & Jukola, S. (forthcoming). Sex, drugs, and how to deal with criticism: The case of flibanserin. In: B. Osimani & A. La Caze (Eds.), Uncertainty in pharmacology: Epistemology, methods and decisions. New York: Springer.

  • Caplan, P. J. (1996). They say you’re crazy: How the world’s most powerful psychiatrists decide who’s normal. Cambridge, MA: Da Capo Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisler, J. C., & Johnston-Robledo, I. (2002). Raging hormones? Feminist perspectives on premenstrual symptom and postpartum depression. In M. Ballou & L. Brown (Eds.), Rethinking mental health and disorder: Feminist perspectives (pp. 174–197). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2002). Disease. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33, 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., & Krimsky, S. (2012). A comparison of DSM-IV and DSM-5 panel members’ financial associations with industry: A pernicious problem persists. PLoS Medicine, 9, 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosgrove, L., Krimsky, S., Vijayaraghavan, M., & Schneider, L. (2006). Financial ties between DSM-IV panel members and the pharmaceutical industry. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 75, 154–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1995). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1998). The viewpoint of no one in particular. In W. Egginton & M. Sandbothe (Eds.), The pragmatic turn in philosophy (pp. 115–129). New York: State University of New York Press 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Follette, W. C., & Houts, A. C. (1996). Models of scientific progress and the role of theory in taxonomy development: A case study of the DSM. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 64, 1120–1132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frances, A. J., & Widinger, T. (2012). Psychiatric diagnosis: Lessons from the DSM-IV past and cautions for the DSM future. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 8, 109–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • George, B. (2010). What’s in a name? Client participation, diagnosis, and the DSM-5. Journal of Mental Health, 19, 479–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gureje, O., & Stein, D. J. (2012). Classification of mental disorders: The importance of inclusive decision-making. International Review of Psychiatry, 24, 606–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2007). Kinds of people: Moving targets. Proceedings of the British Academy, 151, 285–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2013a). Lost in the forest. Review of DSM-5: Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, Fifth Edition by the American Psychiatric Association. London Review of Books 35, 7–8.

  • Hacking, I. (2013b). On the ratio of science and activism in the shaping of autism. In K. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry III: The nature and sources of historical change (pp. 326–339). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, S. C. C. (2010). Institutionalized intolerance of ADHD: Sources and consequences. Hypatia, 25, 504–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, G. A., & Zachar, P. (2017). RDoC’s metaphysical assumptions: Problems and promises. In J. Poland & Ş. Tekin (Eds.), Extraordinary science: Responding to the current crisis in psychiatric research (pp. 59–86). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwitz, A. V., & Wakefield, J. C. (2012). The loss of sadness: How psychiatry transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, S. E. (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: The problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 6, 155–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Insel, T., Cuthbert, B., Garvey, M., et al. (2010). Research domain criteria (RDOC): Toward a new classification framework for research on mental disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Insel, T. (04/29/2013). Transfoming diagnosis. Director’s Blog, NIMH. www.nimh.nih.gov/about/director/2013/transforming-diagnosis.shtml. Accessed 30 January 2016.

  • Irzik, G., & Kurtulmus, F. (forthcoming). What is epistemic public trust in science? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Kendell, R., & Jablensky, A. (2003). Distinguishing between the validity and utility of psychiatric diagnoses. American Journal of Psychiatry, 160, 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., et al. (2009). Guidelines for making changes to DSM-V. www.dsm5.org/ProgressReports/Documents/Guidelines-for-Making-Changes-to-DSM_1.pdf. Accessed 13 September 2015.

  • Kendler, K. S. (2013). A history of the DSM-5 scientific review committee. Psychological Medicine, 43, 1793–1800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S. (2016). The phenomenology of major depression and the representativeness and nature of DSM criteria. American Journal of Psychiatry, 173(8), 771–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kesey, K. (1962). One flew over the Cuckoo’s nest. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., & Reiss, J. (2010). Biomedical research, neglected diseases, and well-ordered science. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History, and Foundations of Science, 24, 263–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laing, R. D. (1967). The politics of experience. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, C. (2007). Shyness: How normal behavior became a sickness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lundh, A., Lexchin, J., Mintzes, B., Schroll, J. B., & Bero, L. (2017). Industry sponsorship and research outcome. The Cochrane Library.

