Skip to main content
Log in

On the Mumford–Tate conjecture for 1-motives

  • Published:
Inventiones mathematicae Aims and scope

Abstract

We show that the statement analogous to the Mumford–Tate conjecture for Abelian varieties holds for 1-motives on unipotent parts. This is done by comparing the unipotent part of the associated Hodge group and the unipotent part of the image of the absolute Galois group with the unipotent part of the motivic fundamental group.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is nonstandard terminology. By a semiabelian scheme over S one usually understands a group scheme over S each of whose fibres is an extension of an Abelian scheme by a torus. This is the right thing to consider in order to study degenerations of Abelian schemes.

  2. Recall that we have chosen to place the complexes [YG] associated with 1-motives in degrees 0 and 1. With this convention the 1-motive [ℤ→0] is a neutral object for the tensor product of complexes, as it should be.

  3. Actually: a \(\pi_{1}^{\mathrm {mot}}(M)\)-equivariant derivation.

References

  1. Andreatta, F., Bertapelle, A.: Crystalline realisation of 1-motives. J. Pure Appl. Algebra 215, 1919–1944 (2011)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Bertolin, C.: Le radical unipotent du groupe de Galois motivique d’un 1-motif. Math. Ann. 327(3), 585–607 (2003)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. Bertrand, D.: Special points and Poincaré biextensions. arXiv:1104.5178

  4. Brylinski, J.L.: 1-Motifs et Formes Automorphes (théorie Arithmétique des Domaines de Siegel), Publ. Univ. Paris VII, vol. 15 (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Barbieri-Viale, L., Srinivas, V.: Albanese and Picard 1-Motives. Mémoires Société Mathématique de France, vol. 87. Soc. Math. France, Paris (2001), vi+104 pages

    Google Scholar 

  6. Deligne, P.: Théorie de Hodge III. Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 44, 5–77 (1974)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  7. Charles, F., Schnell, C.: Notes on absolute Hodge classes. arXiv:1101.3647v1 50 p

  8. Deligne, P.: Hodge cycles on Abelian varieties. In: Deligne, P., Milne, J.S., Ogus, A., Shih, K. (eds.) Hodge Cycles, Motives, and Shimura Varieties. Lecture Notes in Math., vol. 900. Springer, Berlin (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hindry, M.: Autour d’une conjecture de Serge Lang. Invent. Math. 94, 575–603 (1988)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  10. Jacquinot, O., Ribet, K.: Deficient points on extensions of Abelian varieties by 𝔾 m . J. Number Theory 25(2), 133–151 (1987)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Jannsen, U.: Mixed motives, motivic cohomology and ext-groups. In: Proceedings of the ICM, vol. I, pp. 667–679. Birkhäuser, Basel (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Jossen, P.: Detecting linear dependence on a simple Abelian variety. Comment. Math. Helv., to appear, 24 p

  13. Lazard, M.: Groupes analytiques p-adiques. Publ. Math. Inst. Hautes Études Sci. 26, 5–219 (1965)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Pink, R.: -adic algebraic monodromy groups, cocharacters and the Mumford–Tate conjecture. J. Reine Angew. Math. 495, 187–237 (1998)

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Pohlmann, H.: Algebraic cycles on Abelian varieties of complex multiplication type. J. Ann. Math. (2) 88, 161–180 (1968)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Ribet, K.: Dividing rational points on Abelian varieties of CM-type. Compos. Math. 33(1), 69–74 (1976)

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. Ribet, K.: Kummer theory on an extension of an Abelian variety by tori. Duke Math. J. 46, 745–761 (1979)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Ribet, K.: Review of Abelian -adic representations and elliptic curves by J.-P. Serre. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. (N.S.) 22(1), 214–218 (1990)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  19. Serre, J.-P.: Abelian -Adic Representations and Elliptic Curves. Benjamin, New York (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Serre, J.-P.: Sur les groupes de congruence des variétés abéliennes II. Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR 35, 731–735 (1971)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Serre, J.-P.: Cours au collège de France, 1984–1985

