Skip to main content
Log in

Better Red than Dead—Putting an End to the Social Irrelevance of Postwar Philosophy of Science

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper asks what is necessary in a theory of science adequate to the task of empowering philosophers of science to participate in public debate about science in a social context. It is argued that an adequate theory of science must be capable of theorizing the role of values and motives in science and that it must take seriously the irreducibly social nature of scientific knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Brenner (1990) and Martin (1991) are good sources on Duhem’s work in context. For a more partisan view, see Jaki (1987). For more general background, see Brenner (2003).

  2. Blackmore (1972) is still the best general introduction to Mach’s work in context.

  3. The literature on Neurath has blossomed in the last twenty years. Among the better sources are Cartwright et al. (1996), Nemeth and Stadler (1996), and Uebel (1992, 2000). For general background on logical empiricism, see Stadler (1997).

  4. The scare quotation marks around “non-cognitive” are to remind the reader that casual use of the expression begs important philosophical questions by implying that values and motives are not integral to some presumably “pure” form of cognition. The ineliminable, often constructive role of values and motives in cognition was a point of great importance to philosophers like Neurath and John Dewey.

  5. For a recent reassessment of the discovery-justification distinction, see Schickore and Steinle (2006).

  6. The English version of Logik der Forschung appeared only in 1959 (Popper 1959), long after Popper had become the loudest voice in post-war British philosophy of science.

  7. For more on the North American background, see Reisch (2005), Howard (2003), and McCumber (2001). On Dewey, in particular, see Ryan (1995); on Cohen, see Hollinger (1975).

  8. Philosophers of science were not alone in failing to defend persecuted colleagues during the 1950s. On the response of the general philosophical community, see McCumber (2001), and for a still broader perspective, see Schrecker (1986). The situation of the sciences during the McCarthy period is the subject of Wang (1999).

  9. Pennock (2001) is a very helpful collection of views on the intelligent design controversy. On the role of the religious right in other controversies about science policy, see Kaplan (2004).

  10. For more on the politics of the “sound science” debate and the growing role of corporate lobbyists in science policy formation, see Mooney (2006).

  11. Golan (2004) is provides a comprehensive history of expert scientific testimony.

  12. Heilbron (1987) gives several examples of historians of science providing expert testimony regarding science policy.

  13. See the recent program solicitation from the National Science Foundation, “Science of Science and Innovation Policy” (SciSIP, NSF 07-547), http://www.nsf.gov/funding/pgm_summ.jsp?pims_id=501084

  14. One noteworthy exception is Susan Haack’s recent work on science in the courtroom, Haack (2003a, b).

  15. Schrader-Frechette (1993) is a rare and praiseworthy example of a philosopher’s substantive intervention in such public controversy. See also Schrader-Frechette (2007).

  16. Some philosophers of science have been thinking and arguing about the social dimensions of science for a long time; Longino (2006) is a helpful survey. But the question at issue here is that of developing a theory of science that empowers effective intervention in public debate.

  17. Ben-Menahem (2006) is provides a helpful, critical appraisal of arguments concerning underdetermination and conventionalism, more generally.

  18. Kitcher’s dismissal of the problem of permanent underdetermination (Kitcher 2001, 31–38) shares with other such (for example, Friedman 2001) the straw-man strategy of taking the thesis to assert that anything goes, that any of one’s favored doctrines can be defended, come what may by way of future evidence, and that there are no rational grounds upon which to distinguish alternative, empirically equivalent theories. Some who use underdetermination arguments to impugn the objectivity of science might argue thusly, but sober, science-friendly proponents of strong underdetermination theses like Duhem, Neurath, and Quine do not. One is tempted to say to Kitcher, “pick on somebody your own size.” Consider the Quinean version of the thesis. Quine emphasizes asymmetries in the “web of belief,” such as relative resistance to revision varying with distance from the center of the web (we don’t give up our logic easily), that provide the scientist with rational reasons for preferring one option to another. On this view, no principle is ever permanently immune to revision (why should it be?), but what drives the scientist’s choices is not just whim or prejudice. Nor does Quine assert that anything goes. What he asserts is that a cherished thesis can always be retained, as long as one is willing to make sufficiently drastic changes elsewhere in the web of belief. The problem for the anything-goes relativist is that the price one has to pay to maintain one’s pet principle is usually prohibitively high, as with denying what others see as obvious evidence. No proof from self-evident first principles will convict the persistent dogmatist of error in such cases, but it is one of several diseases peculiar to philosophers to think that only such proof suffices to secure the integrity of science. Why, in a contingent world, should one not be content with contingent safeguards for the integrity of science?

