Skip to main content
Log in

Lost memories and useless coins: revisiting the absentminded driver

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The puzzle of the absentminded driver combines an unstable decision problem with a version of the Sleeping Beauty problem. Its analysis depends on the choice between “halfing” and “thirding” as well as that between “evidential” and “causal” decision theory. I show that all four combinations lead to interestingly different solutions, and draw some general lessons about the formulation of causal decision theory, the interpretation of mixed strategies and the connection between rational credence and objective chance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more precise statements, see e.g. Lewis (1981) and Joyce (1999, Chap. 5). While it is not essential for my discussion, I assume that states, acts and outcomes are all entities of the same kind (propositions), and that outcomes can be identified with conjunctions of states and acts; see Joyce (1999, Chap. 2) for discussion. See also Skyrms (1984, Chap. 4) and Joyce (2002) on the causal interpretation of Savage (1954).

  2. There are other ways to understand desire on which desirability isn’t represented by conditional expected utility. Roughly speaking, conditional expected utilities measure the extent to which the agent would be pleased to learn that the relevant proposition is true. Something else is in play when one expresses a positive attitude towards counterfactual scenarios in which Kennedy was not killed by saying, “I wish Oswald hadn’t killed Kennedy”. The causal expected utility \({\textit{EU}}(A)\) of a proposition \(A\) arguably captures this kind of subjunctive desirability of \(A\). See e.g. Etlin (2008, Chap. 2) for discussion.

  3. Proof: I first show that \(P({\textit{Continue}}_1) = P({\textit{Continue}}_2) = c\). Observe that \({{\textit{Second}}}\) entails \({\textit{Continue}}_1\), wherefore \({{\textit{Continue}}}\) entails \({\textit{Continue}}_1\). More specifically, \({\textit{Continue}}_1\) is the disjunction of \({{\textit{Continue}}}\) and \( {{\textit{Second}}} \; \& \; {{\textit{Leave}}}_2\). By uniformity, the latter has probability 0, as does \( {\textit{Continue}}_1 \; \& \; {{\textit{Leave}}}_2\). Hence \( c = P({{\textit{Continue}}}) = P({\textit{Continue}}_1) = P({\textit{Continue}}_1 \; \& \; {\textit{Continue}}_2)\). Since \( {\textit{Continue}}_2 \; \& \; {{\textit{Leave}}}_1\) also has probability 0, it follows that \( P({\textit{Continue}}_2) = P({\textit{Continue}}_2 \; \& \; {\textit{Continue}}_1) = c\).

    Now \({\textit{Continue}}_2\) divides into \( {\textit{First}} \; \& \; {\textit{Continue}}_2\) and \( {{\textit{Second}}} \; \& \; {\textit{Continue}}_2\), so \( c = P({\textit{First}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_2) + P({{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_2)\). By uniformity, it follows that \( c = P({\textit{First}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_2) + P({{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1)\). Moreover, by symmetry, \( P({\textit{First}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1) = P({{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1)\), and so \( P({\textit{First}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_2) = P({{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1)\) by uniformity. Hence \( P({\textit{First}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_2) = P({{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1) = c/2\). \( {{\textit{Second}}} \, \& \, {\textit{Continue}}_1\) is equivalent to \({{\textit{Second}}}\). The remaining possibility \( {\textit{First}} \, \& \, {{\textit{Leave}}}_2\) must then have probability \(1-c\).

  4. Pace Lewis (1981, p. 29f.).

  5. There are also equilibrium states of indecision. In general, any state in which the expected bias is 2/3 is a stable solution.

  6. Neither Aumann et al. nor Piccione and Rubinstein actually mention the connection to evidential and causal decision theory. Piccione and Rubinstein implicitly assume evidential decision theory by setting \(c=b\). In addition, they overlook the fact that the probability of being at the first exit (evidentially) depends on the chosen bias \(b\). Instead they assume that \(P({\textit{First}})\) has a fixed value of 3/5, based on the driver’s prior decision to use bias \(c=2/3\) and the fact that \(P({\textit{First}}) = 1/(c+1)\). Setting \(c=b\) then yields the payoff function \((6b -3b^2 +8)/5\), which has its maximum at \(b = 1/3\). The corrected evidential formula \((8b - 6b^2)/(b+1)\) appears in the appendix of Rabinowicz (2003).

