Skip to main content
Log in

Iconic pragmatics

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent comparative semantics suggests that sign language makes use of the same logical resources as spoken language, but has richer mechanisms of iconic enrichment. It is often thought that when speech is analyzed in tandem with iconic gestures, ‘expressive parity’ is regained between speech and sign. But this comparison between sign-with-iconicity and speech-with-gestures turns out to be complex because iconic enrichments often have a non-at-issue status, as attested by their interaction with logical operators. We argue that the status of iconic enrichments is constrained by two parameters: ±internal, ±separate_time_slot. If an enrichment is effected by the internal modification of an expression (+internal)—e.g. by lengthening the word loooong in English, or the sign GROW in ASL—it can have any semantic status and can in particular be at-issue. If an enrichment is an external addition to an expression (-internal)—as is the case of co-speech gestures in English—it does not make an at-issue contribution, but it may have the status of a presupposition or of a supplement. If an enrichment has a separate time slot (+separate_time_slot), it may not be trivial (= presupposed), and must thus be at-issue or supplemental. The generalization is assessed on the basis of vocal iconicity in spoken language, iconic modulations in sign language, co-speech/co-sign as well as post-speech/post-sign gestures and facial expressions in spoken and sign language, and also gestures that fully replace words in spoken language. Our typology suggests that there are systematic expressive differences between sign-with-iconicity and speech-with-gestures, and also that the semantic status of iconic enrichments can in part be predicted by parameters pertaining to their form.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the terminological side, we follow Goldin-Meadow and Brentari (to appear) in sometimes referring to spoken language as ‘speech’ and to sign language as ‘sign’.

  2. This claim is a bit less obvious than it might seem. First, there are numerous mouthings in sign language, which can be accompanied with sounds, including when produced by deaf signers. Second, assessing the claim would require that one study both deaf and hearing signers.

  3. Our claims are restricted to the projection of iconic enrichments. Thus we do not seek to explain how iconic meanings arise in the first place (but see for instance Ortega et al. to appear, on similarities between sign and gesture iconicity). And we cannot exclude the possibility that non-iconic gestures make different kinds of contributions. For instance, Dohen and Loevenbruck (2009) show that raised eyebrows play a role in focus interpretation in spoken language; these are not iconic gestures and thus fall outside of our generalizations.

  4. Okrent (2002) provides several examples of vocal iconicity:

    1. (i)
      1. a.

        It was a looooong time.

      2. b.

        The bird flew up [high pitch] and down [low pitch].

      3. c.

        Work, work, work, rest.

    For recent discussions of vocal iconicity, see for instance Clark et al. (2013), Perlman and Cain (to appear), and Grenoble et al. (2015).

  5. The discussion of GROW borrows from Schlenker et al. (2013).

  6. Briefly, a cosupposition is a presupposition which is conditionalized on the at-issue contribution of the expression it modifies. For instance, Did John punish his son? does not trigger the presupposition that John slapped his son, but that if he punished his son, slapping was involved. A more detailed definition is given in Sect. 3.2.

  7. This is only a first approximation. One key issue in the future will be to distinguish optional modifiers from supplemental ones, since there is a sense in which both types can be eliminated without yielding syntactic unacceptability. In Schlenker (2010, 2013) it is argued that appositive relative clauses have a rather special syntax, which allows them to be attached to any propositional node that dominates their surface position—with the result that matrix appositives could be removed without changing anything to the syntactic tree to which they are attached. (By contrast, eliminating a standard modifier would remove a node from the expression it modifies.)

  8. One could test whether an inference is obtained when a high pitch is applied to fly away, as in (i)—with the advantage that in this case the verb does not by itself trigger the inference that might be independently obtained because of the iconic modulation.

    1. (i)

      The bird [flew away]_<high_pitch>.

  9. This is a sufficiently important inference that some animals apparently evolved mechanisms—specifically, laryngeal descent—to lower their vocal-tract resonant frequencies so as to exaggerate their perceived size (Fitch and Reby 2001).

  10. It is quite possible (as Pasternak observes) that high pitch can in this case trigger what we call a cosupposition, i.e. a conditionalized presupposition of the form: if Johnny were to talk, he would talk with a high-pitched voice. This is in particular suggested by the universal inference that is arguably obtained in (i):

    1. (i)

      None of these ten guys will start talking_<high-pitched>.

      => for each of these ten guys, if he talks, he does so in a high-pitched voice

  11. We do not claim that speed modulations of the sign necessarily trigger inferences about the speed of the event; less direct interpretations might be obtained pertaining for instance to the difficulty of accomplishing a particular action.

