Skip to main content
Log in

What Is the Question to which Anti-Natalism Is the Answer?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The ethics of biological procreation has received a great deal of attention in recent years. Yet, as I show in this paper, much of what has come to be called procreative ethics is conducted in a strangely abstract, impersonal mode, one which stands little chance of speaking to the practical perspectives of any prospective parent. In short, the field appears to be flirting with a strange sort of practical irrelevance, wherein its verdicts are answers to questions that no-one is asking. I go on to articulate a theory of what I call existential grounding, a notion which explains the role that prospective children play in the lives of many would-be parents. Procreative ethicists who want their work to have real practical relevance must, I claim, start to engage with this markedly first-personal kind of practical consideration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I owe this more general idea to R.G. Collingwood, who believed that propositions are not fully understood unless seen in light of the questions they are meant to answer. See (Collingwood 1939, pp. 25–43).

  2. See (Korsgaard 1996; Nagel 1989; Williams 1985; Wolf 1997). For a canonical discussion of this general issue, see (Scheffler 1994)

  3. The question of how reflection on ethical propositions can issue in intentions was most influentially articulated by Aristotle. In recent meta-ethics, it has come to be known as “the normative question”. (Aristotle 2009, p. 1147a; Dreier 2015; Korsgaard 1996) I add the qualifier “rational” in my description because it is not clear that a moral philosopher has to explain how moral considerations can motivate any agent; most philosophers in this area will concede that this explanatory burden only exists for agents who meet certain minimal standards. Even the fairly skeptical Williams granted that an agent may be totally unmoved by their own overriding reasons if they lack certain cognitive or imaginative capacities. (Williams 1981) I am grateful to Mona Simion for discussion of this point.

  4. For various discussions of what has been called the “overridingness” question, see (Archer 2014; Black and Tiffany 2011; Portmore 2008; Stroud 1998; Tanyi 2012; Williams 1981). See also Sam Scheffler’s Human Morality, ch.3 (Scheffler 1992).

  5. A principal exception is Christine Overall. The final chapter in her Why Have Children? has the virtue of not automatically treating the moral and the practical questions as though they were identical, and openly discusses meaningfulness, authenticity and identity. (Overall 2012)

  6. See (McMahan 2009).

  7. In saying this, I am not asserting that the badness of a possible-future person’s life should never weigh in our deliberations. My argument here merely concerns the form of the comparative question that is being asked: if we are to include such possible-future persons in our deliberation about whether to make them actual, we necessarily compare worlds and not lives.

  8. Of course, many parents have children to ensure their own well-being as they enter old age. But this is not the kind of consideration that Gheaus cites. Rather, she focuses solely on the well-being of humanity in general.

  9. For example, The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy published an entire issue on methodology in applied ethics in 2000. While the authors differed in many respects, the editor noted that every contributor to the issue shared the assumptions that “bioethics is about resolving cases, not about moral theory, and that the best method of bioethical decision-making is that which produces useful answers.” (Smith Iltis 2000)

  10. Perhaps more charitably, these philosophers may be offering arguments in favor of certain state policies, such as China’s well-known one-child policy. If this is so, then they should be far more explicit about this, and drop any references to moral censure and blame, to rightness, wrongness, permissibility or impermissibility. If, for example, MacIver’s point is simply that governments have strong reasons to discourage reproduction, reasons grounded in resource-scarcity, then he should simply say so, and not insist that procreators are subject to “moral censure”.

  11. This is roughly the tension to which Williams was referring when he said: “We can dream of a philosophy that would be thoroughly truthful and honestly helpful. This, of course, implies an impossible combination of characteristics.” (Williams 2000, 212).

  12. Once again, I wish to explicitly exempt Christine Overall from this criticism.

  13. According to Galen Strawson, narratival continuity is not a universally shared human experience, and I am perfectly willing to grant that these descriptions won’t resonate with everyone (Strawson 2004). However, this is dialectically irrelevant here. Procreative ethicists argue over whether procreation is right or wrong as such, and these positions are rendered problematic even by the existence of some people whose lives are such that they have strong practical reasons to procreate.

  14. Most notable here is Heidegger; see (Edwards et al. 1979; Heidegger 1996). .

  15. I use the terms “resonant” and “wholehearted” in roughly the sense given to them by Harry Frankfurt in his important work on identity and autonomy. See (Frankfurt 1987).

  16. I am thus in agreement with Nomy Arpaly’s critique of Susan Wolf’s account of life’s meaningfulness. Wolf includes an “objective” component in her account, which is meant to rule out the meaningfulness of lives which, for example, entirely revolve around the love for a goldfish. Arpaly simply asks: why isn’t such a life meaningful for the person who is living it? Here, we may simply distinguish two questions. Is this a life we would wish to lead, or that we would wish for our loved ones to lead? The answer is probably ‘no’. But is this a life that is existentially grounding for the goldfish-lover? The answer is ‘yes’ (Wolf et al. 2010).

  17. Curiously, in his most recent work, Benatar recognizes that something like this is true. He writes: “Many

    people have meaningful lives from this perspective. They are loved and cherished by their family, and in turn they play important, meaningful roles in the lives of those family members. They provide love, support, company, and deep personal connections.”(Benatar 2017, p. 28) He does not seem to recognize that this complicates his anti-natalist position.