    Aumann et al. (1997) object that by setting \(c=b\), Piccione and Rubinstein erroneously represent the driver’s present choice as controlling her choice at the other exit. They suggest that if the driver is certain that she chooses bias \(c\), then the expected utility of Bias \( = b\) is \((4b+4c-6bc)/(c+1)\), which agrees with our formula (21). According to Aumann et al., the optimal bias is then the value of \(b\) that maximises that function when plugged in for \(c\): 2/3.

  7. One disanalogy between the two cases is that the driver’s coin is tossed after she arrives at the first exit, while Beauty’s coin is usually assumed to be tossed before she wakes up on Monday. However, that timing is plausibly inessential to the Sleeping Beauty problem. Since the outcome of the toss has no effect until Tuesday morning, the coin might as well be tossed on Monday instead of Sunday.

  8. This line of thought occurs in Elga (2000) and Lewis (2001), and is further developed e.g. in Bradley (2011), Schwarz (2012) and Schwarz (2013). One complication here is that Beauty may be forced to violate doxastic conservatism if the coin lands tails: for example, her credence in the proposition that the sky is overcast on either Monday or Tuesday will be high on Monday evening, but low on Tuesday morning, although she doesn’t acquire any relevant information. (At least this should be so if we assume, as we did for the driver, that her belief state on Monday morning is identical to her belief state on Tuesday morning.) One might think that this threat of diachronic irrationality somehow undermines the force of doxastic conservatism at the earlier transition from Sunday to Monday. In Schwarz (2013) I argue that it doesn’t.

  9. The argument from evidential support can be found, in different variations, e.g. in Piccione and Rubinstein (1997), Dorr (2002), Arntzenius (2003), Horgan (2004, 2008) and Horgan and Mahtani (2013).

  10. For another motivation of the thirder assignment, observe that if the experiment were repeated indefinitely, the ratio of occasions where the driver finds herself at an exit and the (first) coin lands tails to such occasions where the coin lands heads would converge to \(2c : (1-c)\).

  11. In the case of Sleeping Beauty, the symmetry assumption is sometimes motivated by a stipulation that Beauty’s two tails awakenings are “subjectively indistinguishable”. Symmetry is then supposed to follow from a general principle of self-locating indifference. Halfers sometimes object to symmetry, suggesting that Beauty ought to be certain on Monday that it is Monday and on Tuesday that it is Tuesday; see e.g. Hawley (2013). This response gets less attractive if it is stipulated, as I have, that the driver has the same beliefs at every exit. (Whether the two situations are otherwise indistinguishable is to my mind irrelevant, but feel free to suppose so if you think it matters).

  12. The driver does in fact not violate the Principle formulated in Lewis (1980), since her credences aren’t “initial”. One might also question whether there even is an objective chance for the centred proposition Tails, as opposed to the uncentred \({\textit{Tails}}_1\) and \({\textit{Tails}}_2\).

  13. For the second exit, we assumed that \( V({{\textit{Second}}} \; \& \; {{\textit{Bias}}}=b) = (1-b)4 + b1 = 4-3b\). This is correct on both halfing and thirding, since on either account the probability of Tails, given \( {{\textit{Second}}} \; \& \; \textit{Bias}=b\), is \(b\).

  14. See Harper (1986) and Skyrms (1990) on the connection between Nash equilibria in game theory and deliberation equilibria in causal decision theory.

  15. One noteworthy aspect of the puzzle that I have not discussed concerns the form of the deliberation dynamics. In all versions of the puzzle, the dynamics can’t go by the simple models described in Skyrms (1990). For example, these models would not preserve the symmetry assumption; they also don’t take into account how the driver’s choices at the two exits can become decorrelated through the process of deliberation.