  19. Yet another factor complicating theory choice in the here and now is that the underdetermination often results not because two competing theories are empirically equivalent but because what one might term the “phenomenal domains” of the theories don’t coincide. One theory might have implications with respect to questions about which another theory is mute. Judgments about which are the important questions to address represent another moment of theory choice in which auxiliary motives might play a big role.

  20. For contrasting views on the question see Pielke et al. (2005) and Mann and Emanuel (2006).

  21. The project on “Wissenschaftstheorie im Anwendungsbereich” (“Philosophy of Science in the Domain of Application”) at Bielefeld University is a commendable if rare example of philosophers of science seeking to address the distinctive characteristics of applied science. Representative of the work emerging from this project is Carrier (2004).

  22. It was Albert Einstein who wrote, about the benefit of studying history and philosophy of science, “A knowledge of the historic and philosophical background gives that kind of independence from prejudices of his generation from which most scientists are suffering. This independence created by philosophical insight is—in my opinion—the mark of distinction between a mere artisan or specialist and a real seeker after truth” (Einstein to Robert Thornton, December 7, 1944, as quoted in Howard (2005), 34).

  23. See Mirowski (1989) for a critical discussion of the scientific pretensions of neo-classical economics.

  24. Fortunately, philosophers of science who think questions of justice relevant to a socialized theory of science have more resources upon which to draw than just the neo-liberalism of John Rawls (1971), which is Kitcher’s main resource (Kitcher 2001). Those making policy in a contingent, real, social world pervaded by interests of many kinds are little helped by an ideal model of rational calculators operating behind the veil of ignorance in the original position, a model that Neurath probably would have seen as just another example of pseudo-rationalism. One needs tools for theorizing interest. In this one respect, at least, Marx has the advantage over Rawls.

  25. Rudner’s argument was, just as famously, attacked in Levi (1960).

  26. Peterson (1984) is a classic source. For more recent overviews, see Chopyak and Levesque (2002) and Douglas (2005). For examples of philosophers of science tentatively exploring connections between game theory and norms, see Bicchieri et al. (1997).

  27. Some aspects of the reductionism and emergence controversy and the debate between solid state and particle physicists are discussed in Howard (2007).

  28. Kitcher (1996) is an impressive, and rare, example of a philosopher of science seriously engaging the revolution in applied molecular genetics.

  29. Okruhlik (1994) makes this point very persuasively.

  30. Only in 1994 was it mandated by NIH that women and minorities be represented in clinical trials. For overviews, see Caldwell et al. (2004), McMurdo et al. (2005), and Merkatz (1998).

  31. Herzog et al. (2001) provides a helpful review of the funding for research on renewable energy sources.

  32. One takes heart from recent growth of interest in value questions among philosophers of science. See, for example, Machamer and Wolters (2004), Kincaid et al. (2007), and Carrier et al. (2007).

  33. Early failures to replicate Boyle’s results are an important issue in Shapin and Schaffer (1985).

  34. A helpful, sober appraisal of this famously controversial episode can be found in Gliboff (2006).

  35. That we so easily advert to the view that “knowing” is the relevant epistemic modality in science, as opposed to something like “provisional acceptance” or “taking as pursuitworthy,” might be yet another legacy of the individualist bias in epistemology. After all, in the strictest sense, scientists do not know that space-time is curved, while there is general agreement within the relevant communities that this view, a consequence of general relativity, is the best one available at present. For more on the variety of epistemic modalities at play in science, see McKaughan (2007).