  18. It appears, for example, in the ancient Epic of Gilgamesh, which is often read as the story of Gilgamesh coming to terms with human mortality. And of course, a great deal of religious belief is very often motivated by consciousness of earthly mortality. One famous hymn, written during the Irish Famine, reads “Change and decay in all around I see; O Thou who changest not: abide with me.”

  19. For a systematic treatment of the distinction between reasons for me and reasons for all, see (Hodder 2014).

  20. (Wittgenstein 1958)

References

  • Archer A (2014) Moral rationalism without Overridingness. Ratio 27(1):100–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (2009) The Nicomachean Ethics. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D (2006) Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming Into Existence, vol 32. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D (2013) Still better never to have been: a reply to (more of) my critics. J Ethics 17(1–2):121–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D (2017) The Human Predicament: A Candid Guide to Life's Biggest Questions. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar D, Wasserman D (2015) Debating Procreation: Is it Wrong to Reproduce? Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black S, Tiffany E (2011) Why Be Moral. Wiley online library

  • Brake E (2015) Creation theory: do genetic ties matter. Permissible Progeny? The Morality of Procreation and Parenting:129–149

  • Collingwood RG (1939) An Autobiography, vol 50. Oxford University press, New York, Etc

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp D (2008) Darwinian skepticism about moral realism. Philosophical Issues 18(1):186–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cutas D (2009) Sex is over-rated: on the right to reproduce. Hum Fertil 12(1):45–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2006) Higher-order truths about chmess. Topoi 25(1–2):39–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier J (2015) Can reasons fundamentalism answer the normative question? Motivational Internalism 167

  • Edwards P, Freeman E, Sugden SJ (1979) Heidegger on death: a critical evaluation. Hegeler institute La Salle

  • Frankfurt H (1987) Identification and wholeheartedness. In: Schoeman F (ed) Responsibility, character and the emotions. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 27–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Gheaus A (2015) Could there ever be a duty to have children? In: Permissible Progeny?: The Morality of Procreation and Parenting

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood C (2014) Subjective theories of well-being

  • Heidegger M (1996) Being and time: A translation of Sein und Zeit. SUNY press

  • Heyd D (2009) The intractability of the nonidentity problem. In: Wasserman D, Roberts M (eds) Harming Future Persons. Springer, Berlin, pp 3–25

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hodder I (2014) The entanglements of humans and things: a long-term view. New literary history 45(1):19–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley P (2009) Beyond Consequentialism. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). The Sources of Normativity (Vol. 110): Cambridge University press

  • Krause E (2017) The things that come around again. In: Gadd A (ed) The magic of motherhood: the good stuff, the hard stuff, and everything in between. Brentwood, TN, Creative Trust Literary Group

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIver C (2015) Procreation or appropriation? Permissible Progeny, The Morality of Procreation and Parenting, pp 107–128

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2009) Asymmetries in the morality of causing people to exist. In: Roberts MA, Wasserman DT (eds) Harming future persons: ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, pp 49–68

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1989) The view from nowhere. Oxford university press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (1990) "Finely Aware and Richly Responsible": Literature and the Moral Imagination. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Overall C (2012) Why have children?: The ethical debate. Mit press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (2011) On What Matters. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore DW (2008) Are moral reasons morally overriding? Ethical Theory Moral Pract 11(4):369–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quigley M (2010) A right to reproduce? Bioethics 24(8):403–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson JA (1996) Children of choice: freedom and the new reproductive technologies. Princeton University press

  • Scanlon TM (2014) Being Realistic About Reasons. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (1992) Human Morality, vol 43. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (1994) The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions, vol 100. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (1975) Animal liberation: a new ethic for our treatment of animals. Avon, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith Iltis A (2000) Bioethics as methodological case resolution: specification, specified principlism and casuistry. The Journal of medicine and philosophy 25(3):271–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Specter M (1999) The dangerous philosopher. New Yorker 75:46–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson G (2004) Against narrativity. Ratio 17(4): 428–452

  • Street S (2016) Objectivity and truth: You'd better rethink it. In: Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol 11. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud S (1998) Moral overridingness and moral theory. Pac Philos Q 79(2):170–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanyi A (2012) The case for authority. In: Schleidgen S (ed) Should we always act morally? Essays on Overridingness. Tectum

  • Vavova K (2014) Debunking Evolutionary Debunking. Oxford Studies in Metaethics 9:76–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1981) Persons, character, and morality. In: Rachels J (ed) Moral Luck. Cambridge University press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy, vol 83. Harvard University press, Cambridge

  • Williams B (2000) Philosophy as a humanistic discipline. Philosophy 75(4):477–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1958) The Blue and Brown Books, vol 34. Harper and row, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf S (1997) Happiness and meaning: two aspects of the good life. Soc Philos Policy 14(01):207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf S, Macedo S, Koethe J, Adams RM, Arpaly N, Haidt J (2010) Meaning in Life and Why It Matters. Princeton University press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young T (2001) Overconsumption and procreation: are they morally equivalent? J Appl Philos 18(2):183–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicholas Smyth.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Smyth, N. What Is the Question to which Anti-Natalism Is the Answer?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 71–87 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10070-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10070-7

Keywords

Navigation