  16. Skyrms’s own formulation is superficially different: he defines \({\textit{EU}}(A)\) as \(\sum _K P(K) \sum _C {\textit{Ch}}_{K}(C/A) V(C)\), where \(K\) ranges over chance hypotheses, \(C\) over “consequences” and \({\textit{Ch}}_K(C/A)\) is the conditional chance of \(C\) given \(A\) according to \(K\).

References

  • Arntzenius, F. (2002). Reflections on Sleeping Beauty. Analysis, 62, 53–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arntzenius, F. (2003). Some problems for conditionalization and reflection. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 356–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arntzenius, F. (2008). No regrets, or: Edith Piaf revamps decision theory. Erkenntnis, 68, 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R., & Brandenburger, A. (1995). Epistemic conditions for nash equilibrium. Econometrica, 63, 1161–1180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R., Hart, S., & Perry, M. (1997). The absent-minded driver. Games and Economic Behavior, 20, 102–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, D. (2011). Confirmation in a branching world: The Everett interpretation and Sleeping Beauty. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 323–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, R. (2010). Putting a value on Beauty. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hájek, A. (1997). David Hume, David Lewis, and decision theory. Mind, 106, 411–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C. (2002). Sleeping Beauty: In defence of elga. Analysis, 62, 292–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. (2007). Some counterexamples to causal decision theory. Philosophical Review, 116, 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2000). Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem. Analysis, 60, 143–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, E. (2008). “Desire, belief, and conditional belief”. PhD Dissertation.

  • Gibbard, A., & Harper, W. (1978). Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In C. A. Hooker, J. J. Leach, & E. F. McClennen (Eds.), Foundations and applications of decision theory (pp. 125–162). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harper, W. (1986). Mixed strategies and ratifiability in causal decision theory. Erkenntnis, 24, 25–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, P. (2013). Inertia, optimism and Beauty. Nos, 47(1), 85–103.

  • Horgan, T. (2004). Sleeping Beauty awakened: New odds at the dawn of the new day. Analysis, 64, 10–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (2008). Synchronic bayesian updating and the Sleeping Beauty problem: Reply to Pust. Synthese, 160, 155–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Mahtani, A. (2013). Generalized conditionalization and the Sleeping Beauty problem. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 333–351.

  • Jeffrey, R. (1965). The logic of decision. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (1999). The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2002). Levi on causal decision theory and the possibility of predicting one’s own actions. Philosophical Studies, 110, 69–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. (2012). Regret and instability in causal decision theory. Synthese, 187(1), 123–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In R. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. 2). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Causal decision theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59, 5–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2001). Sleeping Beauty: Reply to Elga. Analysis, 61, 171–176.

  • Piccione, M., & Rubinstein, A. (1997). On the interpretation of decision problems with imperfect recall. Games and Economic Behavior, 20, 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz, W. (2003). Remarks on the absentminded driver. Studia Logica, 73, 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richter, R. (1985). Rationality, group choice and expected utility. Synthese, 63, 203–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, W. (2012). Changing minds in a changing world. Philosophical Studies, 159, 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, W. (2013). Conservatism and evidentialism in Bayesian epistemology. Unpublished Manuscript.

  • Skyrms, B. (1984). Pragmatics and empiricism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Skyrms, B. (1990). The dynamics of rational deliberation. Cambridge(Mass.): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Titelbaum, M. G. (2012). An embarrassment for double-halfers. Thought, 1(2), 146–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weirich, P. (1985). Decision instability. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 63, 465–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Ancestors of this paper were presented at the ANU in 2007 and at the Formal Epistemology Workshop in Munich in 2012. I thank the audiences on these occasions, as well as Alma Barner, Rachael Briggs, Kenny Easwaran, Alan Hájek, Daniel Nolan, Michael Titelbaum, David Wiens, and three anonymous referees for comments and discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wolfgang Schwarz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schwarz, W. Lost memories and useless coins: revisiting the absentminded driver. Synthese 192, 3011–3036 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0699-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0699-z

Keywords

Navigation