  36. Hardwig (1985) emphasizes the point about the large numbers of people involved in particle physics experiments. See Baird (2004) for an interesting discussion of the way in which, starting in the mid-20th century, the knowledge involved in the design, construction, and operation of scientific instrumentation tends to be black-boxed.

  37. No surprise, therefore, that Neurath (1932) contested the phenomenalism advocated by the Vienna Circle’s right wing in the context of the protocol-sentence debate during the early 1930s. For an analysis of the debate, see Zhai (1990).

  38. Boring (1929) is the classic history of the development of experimental psychology; see also Rieber et al. (1980). For recent philosophical and sociological perspectives, see Hatfield (1990) and Kusch (1995).

  39. Two helpful sources are Shimony and Nails (1987) and Kornblith (1994).

  40. See Biddle (2007) for a compelling argument that the important failures were institutional.

  41. Fuller’s unfortunate intervention on behalf of the defendants, hence on behalf of requiring the teaching of intelligent design in public schools, in the Katzmiller v. Dover case of 2005 (Tammy Kitzmiller, et al. v. Dover Area School District, et al. 400 F. Supp. 2d 707 (M.D. Pa. 2005)) demonstrates only too well how, from the point of view of serious defenders of the integrity of science, social critique can devolve into what one dogged defender dubs the “New Cynicism” (Haack 2007, 21). Fuller’s statement in the Kitzmiller v. Dover case, “Rebuttal of Dover Expert Reports,” a copy of which can be found at http://www2.ncseweb.org/kvd/experts/fuller.pdf, makes instructive reading.

  42. How to interpret the longer-term implications of Ward Churchill’s recent firing by the University of Colorado is not clear. One is distressed, however, by the alacrity with which charges of plagiarism and other academic misconduct, the subject of old rumors, were investigated and made the legal basis for his dismissal only after his ill-considered remarks about the 9/11 attacks. For a recent, somewhat comprehensive report, see the story about the firing in the July 24, 2007 issue of the Rocky Mountain News: http://www.rockymountainnews.com/drmn/local/article/0,1299,DRMN_15_5642650,00.html

  43. See also Kitcher (1993). The quibbler will say that realism is not a neo-positivist dogma. In fact, the relationship of realism to neo-positivism is more complicated than folklore suggests. Here, just three points out of a much-needed longer analysis: (1) Reichenbach, the teacher of Hilary Putnam (who made famous the “no-miracles” argument for realism), was, himself, a realist of sorts. (2) Thoughtful readers of Carl Hempel’s “The Theoretician’s Dilemma” (1958) all realized that the in-principle eliminabiltiy of theoretical terms promised by the Craig elimination theorem wouldn’t pose a dilemma for the anti-realist. (3) The call for the elimination of metaphysics from science does not entail anti-realism, and the dispensibility of theoretical terms, especially via individual, eliminative definitions, can be viewed as proof of possession of cognitive meaning, not lack of it.

  44. But see also the interesting later collection, Koertge (2005), where the temperature is a bit lower.

  45. See the opinion of Judge John E. Jones III in the Kitzmiller v. Dover case, a copy of which can be found here: http://www2.ncseweb.org/kvd/all_legal/2005-12-20_Kitzmiller_decision.pdf

  46. McLean v. Arkansas Board of Education, 529 F. Supp. 1255, 1258–1264 (ED Ark. 1982).

  47. This difficulty and the associated difficulty of specifying necessary and sufficient conditions for cognitive meaningfulness were old news by the 1980s; see, for example, Hempel (1950). Robert Pennock’s expert statement in the Kitzmiller v. Dover case, while arguing that intelligent design is not science, handles the demarcation question with more subtlety and nuance than one found in Ruse’s testimony in the Arkansas case. A copy of Pennock’s statement can be found here: http://www2.ncseweb.org/kvd/experts/pennock.pdf

References

  • Baird D (2004) Thing knowledge: a philosophy of scientific instruments. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell D (1960) The end of ideology: on the exhaustion of political ideas in the fifties. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Menahem Y (2006) Conventionalism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri C, Jeffrey R, Skyrms B (eds) (1997) The dynamics of norms. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Biddle J (2006) Socializing science: on the epistemic significance of the institutional context of science. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Notre Dame