  12. We disregard two further conditions, which involved repeated singular nouns; these were also interpreted in a highly iconic fashion.

  13. We checked in the 4th judgment task that these sentences do not trigger any inference to the effect that if there are trophies, they should be arranged in a particular way; in other words, there is no ‘projection’ outside of the conditional of the inference pertaining to the arrangement of the relevant objects.

  14. Schlenker et al. (2013) write that they “asked the consultant to provide acceptability judgments in the best context he could imagine for the sentence; this matters because the use of high or low loci in an ‘out of the blue’ context would normally yield deviance.”

  15. Schlenker et al. (2013) provide preliminary data from ASL that suggest that height specifications of loci also resemble gender features of pronouns in that they trigger presuppositions that are indexical, i.e. evaluated with respect to the context of utterance rather than to the world of evaluation. We disregard this more subtle point here.

  16. This section, as well as the following two sections, borrow from Schlenker (to appear b).

  17. One cautionary note might be helpful at the outset, however. Presuppositions can, at some cost, undergo ‘local accommodation’, with the result that their content is treated as an at-issue meaning component (e.g. Heim 1983). We come back to this issue in Sect. 5.3.

  18. Since this is a demonstrative, it denotes something which is made salient by the context—here the action evoked by the accompanying gesture. The semantics of this need not involve explicit gestures, however, and thus it must be handled by a theory of context dependency that does not reduce to gesture semantics.

  19. In some embedded environments, a sentence such as John won’t help his son like this could trigger an implicature because it has a structurally simpler alternative John won’t help his son. Since the latter is more informative, scalar reasoning yields the inference that it is false, hence an implicature that John will help his son. For simplicity, we disregard implicatures in the present discussion.

  20. In principle, one could profitably investigate the role of vocal enrichments in sign language (in hearing native signers). These would genuinely be the analogue of co-speech gestures in spoken language. We leave this question for future research.

  21. As noted in (55)c, on occasion the inference is not just that it is bad/difficult for poor states to spend money, but for states in general. This might be part of a more general issue in the study of presupposition, called the Proviso Problem: in many cases, presuppositions that are predicted by dynamic semantics to be conditional in nature get strengthened (here, we predict an inference of the form: if a state is poor, it is bad/difficult for that state to spend money; this is strengthened to: it is bad/difficult for states to spend money). See Schlenker (to appear b) for further discussion, and see Beaver and Geurts (2014) and Schlenker (2016a) for surveys of presupposition theory that discuss the Proviso Problem.

  22. The inference might be strengthened to ‘it is bad for states in general to spend money’, or even: ‘spending money is bad’. As noted in fn. 21, this falls under the ‘Proviso Problem’, i.e. the observation that presuppositions are sometimes stronger than is predicted by standard dynamic analyses.

  23. Thanks to Larry Horn for helpful remarks on this topic.

  24. We tested examples involving the one-handed sign for COOL performed with the gesture for a big belly, with some projection effects—but not ones that are captured by theories under discussion here.

  25. See Esipova (2016a, 2016b) for further discussion of this matter in connection with possibilities (or lack thereof) of local accommodation of inferences triggered by facial expressions.

  26. This section borrows from Sect. 4.2.1 of Schlenker (to appear b).

  27. Thanks to Miloje Despić for making this suggestion.

  28. Note that here and in the other b-examples one might expect a slight pragmatic oddity with likely because this expression implicates that it’s not established that the relevant event took place, whereas the which-clause presupposes its existence. But in any event the version of the sentence with unlikely is far worse.

  29. Thanks to Cornelia Ebert (p.c.) for discussion of this point.

  30. This section borrows from Sect. 4.2.2 of Schlenker (to appear b).

  31. This section borrows from Sect. 4.2.2 of Schlenker (to appear b).

  32. One possible way to develop the theory (possibly along Krifka’s lines) would be to take the pronoun \(\mathit{pro} _{i}\) in (85) to be a definite description of events, one that triggers a presupposition to the effect that the relevant events exist. (I believe this point was made by seminar participants at NYU in Fall 2016.)

  33. In this respect, co-speech gestures resemble height specifications of sign language loci, as studied by Schlenker et al. (2013) and Schlenker (2014).

  34. In fact, in (95)b triggers another shape-related presupposition, namely that the subject denotes a helicopter: if helicopters is replaced with aircraft in (97)b, we get an inference that each of the aircraft is a helicopter.