  22. Serre, J.-P.: Lettres à Marie–France Vignéras du 10 février et à Ken Ribet du 7 mai 1986. Oeuvres IV, 38–65 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Vasiu, A.: Some cases of the Mumford–Tate conjecture and Shimura varieties. Indiana Univ. Math. J. 57, 1–76 (2008)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to the University of Regensburg, who kindly supported me for quite some time now without ever seriously complaining. I am grateful to Tamás Szamuely who suggested valuable improvements to earlier versions of the text, and to Pierre Deligne who contributed an essential complement and generously permitted me to propagate it. This work was initiated in July 2010 while attending a workshop on Tannakian categories in Lausanne, I wish to thank the EPFL and in particular Varvara Karpova for kindest hospitality.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Jossen.

Appendix: The Tannakian construction of P(M) (following P. Deligne)

Appendix: The Tannakian construction of P(M) (following P. Deligne)

I reproduce here in almost unaltered form a comment of P. Deligne, explaining our construction of the Lie algebra of the unipotent motivic fundamental group P(M) of a 1-motive M in terms of Tannakian formalism. I alone am to blame for mistakes.

The starting point is that in Definition 4.3 the point \(\overline{u}\) should be seen as an extension of \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) by the unit object ℤ. This extension can be constructed in a general setting as follows:

A.1

Let \(\mathcal{T}\) be a Tannakian category in characteristic zero with unit object . Suppose each object of \(\mathcal{T}\) has a functorial exhaustive filtration W compatible with tensor products and duals, the functor \(\mathrm{gr}^{W}_{\ast}\) being exact. For any object M, the object \(\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M) = M^{\vee}\otimes M\) contains the subobject \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\). The filtration of \(\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) is deduced from the filtration of M, hence

$$W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M) = \mathrm{im} \Bigl(\bigoplus_p\mathcal {H}\mathit {om}(M/W_pM,W_pM) \to \mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\Bigr) $$

As , we can take the class of M in each of the vector spaces Ext1(M/W p M,W p M), interpret it as a class in , take the sum of those and push to \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) by functoriality of Ext1. We get a class

which is natural in M under taking subobjects and quotients.

A.2

Let G be the fundamental group of \(\mathcal{T}\). It has an invariant unipotent subgroup W −1(G) with Lie algebra \(W_{-1}(\operatorname{Lie} G)\). Thus, for all objects M, the group G acts on M respecting the filtration W, and the unipotent subgroup W −1(M) acts trivially on \(\mathrm{gr}^{W}_{\ast}M\). Let w:𝔾 m G/W −1(G) be the cocharacter defined by the numbering of the filtration of W of M, for any M. This means that for a∈𝔾 m , the automorphism w(a) of \(\mathrm{gr}^{W}_{\ast}(M)\) acts as multiplication with a n on \(\mathrm{gr}^{W}_{n}(M)\). Let us consider the inverse image of this 𝔾 m in G, or more precisely \(\mathbb {G}_{m}\times_{G/W_{-1}G}G\). Its Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{L}\) is an extension of by \(\operatorname{Lie} W_{-1}(G)\).

For any object M of \(\mathcal{T}\), let \(\mathfrak{u}_{M}\) be the image in \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) of \(\operatorname{Lie} W_{-1}(G)\). The extension \(\mathfrak{L}\) gives us by functoriality a quotient \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) of \(\mathfrak{L}\) acting on M, which is an extension of by \(\mathfrak{u}_{M}\).

In the setting of Sect. 4, U(M) corresponds to \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\), and the subobject P(M) of U(M) corresponds to the subobject \(\mathfrak{u}_{M}\) of \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\). We have a 1-motive [ℤ→U(M)] given by the point \(\overline{u}\), which has to be seen as an extension of [0→U(M)] by [ℤ→0], and P(M) was defined to be the smallest subobject of U(M) from which this extension comes, say after passing to ℚ-coefficients. Exactly in this way the two stories A.1 and A.2 are related:

Proposition A.3

  1. (1)

    The extension cl(M) is the push out of the extension \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) via the inclusion \(\mathfrak{u}_{M}\to W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\).