  • Biddle J (2007) Lessons from the Vioxx Debacle: what the privatization of science can teach us about social epistemology. Social Epistemol 21:21–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackmore JT (1972) Ernst Mach. His life, work, and influence. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor D (1976) Knowledge and social imagery, 2nd edn. Routledge and K. Paul, London and Boston; University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1991

  • Boring EG (1929) A history of experimental psychology. Century, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner A (1990) Duhem. Science, réalité et apparence. La Relation entre philosophie et histoire dan l’œuvre de Pierre Duhem. J. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner A (2003) Les Origines françaises de la philosophie des science. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell P et al (2004) Clinical trials in children. Lancet 364:803–811

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier M (2004) Knowledge and control: on the bearing of epistemic values in applied science. In: Machamer P, Wolters G (eds) Science, values and objectivity. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 275–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier M, Howard D, Kourany J (eds) (2007) The challenge of the social and the pressure of practice: science and values revisited. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N et al (1996) Otto Neurath: philosophy between science and politics. Ideas in Context No. 38 Skinner et al (eds). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Chopyak J, Levesque P (2002) Public participation in science and technology decision making: trends for the future. Technol Soc 24:155–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Santillana G, Zilsel E (1941) The development of rationalism and empiricism. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol 2, No. 8. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Doell R, Longino HE (1988) Sex hormones and human behavior: a critique of the linear model. J Homosexual 15(3/4):55–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas H (2002) Robert Merton and the ethos of science. Paper presented at HOPOS 2004, the fifth international conference on the history of the philosophy of science. San Francisco, CA, June 24–27

  • Douglas H (2005) Inserting the public into science. In: Maasen S, Weingart P (eds) Democratization of expertise? Exploring novel forms of scientific advice in political decision-making. Sociology of the Sciences Yearbook, vol 24. Springer, Berlin, pp 153-159

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem P (1906) La Théorie physique. Son objet et sa structure. Chevalier & Rivière, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1975) Against method: outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. NLB, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1978) Science in a free society. NLB, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck L (1935) Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Schwabe und Co., Verlagsbuchhandlung, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank P (1953) The variety of reasons for the acceptance of scientific theories. In: Frank P (ed) The validation of scientific theories. Beacon Press, Boston, 1956. Reprint Collier Books, New York, 1961, pp 13–26

  • Frank P (1957) Philosophy of science: the link between science and philosophy. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (2001) Dynamics of reason: the 1999 Kant lectures at Stanford University. CSLI Publications, Stanford, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller S (1988) Social epistemology, 2nd ed. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 2002

    Google Scholar 

  • Golan T (2004) Laws of men and laws of nature: the history of scientific expert testimony in England and America. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gliboff S (2006) The case of Paul Kammerer: evolution and experimentation in the early 20th century. J Hist Biol 39:525–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A (1999) Knowledge in a social world. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross PR, Levitt N (1994) Higher superstition: the academic left and its quarrels with science. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (2003a) Trials and tribulations: science in the law. Daedalus 132(4):54–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (2003b) Inquiry and advocacy, fallibilism and finality: culture and inference in science and the law. Law Probabil Risk 2:205–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (2007) Defending science – within reason: between scientism and cynicism. Prometheus, Amherst, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson NR (1958) Patterns of discovery: an inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig J (1985) Epistemic dependence. J Philos 82:335–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield GC (1990) The natural and the normative: theories of spatial perception from Kant to Helmholtz. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbron JL (1987) Applied history of science. Isis 78:552–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel CG (1950) Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaningfulness. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 41(11):41–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel CG (1958) The theoretician’s dilemma: a study in the logic of theory construction. In: Feigl H, Scriven M, Maxwell G (eds) Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 2. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 37–98