  35. See Schlenker and Chemla (to appear) for an attempt to use pro-speech gestures to replicate within English some properties of sign language object agreement verbs.

  36. Exceptions include the presuppositional particles too and again.

  37. The proposal in Schlenker (2013) was that supplements should be non-trivial in their local context, but they should be ‘easy’ to accommodate, in the sense that the global context C could ‘easily’ be turned into a strengthened context C+ relative to which a supplement becomes locally trivial.

  38. It must be kept in mind, however, that our comparison between speech and sign was not fully minimal. In particular, we investigated a variety of co-speech gestures, but very few co-sign gestures: only facial expressions fulfilled this function. As emphasized by Esipova (p.c.), it cannot be excluded that these make a special contribution due to their semantics rather than to their co-sign status, and thus further gestures should be investigated in sign language.

References

  • Abrusán, Márta. 2011. Predicting the presuppositions of soft triggers. Linguistics and Philosophy 34(6): 491–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrusan, Marta. 2016. Presupposition cancellation: Explaining the ‘soft–hard’ trigger distinction. Natural Language Semantics 24(2): 165–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abusch, Dorit. 2010. Presupposition triggering from alternatives. Journal of Semantics 27(1): 37–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, David. 2001. Presupposition and assertion in dynamic semantics. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, David. 2010. Have you noticed that your belly button lint colour is related to the colour of your clothing? In Presupposition: Papers in honor of Hans Kamp, eds. Rainer Bäuerle, Uwe Reyle, and Thomas E. Zimmerman. Bingley: Emerald.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, David I., and Bart Geurts. 2014. Presupposition. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2014 edn., ed. Edward N. Zalta. Available at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/presupposition/. Accessed 19 November 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Büring, Daniel. 2012. Focus and intonation. In Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, eds. Gillian Russell and Delia Graff Fara, 103–115. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemla, Emmanuel. 2009. Presuppositions of quantified sentences: Experimental data. Natural Language Semantics 17(4): 299–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Herbert H. 1996. Using language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Nathaniel, Marcus Perlman, and Marlene Johansson Falck. 2013. Iconic pitch expresses vertical space. In Language and the creative mind, eds. Barbara Dancygier, Mike Borkent, and Jennifer Hinnell, 393–410. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, Ian, and Ghofur E. Woodruff. 2008. Music as a communicative medium. In The prehistory of language, eds. Rudolf Botha and Chris Knight. Vol. 1, 113–144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Brabanter, Philippe. 2010. Uttering sentences made up of words and gestures. In Explicit communication: Essays on Robyn Carston’s pragmatics, eds. Belén Soria and Esther Romero, 199–216. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dingemanse, Mark. 2012. Advances in the cross-linguistic study of ideophones. Language and Linguistics Compass 6(10): 654–672. doi:10.1002/lnc3.361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dingemanse, Mark, and Kimi Akita. 2016. An inverse relation between expressiveness and grammatical integration: On the morphosyntactic typology of ideophones, with special reference to Japanese. Journal of Linguistics 53(3): 501–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dingemanse, Mark, Will Schuerman, Eva Reinisch, Sylvia Tufvesson, and Holger Mitterer. 2016. What sound symbolism can and cannot do: Testing the iconicity of ideophones from five languages. Language 92(2): e117–e133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dohen, Marion, and Hélène Loevenbruck. 2009. Interaction of audition and vision for the perception of prosodic contrastive focus. Language and Speech 52(2–3): 177–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, Cornelia, and Christian Ebert. 2014. Gestures, demonstratives, and the attributive/referential distinction. Handout of a talk given at Semantics and Philosophy in Europe (SPE) 7, Berlin.

  • Esipova, Maria. 2016a. Alternatives matter: Contrastive focus and presupposition projection in standard triggers and co-speech gestures. Poster presented at MACSIM 6, CUNY.

  • Esipova, Maria. 2016b. Presuppositions under contrastive focus: Standard triggers and co-speech gestures. Ms., New York University.

  • Fauconnier, Gilles. 1985. Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, Tecumseh W., and David Reby. 2001. The descended larynx is not uniquely human. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 268: 1669–1675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricke, Ellen. 2008. Grundlagen einer multimodalen Grammatik des Deutschen: Syntaktische Strukturen und Funktionen. Habilitation treatise. Frankfurt (Oder): European University Viadrina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, Bart. 1994. Presupposing. PhD dissertation. Universität Osnabrück.

  • Goldin-Meadow, Susan, and Diane Brentari. to appear. Gesture, sign and language: The coming of age of sign language and gesture studies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.

