Skip to main content
Log in

No Body to Kick, No Soul to Damn: Responsibility and Accountability for the Financial Crisis (2007–2010)

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“Did you ever expect a corporation to have a conscience, when it has no soul to be damned, and no body to be kicked?”

Edward, first Baron Thurlow (1731–1806).

Abstract

This article takes the 2008–2010 financial crisis as a case study to explore the tension between responsibility and accountability in complex crises. I analyze the patterns of attribution and assumption of responsibility of thirty-three bankers in Wall Street, interviewed from fall 2008 to summer 2010. First, I show that responsibility for complex failures cannot be easily attributed or assumed: responsibility becomes diluted within the collective. Actors can only assume collective responsibility, recognizing that they belong to an institution at fault. Second, I show that blaming is a social process that should be examined contextually, relationally, and dynamically. I build on sociological theories to depart from the normative focus of philosophers, and the cognitive focus of psychologists, who have dominated the study of responsibility so far.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Angus Reid, June 2010: Mostly to blame for the financial crisis: Banks and financial institutions 58 %, Big corporations 51 %; Governments 40 %; Consumers 24 %. From June 17 to June 18, 2010, Angus Reid Public Opinion conducted an online survey among 1004 American adults who are Summerboard America panelists.

  2. The firing squad is the classical example illustrating the problem of the diffusion of responsibility in a collective. If in a firing squad one or more shooters are randomly given blank cartridges instead of bullets, each shooter might believe that they did not kill the prisoner.

  3. As Curran (2015) remarks, the “boomerang effects” of systemic financial risks could have annihilated the benefits of the risks taken by senior finance employees, who could have suffered severe financial losses.

  4. The notion of organized irresponsibility is equally present in Mills’ work (1956). Although Beck and Mills start from different premises, they both reach the conclusion that actors in position of responsibility can actually avoid being held to account. Mills contends that a system of organized irresponsibility can be produced and reproduced because of the emergence of a mass society, which does not hold the “Power Elite” accountable. However, Mills restricts his argument to the elite, whereas Beck thinks it is more pervasive throughout society.

  5. The other model of collective responsibility consists in blaming the group itself, rather than any specific group member (see Feinberg 1970). This model would not imply any assumption of responsibility from my respondents though.

  6. The three factors correspond to categories for which my sample provides variance.

References

  • Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126(4), 556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1945). Organized guilt and universal responsibility. Jewish Frontier, 12, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1963). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A report on the banality of evil. New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashforth, B. E., & Mael, F. (1989). Social identity theory and the organization. Academy of Management Review, 14(1), 20–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, M. L. (2007). Stakeholder influence capacity and the variability of financial returns to corporate social responsibility. Academy of Management Review, 32(3), 794–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K., & Palazzo, G. (2008). Corporate social responsibility: A process model of sensemaking. Academy of Management Review, 33(1), 122–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (1992). Risk society: Towards a new modernity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (1999). World risk society. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, R., & Kottasz, R. (2012). Public attitudes towards the UK banking industry following the global financial crisis. International Journal of Bank Marketing, 30(2), 128–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumstein, P. W., Carssow, K. G., Hall, J., Hawkins, B., Hoffman, R., Ishem, E., Maurer, C. P., Spens, D., Taylor, J., & Zimmerman, D. L. (1974). The honoring of accounts. American Sociological Review, 39(4), 551–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, M. (1998). The quest for responsibility: Accountability and citizenship in complex organisations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, M. (2007). Analysing and assessing accountability: A conceptual framework1. European law journal, 13(4), 447–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1958). Common fate, similarity, and other indices of the status of aggregates of persons as social entities. Behavioral Science, 3(1), 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambliss, D. F. (1996). Beyond caring: Hospitals, nurses, and the social organization of ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curran, D. (2015). Risk illusion and organized irresponsibility in contemporary finance: rethinking class and risk society. Economy and Society, 44(3), 392–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeZoort, F. T., & Harrison, P. D. (2016). Understanding auditors’ sense of responsibility for detecting fraud within organizations. Journal of Business Ethics. doi:10.1007/s10551-016-3064-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diefenbach, T., & Sillince, J. A. A. (2011). Formal and informal hierarchy in different types of organization. Organization Studies, 32(11), 1515–1537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1994). Toward a unified conception of business ethics: Integrative social contracts theory. Academy of Management Review, 19(2), 252–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eshleman, A. (2014). Moral responsibility. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-responsibility/.

