Skip to main content
Log in

Against the Asymmetric Convergence Model of Public Justification

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Compared to standard liberal approaches to public reason and justification, the asymmetric convergence model of public justification allows for the public justification of laws and policies based on a convergence of quite different and even publicly inaccessible reasons. The model is asymmetrical in the sense of identifying a broader range of reasons that may function as decisive defeaters of proposed laws and policies. This paper raises several critical questions about the asymmetric convergence model and its central but ambiguous presumption against coercion. By drawing on the theory of structural coercion, a main conclusion of the paper is that the asymmetric convergence model ultimately encounters the very incompleteness problems that its proponents often associate with more familiar consensus models of public justification. The paper also develops an alternative, Rawlsian-inspired account of public justification that includes elements of both convergence and consensus but not asymmetry. The Rawlsian model enables us to understand how democratic decisions may possess a degree of procedural, but still morally significant, liberal legitimacy under conditions of pluralism even when citizens fail to agree fully about either the premises of or conclusions to their political arguments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I adapt a distinction between intelligibility and accessibility presented in Vallier 2011a, though I do not exactly follow his definition of accessibility. For additional discussion, see Gaus 2011: 286.

  2. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for helping to clarify this formulation.

  3. In the case of largely secular societies, the model adopted by Gaus and Vallier recommends a “minimalist proviso” according to which “a citizen should not endorse a law which she or he believes has only a religious rationale” (Gaus and Vallier 2009: 61).

  4. The distinction between indeterminacy and inconclusiveness is emphasized in Schwartzman 2004, drawing on distinctions from Gaus 1996: 152–5.

  5. A helpful discussion of why sincere justifications need not be motivationally primary is found in Schwartzman 2011. Sincerity is also consistent with the Rawls’s “wide view” of public reason concerning religious reasoning (2005: 462).

  6. I continue to use the term “public justification” to refer to the justification of laws, policies, procedures, constitutional provisions, and other institutional arrangements. Rawls sometimes assigns a different and more specific meaning to the term when he refers to the “public justification” of a political conception of justice that is facilitated by a reasonable overlapping consensus (2005: 387).

  7. I am grateful to Quong for identifying problems with an earlier formulation of this principle.

  8. Of course, (PJ4) may seem difficult to operationalize, since it will be hard to know in any given case whether citizens have or would have satisfied requirements of public reason. But any such standard is bound to be imprecise in similar ways. It is likewise difficult to verify whether citizens have sufficient and intelligible reasons or whether institutions have actually issued publicly justified outcomes in accordance with (PJ1) and asymmetric convergence.

  9. Wide acceptance is similar to what Sebastiano Maffetone calls “legitimation” (2010).

  10. Vallier introduces a second example of reasoning based on religious testimony. I leave aside this example, which seems to concern judgments about the general reliability of testifiers rather than the accessibility of the justifications a citizen might inherit from them.

  11. For helpful discussion, see Audi 2011: 81–4.

  12. Both arguments in support of asymmetric convergence might be bolstered with the following example. Consider a religious group whose members engage in potentially self-harming conduct for religious reasons (e.g., ritualistic drug use). Others are unlikely to understand or perhaps even tolerate such conduct if they fail to enter into the group’s doctrinal framework and system of meaning. The worry is that other citizens would be entitled to coerce the group’s members for the members’ own supposed good, e.g., by banning the conduct, and might do so without even considering the most relevant reasons for the conduct. Yet this worry is allayed by the demand that all reasonable citizens recognize and prioritize the value of religious liberty as part of a reasonable political conception, even when they do not fully appreciate how that liberty is being exercised. The norm of religious liberty is the source of public reasons that would protect groups against interference and enable them to pursue accommodations such as exemptions from generally applicable laws. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this example and objection, even if this note does not fully address it.

  13. My (Boettcher 2007) examines in more detail the issues of religious freedom, integrity, and respect for persons that motivate this argument and the subsequent one examined in the text.

  14. Indeed this concern may seem to suggest that the asymmetric convergence model tilts not in the direction of classical liberalism but rather libertarianism, or even anarchism.

  15. This insight is incorporated in the formulation of my PJ4 above, with its reference to reasonably acceptable and widely accepted procedures.

  16. This is my own gloss on the meaning of structural coercion in Reiman 2012.

  17. Indeed I do not ultimately endorse Reiman’s theory, though that’s not important here. For a similar account of the coerciveness of private property that does not employ the concept of structural coercion see Cohen 2011.