  • Herzog AV et al (2001) Renewable energy: a viable choice. Environment 43(10):8–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollinger DA (1975) Morris R. Cohen and the scientific ideal. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard D (2003) Two left turns make a right: on the curious political career of North American philosophy of science at mid-century. In: Richardson A, Hardcastle G (eds) Logical empiricism in North America. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 25–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard D (2005) Albert Einstein as a philosopher of science. Phys Today 58(12):34–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard D (2007) Reduction and emergence in the physical sciences: some lessons from the particle physics and condensed matter debate. In: Murphy N, Stoeger WR (eds) Evolution and emergence: systems, organisms, persons. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 141–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaki SL (1987) Uneasy genius: the life and work of Pierre Duhem. Nijhoff, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan E (2004) With God on their side: how Christian fundamentalists trampled science, policy, and democracy in George W. Bush’s White House. New Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid H, Dupré J, Wylie A (eds) (2007) Value-free science? Ideals and illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1996) The lives to come: the genetic revolution and human possibilities. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (2001) Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge N (ed) (1998) A house built on sand: exposing postmodernist myths about science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertge N (ed) (2005) Scientific values and civic virtues. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith H (ed) (1994) Naturalizing epistemology, 2d ed. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M (1995) Psychologism: a case study in the sociology of philosophical knowledge. Routledge, London and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M (2002) Knowledge by agreement: the programme of communitarian epistemology. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Laudan L (1982) Commentary: science at the bar – causes for concern. Sci Technol Human Values 7(41):16–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenin, VI (1909) [Materializm i empiriokrititsizm. Kriticheskie zametki ob odnoi reaktsionnoi filosofii]. Moscow: Zveno. English translation: Materialism and empirio-criticism: critical comments on a reactionary philosophy. Foreign Languages Publishing House, Moscow, 1952

  • Levi I (1960) Must the scientist make value judgments? J Philos 57:345–357

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (1990) Science as social knowledge: values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (2002) The fate of knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (2006) The social dimensions of scientific knowledge. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2006 Edition). URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/scientific-knowledge-social/

  • Machamer P, Wolters G (eds) (2004) Science, values and objectivity. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

  • Mann ME, Emanuel K (2006) Atlantic hurricane trends linked to climate change. Eos Trans Am Geophys Soc 87:233–244

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim K (1929) Ideologie und Utopie. Bonn: F. Cohen. English translation: Ideology and Utopia: an introduction to the sociology of knowledge. Wirth L and Shils E (trans). K. Paul, Trench, Trubner, London; Harcourt, Brace, New York, 1936

  • Martin RND (1991) Pierre Duhem: philosophy and history in the work of a believing physicist. Open Court, La Salle, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • McCumber J (2001) Time in the ditch: American philosophy and the McCarthy era. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL

    Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan DJ (2007) Toward a richer vocabulary for epistemic attitudes: mapping the cognitive landscape. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Notre Dame

  • McMurdo MET, Witham MD, Gillespie ND (2005) Including older people in clinical research: benefits shown in trials in younger people may not apply to older people. Brit Med J 331:1036–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merkatz RB (1998) Inclusion of women in clinical trials: a historical overview of scientific, ethical, and legal issues. J Obstetr Gynecol Neonat Nurs 27:78–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton RK (1938a) Science and the social order. Philos Sci 5:321–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton RK (1938b) Science, technology and society in seventeenth century England. In: Sarton G (ed) Osiris: studies on the history and philosophy of science and on the history of learning and culture. St. Catherine Press, Bruges, Belgium, pp 362–632

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton RK (1942) Science and technology in a democratic social order. J Legal Polit Sociol 1:115–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski PE (1989) More heat than light: economics as social physics. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mooney CC (2006) The Republican war on science. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemeth E, Stadler F (eds) (1996) Encylopedia and Utopia: the life and work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945). Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, No. 4. Kluwer, Dordrecht, Boston, and London

  • Neurath O (1913) Die Verirrten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv. Zur Psychologie des Entschlusses. Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien. Johann Ambrosius Barth, Leipzig. English translation: The Lost Wanderers of Descartes and the Auxiliary Motive (On the Psychology of Decision). In Otto Neurath. Philosophical Papers, 1913–1946. Cohen RS and Neurath M (eds) and trans. Vienna Circle Collection, vol. 16. Mulder HL, Cohen RS and McGuinness B (eds). Dordrecht, Boston, and Lancaster: D. Reidel, 1983, pp 1–12