  • Feinberg, J. (1970). Doing and deserving; essays in the theory of responsibility. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. T., & Taylor, S. E. (1991). Social cognition: From brains to culture (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gailey, J. A., & Lee, M. T. (2005). An integrated model of attribution of responsibility for wrongdoing in organizations. Social Psychology Quarterly, 68(4), 338–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, V. L. (1980). Intuitive psychologist or intuitive lawyer? Alternative models of the attribution process. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39(5), 767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, V. L., & Hagiwara, S. (1992). Roles, responsibility, and accounts across cultures. International Journal of Psychology, 27(2), 157–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, V. L., & Sanders, J. (1981). The effect of roles and deeds on responsibility judgments: The normative structure of wrongdoing. Social Psychology Quarterly, 44(3), 237–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, T. (1985). Causation in the law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, K. G. (1988). The Rashomon effect: When ethnographers disagree. American Anthropologist, 90(1), 73–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heimer, C. (2010). The unstable alliance of law and morality. In S. Hitlin & S. Vaisey (Eds.), Handbook of the sociology of morality (pp. 179–202). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heimer, C., & Staffen, L. (1998). For the sake of the children: The social organization of responsibility in the hospital and the home. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellwig, T., & Coffey, E. (2011). Public opinion, party messages, and responsibility for the financial crisis in Britain. Electoral Studies, 30(3), 417–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobolt, S. B., & Tilley, J. (2014). Blaming Europe?: Responsibility without accountability in the European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackall, R. (1988). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, D., & Washburn, N. T. (2012). Understanding attributions of corporate social irresponsibility. Academy of Management Review, 37(2), 300–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lickel, B., Hamilton, D. L., Wieczorkowska, G., Lewis, A., Sherman, S. J., & Uhles, A. N. (2000). Varieties of groups and the perception of group entitativity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(2), 223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lin-Hi, N., & Müller, K. (2013). The CSR bottom line: Preventing corporate social irresponsibility. Journal of Business Research, 66(10), 1928–1936.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. D., & Walsh, J. P. (2003). Misery loves companies: Rethinking social initiatives by business. Administrative Science Quarterly, 48(2), 268–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, C. W. (1956). The power elite. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, P. E., & Schlegelmilch, B. B. (2013). Corporate social responsibility and corporate social irresponsibility: Introduction to a special topic section. Journal of Business Research, 66(10), 1807–1813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orbuch, T. L. (1997). People’s accounts count: The sociology of accounts. Annual Review of Sociology, 23, 455–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, B. R. (1997). Personal responsibility: Applications of the triangle model. Research in organizational behavior, 19, 241–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, M. B., & Lyman, S. M. (1968). Accounts. American Sociological Review, 33(1), 46–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shultz, T. R., Jaggi, C., & Schleifer, M. (1987). Assigning vicarious responsibility. European Journal of Social Psychology, 17(3), 377–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smiley, M. (1992). Moral responsibility and the boundaries of community: Power and accountability from a pragmatic point of view. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smiley, M. (2010). Collective responsibility. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/collective-responsibility/.

  • Stone, C. D. (1975). Where the law ends: The social control of corporate behavior. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. F. (1980). Moral responsibility of public officials: The problem of many hands. American Political Science Review, 74(4), 905–916.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. F. (2014). Responsibility for failures of government the problem of many hands. The American Review of Public Administration, 44(3), 259–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tourish, D., & Hargie, O. (2012). Metaphors of failure and the failures of metaphor: A critical study of root metaphors used by bankers in explaining the banking crisis. Organization Studies, 33(8), 1045–1069.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treasury, U. D. (2012). The financial crisis response in charts. https://www.treasury.gov/resource-center/data-chart-center/Documents/20120413_FinancialCrisisResponse.pdf. Accessed 04 Jan 2014.

  • Tsutsui, K. (2009). The trajectory of perpetrators’ trauma: Mnemonic politics around the Asia-Pacific War in Japan. Social Forces, 87(3), 1389–1422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, D. (1983). Controlling unlawful organizational behavior: Social structure and corporate misconduct. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, D. (1996). The challenger launch decision: Risky technology, culture, and deviance at NASA. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, D. (2006). The market for virtue: The potential and limits of corporate social responsibility. Washington: Brookings Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Scheve, C., Zink, V., Ismer, S. (2016). The blame game: Economic crisis responsibility, discourse and affective framings. Sociology50(4): 635–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, M. (2014). Fear and anger in Great Britain: Blame assignment and emotional reactions to the financial crisis. Political Behavior, 36(3), 683–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, W. (1970). Pride, shame and responsibility. The Philosophical Quarterly (1950–), 20(78), 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A., & Mueller, F. (2012). Bankers in the dock: Moral storytelling in action. Human Relations, 65(1), 111–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yzerbyt, V. Y., Rogier, A., & Fiske, S. T. (1998). Group entitativity and social attribution: On translating situational constraints into stereotypes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 24(10), 1089–1103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The financial support from the Axa Research Fund is gratefully noted. The author acknowledges, without implicating, helpful comments on earlier versions of this work by Peter Bearman, David Stark, Diane Vaughan, William McAllister, Gabriel Abend, Marion Fourcade, Kristin Murphy, Pilar Opazo, Gérôme Truc, Catherine Tan, as well as the members of Peter Bearman’s workgroup and the members of the Mellon Interdisciplinary program workgroup.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olivia Nicol.

Ethics declarations

Funding

This work was supported by the Axa Research Fund.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nicol, O. No Body to Kick, No Soul to Damn: Responsibility and Accountability for the Financial Crisis (2007–2010). J Bus Ethics 151, 101–114 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-016-3279-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-016-3279-3

Keywords

Navigation