  2. (2)

    If \(\mathfrak{v}\) is a subobject of \(\mathfrak{u}_{M}\) such that cl(M) is the image of a class in , then \(\mathfrak{v} = \mathfrak{u}_{M}\).

I claim in (1) an equality in . As is 0 for weight reasons, it is the same as an (unique) isomorphism of actual extensions.

A first computation, which was helpful for understanding but now has disappeared from the proof, was to consider the category of graded representations of a graded Lie algebra \(\mathfrak{g}\) with degrees <0, and wondering what cocycle \(c:\mathfrak{g}\to W_{-1} \mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) was giving me cl(M) in \(H^{1}(\mathfrak{g}, W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M))\). The answer is the composite map \(\mathfrak{g}\to \mathfrak{g}\to W_{-1} \mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\), where the first map is multiplication by n in degree −n, and the second map is given by the action of \(\mathfrak{g}\) on M.

Proof of Proposition A.3

(1) For each integer n we have a map

The push-out by \(\mathfrak{u}_{M} \to W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) of the extension is the pull-back of the extension

$$ 1\to W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M) \to W_0\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M) \to \mathrm{gr}^W_0\!\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M) \to 1 $$
(∗)

by ∑ n ne n . Indeed, ∑ n ne n gives the action of on \(\mathrm{gr}^{W}_{\ast}\!M\) corresponding to the grading. Define E p :=∑ n>p e n and let AB be integers such that W A M=0 and W B M=M. We have then

$$\sum_nne_n = \sum_{A\leq p\leq B} E_p + m\sum_ne_n $$

for some integer m depending on the choice of A and B. The map ∑ n e n lifts to the identity morphism of M, viewed as a map which factors over \(W_{0}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\). The pull-back of () by m n e n is hence trivial, and the push-out of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) by the inclusion \(\mathfrak{u}_{M} \to W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\) is the sum of the pull-backs of () by the E p . This pull-back by E p comes from an extension of by \(\mathcal {H}\mathit {om}(M/W_{p}M,W_{p}M)\), which I would like to call Endomorphisms of M respecting W p (M), inducing a multiple of the identity on M/W p M and 0 on W p M. At least, that is what it becomes in any realisation. This is the extension already considered in A.1, corresponding to the class of M in Ext1(M/W p M,W p M). The sum of those extension classes, pushed to \(W_{-1}\mathcal {E}\mathit {nd}(M)\), had been defined to be cl(M).

(2) On objects N of weights <0, i.e. such that N=W −1 N, the functor is left exact. For any class α in , there is hence a smallest sub-object N 0 of N such that α comes from a class in . Indeed, if α comes from N′ and from N″, the short exact sequence

$$0\to N'\cap N'' \to N'\oplus N'' \to N $$

shows after applying that α also comes from N′∩N″. It remains to show that the class of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) in does not come from any \(\mathfrak{v} \subsetneq \mathfrak{u}_{M}\). Indeed, any subobject of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) is stable by the action of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) because G and \(\operatorname{Lie} G\) act on everything. □

Proposition A.4

Any Lie-subobject of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) mapping onto is equal to \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\). In other words, the extension is essential.

Proof

The bracket of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) passes to the quotients by W and defines brackets

$$W_p \mathfrak{L}_M /W_{p-1} \mathfrak{L}_M \otimes \mathfrak{L}_M /W_{-1} \mathfrak{L}_M \to W_p \mathfrak{L}_M /W_{p-1}\mathfrak{L}_M $$

and this bracket is the multiplication by p. For any subobject \(\mathfrak{L}'\) of \(\mathfrak{L}_{M}\) mapping onto the quotient , the stability of \(\mathfrak{L}'\) by the action of \(W_{p} \mathfrak{L}_{M}\) hence gives a surjectivity

$$\mathrm{gr}^W_p \mathfrak{L}' \to \mathrm{gr}^W_p \mathfrak{L}_M $$

from which the equality \(\mathfrak{L}' = \mathfrak{L}_{M}\) follows. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Jossen, P. On the Mumford–Tate conjecture for 1-motives. Invent. math. 195, 393–439 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00222-013-0459-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00222-013-0459-y

Keywords

Navigation