  • Neurath O (1930) Einheitswissenschaft und Marxismus. Erkenntnis 1:75

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath O (1932) Protokollsätze. Erkenntnis 3:204–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath O (1935) Pseudorationalismus der Falsifikation. Erkenntnis 5:353–365

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okruhlik K (1994) Gender and the biological sciences. Biol Soc Can J Philos Supplementary volume 20:21–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Overbye D (2007) At Fermilab, the race is on for the ‘God particle.’ New York Times (National Edition), July 24, 2007, D1,4

  • Pennock RT (ed) (2001) Intelligent design, creationism, and its critics: philosophical, theological, and scientific perspectives. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson JC (1984) Citizen participation in science policy. University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Pielke R et al (2005) Hurricanes and global warming. Bull Am Meteorol Soc 86:1571–1575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1935) Logik der Forschung. Zur Erkenntnistheorie der modernen Naturwissenschaft. Julius Springer, Vienna

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1945) The open society and its enemies. G. Routledge & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchinson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1951) Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review 60, 20–43. Reprinted in: From a logical point of view. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1953, pp 20–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1969) Epistemology naturalized. In: Ontological relativity and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 69–90

  • Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1938) Experience and prediction: an analysis of the foundations and the structure of knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1951) The rise of scientific philosophy. University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch GA (2005) How the cold war transformed philosophy of science: to the icy slopes of logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieber RW et al (eds) (1980) Wilhelm Wundt and the making of a scientific psychology. Plenum, New York

  • Rudner R (1953) The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philos Sci 20:1–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1982) Creation science is not science. Sci Technol Human Values 7(40):72–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan A (1995) John Dewey and the high tide of american liberalism. W.W. Norton, New York and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) (2006) Revisiting discovery and justification: historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt F (ed) (1994) Socializing epistemology: the social dimensions of knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrader-Frechette K (1993) Burying uncertainty: risk and the case against geological disposal of nuclear waste. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrader-Frechette K (2007) Taking action, saving lives: our duties to protect environmental and public health. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrecker E (1986) No ivory tower: McCarthyism and the universities. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin S, Schaffer S (1985) Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony A, Nails D (eds) (1987) Naturalistic epistemology: a symposium of two decades. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal AD (1996) Transgressing the boundaries: toward a transformative hermeneutics of quantum gravity. Social Text No. 46/47 (Spring/Summer 1996), pp 217–252

  • Sokal AD, Bricmont J (1998) Fashionable nonsense: postmodern intellectuals’ abuse of science. Picador USA, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon M (2001) Social empiricism. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler F (1997) Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Ursprung, Entwicklung und Wirkung des Logischen Empirismus im Kontext. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt. English translation: The vienna circle: studies in the origins, development, and influence of logical empiricism. Springer-Verlag, Vienna and New York, 2001

  • Toulmin S (1953) The philosophy of science: an introduction. Hutchinson & Co, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin S (1961) Foresight and understanding: an enquiry into the aims of science. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel T (1992) Overcoming logical positivism from within: the emergence of Neurath’s naturalism in the vienna circle’s protocol sentence debate. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel T (2000) Vernunftkritik und Wissenschaft. Otto Neurath und die ersten Wiener Kreis. Springer, Vienna

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen BC (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang J (1999) American science in an age of anxiety: scientists, anticommunism, and the cold war. University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar S (1988) Science, the very idea. Routledge, London and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhai Z (1990) The problem of protocol statements and Schlick’s concept of ‘Konstatierungen.’ In: PSA 1990: proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, vol 1.Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, MI, pp 15–23

  • Zilsel E (1926) Die Entstehung des Geniebegriffes. Ein Beitrag zur Ideengeschichte der Antike und des Frühkapitalismus. Mohr, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Don Howard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Howard, D. Better Red than Dead—Putting an End to the Social Irrelevance of Postwar Philosophy of Science. Sci & Educ 18, 199–220 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9117-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9117-3

Keywords

Navigation