  18. “A coerces B to do X when A proposes to make B worse off if B does not do X” (Wertheimer 2002: 41), Similarly, “[c]oercion occurs when one man’s actions are made to serve another man’s will, not for his own but for the other’s purpose” (Hayek 2006: 89).

  19. This paragraph relies in part on the survey of the coercion literature in Anderson 2011.

  20. A related problem concerns what Andrew Lister calls the “aggregation problem” concerning the extent to which laws and policies can be evaluated independently of one another in practices of public justification (Lister 2010: 157; Gaus 2010b: 199).

  21. I thank Zuolo for this point.

  22. Some Rawlsians reject a narrow interpretation of the scope of public reason and maintain instead that all decisions concerning coercive law and policy should be subject to requirements of public reason (Quong 2011: 274-298). While I presuppose the narrow interpretation here, the main arguments of the paper do not depend on it. The subject of public justification is the basic institutional structure and public reason can apply therein either narrowly or broadly.

References

  • Anderson S (2010) The enforcement approach to coercion. J Ethics Soc Philos 5:1–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson S (2011) Coercion. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford Ency Philos., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/coercion. Accessed 9 Jan 2013

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi R (2011) Democratic authority and the separation of church and state. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird C (2014) Coercion and Public Justification. Polit Philos Econ., doi:10.1177/1470594X13496073

  • Boettcher J (2007) Respect, recognition, and public reason. Soc Theor Pract 33:223–249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boettcher J (2009) Habermas, religion and the ethics of citizenship. Philos Soc Crit 35:215–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (2011) Freedom and money. In: Otsuka M (ed) On the currency of egalitarian justice and other essays. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 166–192

    Google Scholar 

  • De Marneffe P (1994) Rawls’s idea of public reason. Pac Philos Q 75:232–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberle C (2002) Religious conviction in liberal politics. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberle C (2011) Consensus, convergence and religiously justified coercion. Publ Aff Q 25:281–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G (1996) Justificatory liberalism. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G (1997) Reason, justification, and consensus: Why democracy can’t have it all. In: Bohman J, Rehg W (eds) Deliberative democracy. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G (2010a) Coercion, ownership and the redistributive state: justificatory liberalism’s classical tilt. Soc Philos Pol 27:233–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G (2010b) On two criticisms of justificatory liberalism: a response to Wall and Lister. Polit Philos Econ 9:177–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G (2011) The order of public reason. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus G, Vallier K (2009) The roles of religious conviction in a publicly justified polity. Philos Soc Crit 35:51–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F (2006) Freedom and coercion. In: Miller D (ed) The liberty reader. Paradigm, Boulder, pp 80–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Lister A (2010) Public justification and the limits of state action. Polit Philos Econ 9:151–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lister A (2011) Public justification of what? Coercion vs. decision as competing frames for the basic principle of justificatory liberalism. Publ Aff Q 25:349–367

    Google Scholar 

  • Maffetone S (2010) Rawls: An introduction. Polity, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K (1994) [1844] On the Jewish question. In: Simon L (ed) Karl Marx selected writings. Hackett, Indianapolis, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry M (1997) Religion in politics. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Quong J (2011) Liberalism without perfection. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Quong J (2014) On the idea of public reason. In: Mandle J, Reidy D (eds) A companion to Rawls. Wiley, Polity, pp 265–280

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2001) Justice as fairness: A restatement. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy D (2000) Rawls’s wide view of public reason: not wide enough. Res Publica 6:49–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiman J (2012) As free and as just as possible: A theory of marxian liberalism. Wiley, Malden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzman M (2004) The completeness of public reason. Polit Philos Econ 3:191–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzman M (2011) The sincerity of public reason. J Polit Philos 19:375–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallier K (2011a) Against public reason’s accessibility requirement. J Moral Philos 8:366–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallier K (2011b) Convergence and consensus in public reason. Publ Aff Q 25:261–279

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallier K, D’Agostino F (2013) Public justification. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford Ency Philos., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/justification-public. Accessed 19 June 2013

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer A (2002) Liberty, coercion, and the limits of the state. In: Simon R (ed) The Blackwell guide to social and political philosophy. Wiley, Malden, pp 38–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams A (2000) The alleged incompleteness of public reason. Res Publica 6:199–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James W. Boettcher.

Additional information

The author is grateful for extensive comments from the journal’s anonymous reviewers as well as to Jonathan Quong and Federico Zuolo for written comments on an earlier draft. Helpful feedback was also provided by an audience at the 30th International Social Philosophy Conference (2013).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boettcher, J.W. Against the Asymmetric Convergence Model of Public Justification. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 18, 191–208 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9519-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-014-9519-7

Keywords

Navigation