  • Greenberg, Gabriel. 2013. Beyond resemblance. Philosophical Review 122(2): 215–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grenoble, Lenore A., Martina Martinovic, and Rebekah Baglini. 2015. Verbal gestures in Wolof. In 44th Annual Conference on African Linguistics (ACAL), eds. Ruth Kramer et al., 110–121. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. In Second West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL), eds. Daniel Flickinger et al., 114–125. Reprinted 1991 in Pragmatics: A reader, ed. Steven Davis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, Robert. 2016. Pluractional demonstrations. Ms., University of Arizona. Available at http://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/003127. Accessed 19 November 2017.

  • Kegl, Judy. 1977/2004. ASL syntax: Research in progress and proposed research. Sign Language and Linguistics 7(2). Reprint of an MIT manuscript written in 1977.

  • Kuhn, Jeremy. 2015. Cross-categorial singular and plural reference in sign language. PhD diss., New York University.

  • Kuhn, Jeremy, and Valentina Aristodemo. 2016. Pluractionality, iconicity, and scope in French sign language. Ms., Institut Jean-Nicod.

  • Ladewig, Silva. 2011. Syntactic and semantic integration of gestures into speech: Structural, cognitive, and conceptual aspects. PhD diss., European University Viadrina, Frankfurt (Oder).

  • Lewis, David. 1975. Adverbs of quantification. In Formal semantics of natural language, ed. Edward L. Keenan, 3–15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Liddell, Scott K. 2003. Grammar, gesture, and meaning in American sign language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lillo-Martin, Diane, and Edward S. Klima. 1990. Pointing out differences: ASL pronouns in syntactic theory. In Theoretical issues in sign language research, vol. 1: linguistics, eds. Susan D. Fischer and Patricia Siple, 191–210. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ohala, John J. 1994. The frequency code underlies the sound-symbolic use of voice pitch. In Sound symbolism, eds. Leanne Hinton, Johanna Nichols, and John J. Ohala, 325–347. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okrent, Arika. 2002. A modality-free notion of gesture and how it can help us with the morpheme vs. gesture question in sigh language linguistics, or at least give us some criteria to work with. In Modality and structure in signed and spoken language, eds. Richard P. Meier, David G. Quinto-Pozos, and Kearsy A. Cormier, 175–198. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ortega, Gerardo, Annika Schiefner, and Aslo Özyürek. to appear. Speakers’ gestures predict the meaning and perception of iconicity in signs. In 39th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (CogSci 2017).

  • Perlman, Marcus, and Ashley Cain. to appear. Iconicity in vocalizations, comparisons with gesture, and implications for the evolution of language. Gesture 14(3): 320–350.

  • Potts, Christopher. 2005. The logic of conventional implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2007. Anti-dynamics: Presupposition projection without dynamic semantics. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16(3): 325–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2008. Be articulate: A pragmatic theory of presupposition projection. Theoretical Linguistics 34(3): 157–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2009. Local contexts. Semantics and Pragmatics 3: 1–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2010. Supplements within a unidimensional semantics, I: scope. In Logic, language and meaning: 17th Amsterdam colloquium, eds. Maria Aloni, Harald Bastiaanse, Tikitu de Jager, and Katrin Schulz, 74–83. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2013. Supplements within a unidimensional semantics, II: Epistemic status and projection. In 40th annual meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS), eds. Seda Kan, Claire Moore-Cantwell, and Robert Staubs. Vol. 2, 167–182. Amherst: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2014. Iconic features. Natural Language Semantics 22(4): 299–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2015. Gestural presuppositions (squib). Snippets 30. doi:10.7358/snip-2015-030-schl.

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2016a. The semantics/pragmatics interface. In The Cambridge handbook of formal semantics, eds. Maria Aloni and Paul Dekker, 664–727. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2016b. Gesture projection within the Transparency theory. Ms., Institut Jean-Nicod and New York University.

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2017a. Sign language and the foundations of anaphora. Annual Review of Linguistics 3: 149–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2017b. Outline of music semantics. Music Perception: An Interdisciplinary Journal 35(1): 3–37. doi:10.1525/mp.2017.35.1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. to appear a. Visible meaning: Sign language and the foundations of semantics. Theoretical Linguistics.

  • Schlenker, Philippe. to appear b. Gesture projection and cosuppositions. Linguistics and Philosophy.

  • Schlenker, Philippe. to appear c. Super monsters, II. Semantics and Pragmatics.

