Skip to main content
Log in

Against simplicity

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sometimes metaphysicians appeal to simplicity as a reason to prefer one metaphysical theory to another, especially when a philosophical dispute has otherwise reached a state of equilibrium. In this paper, I show that given a Quinean conception of metaphysics, several initially plausible justifications for simplicity as a metaphysical criterion do not succeed. If philosophers wish to preserve simplicity as a metaphysical criterion, therefore, they must radically reconceive the project of metaphysics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Hirsch argues that all metaphysical disputes are really verbal disputes (2009, 2005). Bennett argues that while metaphysical disputes are substantive, there are nevertheless some debates that have reached a point of equilibrium such that they cannot be resolved on metaphysical grounds; Willard argues that structural features of the practice of metaphysics make it reasonable to believe that all metaphysical disputes are not resolvable (Bennett 2009; Willard 2013).

  2. Thanks to L. A. Paul and Michaela McSweeney for conversations and questions that inspired this paper; Heather Demarest and Jonathan Schaffer for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper; and, Rachael Briggs, Jason Turner, Daniel Korman, Lina Jansson, Ishani Maitra and participants at the 2013 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference for a vigorous and fruitful discussion.

  3. Adapted from Schaffer (2009, 366).

  4. Thanks to Louis deRosset and Michaela McSweeney for pressure on this point.

  5. Huemer (2009, 223–224) discusses a similar (although not a priori) argument, according to which simpler models are more likely to be confirmed or disconfirmed. Suppose that the data to be explained is the wobble in the orbit of Uranus, and we consider the merits of postulating one planet, Neptune, as Leverrier did, over postulating eighty-three planets, which no one did. If we postulate one planet, we can explain the evidence by adjusting the mass and orbit of Neptune; if we postulate eighty-three, we can explain it by adjusting the mass and orbit of all of the postulated planetlets.

    The one-planet theory takes a risk, for it would be refuted by any observations that required more planets. The eighty-three planet theory plays it safe, spreading its possibility over a larger range of possible observations. This means, however, given the actual observations, that the simple theory is more probable.

  6. Though see Huemer (2009) for reasons to think that simplicity is not a driving consideration even in ordinary reasoning.

  7. Thanks to both Heather Demarest and Jonathan Schaffer for encouraging me to consider this possible response.

  8. Thanks to Heather Demarest and Jonathan Schaffer for encouraging me to clarify this point, and to Heather for the apt formulation of the problem with premise (17).

  9. See Della Rocca (2000) for some reasons to think that once one accepts explicability arguments with respect to existence, one must accept the full-blown principle of sufficient reason.

References

  • Baker, A. (2003). Quantitative parsimony and explanatory power. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 54, 245–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2009). Composition, colocation, and metaontology. In D. J. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 38–76). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Rocca, M. (2000). PSR. Philosopher’s Imprint, 10(7), 1–13.

  • Hirsch, E. (2005). Physical-object ontology, verbal disputes, and common sense. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXX(1), 67–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2009). Ontology and alternative languages. In D. J. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 231–259). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2009). When is parsimony a virtue? Philosophical Quarterly, 59(235), 216–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (2001). Counterfactuals (2nd ed.). Blackwell: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1966). On simple theories of a complex world. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), The ways of paradox (pp. 242–245). New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. J. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the past: parsimony, evolution, and inference. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1997). Simplicity as evidence of truth. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willard, M. B. (2013). Game called on account of fog: Metametaphysics and epistemic dismissivism. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-013-0097-7.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to M. B. Willard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Willard, M.B. Against simplicity. Philos Stud 167, 165–181 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0228-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0228-1

Keywords

Navigation