  • Murphy, D. (2006). Psychiatry in the scientific image. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musschenga, A., van der Steen, W., & Ho, V. (2010). The business of drug research: A mixed blessing. In H. Radder (Ed.), The commodification of academic science (pp. 110–131). Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nilsen, E., Myrhaug, H. T., Johansen, M., Oliver, S., & Oxman, A. D. (2006). Methods of consumer involvement in developing healthcare policy and research. The Cochrane Library: Clinical Practice Guidelines and Patient Information Material.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., & Sass, L. (2003). Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 29, 427–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poland, J., & Tekin, Ş. (Eds.). (2017a). Extraordinary science: Responding to the current crisis in psychiatric research. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poland, J., & Tekin, Ş. (2017b). Introduction. In J. Poland & Ş. Tekin (Eds.), Extraordinary science: Responding to the current crisis in psychiatric research (pp. 1–14). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, D. (2013). Establishing normative validity for scientific psychiatric nosology: The significance of integrating patient perspectives. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 63–74). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pouncey, C. (2017). Psychopathology without nosology: The research domain criteria project as normal science. In J. Poland & Ş. Tekin (Eds.), Extraordinary science: Responding to the current crisis in psychiatric research (pp. 87–103). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regier, D. A., Kuhl, E. A., & Kupfer, D. J. (2013). The DSM-5: Classification and criteria changes. World Psychiatry, 12, 92–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, S. L. (2013). Patient advocacy organizations: Institutional conflicts of interest, trust, and trustworthiness. Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics, 41, 680–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, P. A. (2002). Values and Objectivity in Psychiatric Nosology. In J. Z. Sadler (Ed.), Descriptions and prescriptions: Values, mental disorders, and the DSMs (pp. 45–55). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (2002). Values in developing psychiatric classifications: A proposal for DSM-V. In J. Z. Sadler (Ed.), Descriptions and prescriptions: Values, mental disorders, and the DSMs (pp. 301–322). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Pres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (2005). Values and psychiatric diagnosis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z. (2013). Considering the economy of DSM alternatives. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 21–38). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sadler, J. Z., & Fulford, B. (2004). Should patients and their families contribute to the DSM-5 process? Psychiatric Services, 55, 133–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheman, N. (2001). Epistemology resuscitated: Objectivity as trustworthiness. In N. Tuana & S. Morgen (Eds.), Engendering rationalities (pp. 23–52). New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shorter, E. (2013). The history of the DSM. In J. Paris & J. Phillips (Eds.), Making the DSM-5: Concepts and controversies (pp. 3–19). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sisti, D., & Johnson, R. (2015). Revision and representation: The controversial case of DSM-5. Public Affairs Quarterly, 29, 76–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2013). Expert disagreement and medical authority. In K. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry III: The nature and sources of historical change (pp. 60–72). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, R. L. (2004). Good idea or politically correct nonsense? Psychiatric Services, 55, 113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spitzer, R. L. (2008). DSM-V: Open and transparent? Letters to the Editor. Psychiatric News, 43, 26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, D. J., & Phillips, K. A. (2013). Patient advocacy and DSM-5. BMC Medicine, 11, 133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T. (1974). The myth of mental illness: Foundations of a theory of personal conduct. New York: Harper and Row.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tekin, Ş. (2015). Against hyponarrating grief: Incompatible research and treatment interests in the DSM-5. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical reflections on the psychiatric babel (pp. 179–197). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiefer, L. (2006). Female sexual dysfunction: A case study of disease mongering and activist resistance. PLoS Medicine, 3, e178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsou, J. Y. (2015). DSM-5 and psychiatry’s second revolution: Descriptive vs. theoretical approaches to psychiatric classification. In S. Demazeux & P. Singy (Eds.), The DSM-5 in perspective: Philosophical Reflections on the psychiatric babel (pp. 43–62). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47, 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whooley, O. (2010). Diagnostic ambivalence: Psychiatric workarounds and the diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Sociology of Health & Illness, 32, 452–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2009). Bias and values in scientific research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40, 92–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2013). Epistemic trust in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 233–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zachar, P. (2000). Psychiatric disorders are not natural kinds. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 7, 167–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachar, P., & Kendler, K. S. (2013). A DSM insiders’ history of premenstrual dysphoric disorder. In K. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry III: The nature and sources of historical change (pp. 350–372). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I want to thank Martin Carrier, Anne-Marie Gagné-Julien, Gürol Irzik, Saana Jukola, and Torsten Wilholt for helpful comments, as well as Alfons and Najko Jahn for their support. Moreover, the audiences at the workshops on “Responsible Research and Innovation” (Bielefeld) and “Issues in Medical Epistemology” (Cologne) have provided very valuable feedback on earlier versions of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anke Bueter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bueter, A. Public epistemic trustworthiness and the integration of patients in psychiatric classification. Synthese 198 (Suppl 19), 4711–4729 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01913-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01913-z

Keywords

Navigation