  • Schlenker, Philippe. to appear d. Prolegomena to music semantics. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. Accepted with revisions.

  • Schlenker, Philippe, and Emmanuel Chemla. to appear. Gestural agreement. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory.

  • Schlenker, Philippe, and Jonathan Lamberton. 2016. Iconic plurality. Ms., Institut Jean-Nicod and New York University.

  • Schlenker, Philippe, Jonathan Lamberton, and Mirko Santoro. 2013. Iconic variables. Linguistics and Philosophy 36(2): 91–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Mandy. 2001. On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In Semantics and linguistic theory, eds. R. Hastings, B. Jackson, and Z. Zvolenszky. Vol. 11. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Mandy. 2003. Presupposition and accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture. Philosophical Studies 112: 251–278. doi:10.1023/A:1023004203043.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, Mandy, David Beaver, Craige Roberts, and Judith Tonhauser. 2017. The best question: Explaining the projection behavior of factives, eds. Anton Benz and Katja Jasinskaja. Discourse Processes 54(3): 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slama-Cazacu, Tatiana. 1976. Nonverbal components in message sequence: “Mixed syntax”. In Language and man: Anthropological issues, eds. William C. McCormack and Stephen A. Wurm, 217–227. Mouton: The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprouse, J., and D. Almeida. 2012. Assessing the reliability of textbook data in syntax: Adger’s Core Syntax. Journal of Linguistics 48: 609–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprouse, J., and D. Almeida. 2013. The empirical status of data in syntax: A reply to Gibson and Fedorenko. Language and Cognitive Processes 28: 222–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprouse, J., C. T. Schütze, and D. Almeida. 2013. A comparison of informal and formal acceptability judgments using a random sample from Linguistic Inquiry 2001–2010. Lingua 134: 219–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 1974. Pragmatic presuppositions. In Semantics and philosophy, eds. Milton Munitz and Peter Unger. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strickland, Brent, Carlo Geraci, Emmanuel Chemla, Philippe Schlenker, Meltem Kelepir, and Roland Pfau. 2015. Event representations constrain the structure of language: Sign language as a window into universally accessible linguistic biases. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 112(19): 5968–5973. Available at http://www.pnas.org/content/112/19/5968. Accessed 19 November 2017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tieu, Lyn, Robert Pasternak, Philippe Schlenker, and Emmanuel Chemla. 2017. Co-speech gesture projection: Evidence from inferential judgments. Ms., LSCP, IJN, NYU and Stony Brook University.

  • Tieu, Lyn, Robert Pasternak, Philippe Schlenker, and Emmanuel Chemla. to appear. Co-speech gesture projection: Evidence from truth-value judgment and picture selection tasks. Glossa.

  • Wilbur, Ronnie B. 2003. Representations of telicity in ASL. Chicago Linguistic Society 39: 354–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilbur, Ronnie B. 2008. Complex predicates involving events, time and aspect: Is this why sign languages look so similar? In Signs of the time, ed. Josep Quer, 217–250. Hamburg: Signum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilbur, Ronnie B., and Evie Malaia. 2008. Event visibility hypothesis: Motion capture evidence for overt marking of telicity in ASL. Chicago: Linguistic Society of America.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

ASL consultant: Jonathan Lamberton. Special thanks to Jonathan Lamberton, who provided exceptionally fine-grained data throughout this research, and corrected the ASL transcriptions; his contribution as a consultant was considerable.

I am particularly grateful to the following colleagues for discussions and objections: Diane Brentari, Dylan Bumford, Emmanuel Chemla, Caterina Donati, Masha Esipova, Susan Goldin-Meadow, Gabe Greenberg, Jeremy Kuhn, Salvador Mascarenhas, Rob Pasternak, Matthew Stone, Brent Strickland, as well as the participants of my seminar at NYU in Fall 2016. Special thanks to Rob Pasternak for discussion of numerous data points. Thanks also to Lucie Ravaux for checking averages and working on the bibliography. All remaining errors are mine.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philippe Schlenker.

Additional information

Grant acknowledgments: The research leading to these results received funding from the European Research Council under the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP/2007-2013)/ERC Grant Agreement N°324115–FRONTSEM (PI: Schlenker). Research was conducted at Institut d’Etudes Cognitives, Ecole Normale Supérieure—PSL Research University. Institut d’Etudes Cognitives is supported by grants ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC et ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL.

Electronic Supplementary Material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(DOCX 115 kB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schlenker, P. Iconic pragmatics. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 36, 877–936 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9392-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9392-x

Keywords

Navigation