Skip to main content
Log in

Bounded inductive dichotomy: separation of open and clopen determinacies with finite alternatives in constructive contexts

  • Published:
Archive for Mathematical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his previous work, the author has introduced the axiom schema of inductive dichotomy, a weak variant of the axiom schema of inductive definition, and used this schema for elementary (\(\varDelta ^1_0\)) positive operators to separate open and clopen determinacies for those games in which two players make choices from infinitely many alternatives in various circumstances. Among the studies on variants of inductive definitions for bounded (\(\varDelta ^0_0\)) positive operators, the present article investigates inductive dichotomy for these operators, and applies it to constructive investigations of variants of determinacy statements for those games in which the players make choices from only finitely many alternatives. As a result, three formulations of open determinacy, that are all classically equivalent with each other, are equivalent to three different semi-classical principles, namely Markov’s Principle, Lesser Limited Principle of Omniscience and Limited Principle of Omniscience, over a suitable constructive base theory that proves clopen determinacy. Open and clopen determinacies for these games are thus separated. Some basic results on variants of inductive definitions for \(\varDelta ^0_0\) positive operators will also be given.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability Statement

Data sharing not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.

References

  1. Akama, Y., Berardi, S., Hayashi, S., Kohlenbach, U.: An arithmetical hierarchy of the law of excluded middle and related principles. In: Proceedings of the 19th annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, 2004, IEEE, pp.192–201, (2004)

  2. Avigad, J.: On the relationships between ATR\(_0\) and \(\widehat{ID}_{< \omega }\). J. Symb. Log. 61(3), 768–779 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. Buchholz, W., Feferman, S., Pohlers, W., Sieg, W.: Iterated Inductive Definitions and Subsystems of Analysis: Recent Proof-Theoretical Studies. Springer, New York (1981)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Hájek, P., Pudlák, P.: Metamathematics of First-Order Arithmetic. Springer, New York (1998)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Jäger, G., Kahle, R., Setzer, A., Strahm, T.: The proof-theoretic analysis of transfinitely iterated fixed point theories. J. Symb. Log. 64, 53–67 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Moschovakis, Y.: Elementary Introduction on Abstract Structures. North-Holland (1974)

  7. Nemoto, T.: Complete determinacy and subsystems of second order arithmetic. In: Beckmann, A., Dimitracopoulos, C., Löwe, B. (eds.) Logic and Theory of Algorithms, pp. 457–466. Springer, New York (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  8. Nemoto, T.: Determinacy of Wadge classes and subsystems of second order arithmetic. Math. Log. Q. 55(2), 154–176 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Nemoto, T.: Determinacy of Infinite Games and Reverse Mathematics. Tohoku University (2009). (PhD Thesis)

  10. Nemoto, T., MedSalem, M.O., Tanaka, K.: Infinite games in the Cantor space and subsystems of second order arithmetic. Math. Log. Q. 53(3), 226–236 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Nemoto, T., Sato, K.: A marriage of Brouwer’s intuitionism and Hilbert’s Finitism I: arithmetic. J. Symb. Log. (2021). https://doi.org/10.1017/jsl.2018.6 (published online in a preproof version)

  12. Sato, K.: Relative predicativity and dependent recursion in second-order set theory and higher-order theories. J. Symb. Log. 79(3), 712–732 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Sato, K.: Full and hat inductive definitions are equivalent in NBG. Arch. Math. Log. 54(1–2), 75–112 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Sato, K.: A note on predicative ordinal analysis I: iterated comprehension and transfinite induction. J. Symb. Log. 84(1), 226–265 (2019)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Sato, K.: Elementary inductive dichotomy: separation of open and clopen determinacies with infinite alternatives. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 171(3), 102754 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Sato, K.: Ordinal analyses for monotone and cofinal transfinite inductions. Arch. Math. Log. 59(3–4), 277–291 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. Sato, K.: A new model construction by making a detour via intuitionistic theories III: ultrafinitistic proofs of conservations of \(\Sigma ^1_1\) collection. Ann. Pure Appl. Log., accepted for publication (2021)

  18. Sato, K., Walker, J.: Finitist axiomatic truth. J. Symb. Log., accepted for publication (2021)

  19. Sato, K., Zumbrunnen, R.: A new model construction by making a detour via intuitionistic theories I: Operational set theory without choice is \(\Pi _1\)-equivalent to KP. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 166(2), 121–186 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Simpson, S.: Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic. Springer, New York (1999)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. van Oosten, J.: Lifschitz’ realizability. J. Symb. Log. 55(2), 805–821 (1990)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. Veldman, W.: The problem of the determinacy of infinite games from an intuitionistic point of view. Department of Mathematics, University of Nijmegen, Tech. rep (2004)

  23. Veldman, W.: Brouwer’s Fan Theorem as an axiom and as a contrast to Kleene’s Alternative. Arch. Math. Log. 53(5), 621–693 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Veldman, W.: The fan theorem, its strong negation, and the determinacy of games, draft, 2018, arXiv:1311.6988v4

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to express his greatest appreciations to Takako Nemoto for explaining her previous works ([7,8,9,10]) and having stimulus discussions on the subject with him. He also thanks the anonymous referee for careful reading.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kentaro Sato.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

A relation to Veldman’s determinacy

A relation to Veldman’s determinacy

As mentioned in Introduction, Veldman [24] introduced the notion of I-determinateness, which is senseful in the intuitionistic context, by replacing the negated premise with its “strong negation” from our determinacy implication. Namely, his formulation is as follows.

(\(\mathcal {C}\mathsf{-VelDet} ^*\)):

\((\forall \tau \,{<}\,\underline{2})(\exists \pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}) (\mathrm {Ob2}(\pi ,\tau )\,{\wedge }\,\varphi (\pi ))\, {\rightarrow }\,(\exists \sigma \,{<}\,\underline{2})\mathrm {WS1}^*_\varphi (\sigma )\),

for any \(\mathcal {C}\) formula \(\varphi (\pi )\) with a distinguished variable \(\pi \).

He also defined the notion of II-determinateness by exchanging the players but not replacing \(\varphi \) by \(\lnot \varphi \) as Player II’s winning condition (as opposed to our \(\mathcal {C}\mathsf{-DetImp2} ^*\)), which turns to be equivalent to \(\mathcal {C}\mathsf{-VelDet} ^*\) for reasonable \(\mathcal {C}\), by a similar argument as Lemma 5.

Although Veldman admitted that strong negations must be defined manually on a case-by-case basis and cannot be defined systematically, for our purpose \((\forall \pi \,{<}\,\underline{2})\exists x \lnot \varphi (\pi {\upharpoonright }x)\) seems plausible to be called the strong negation of \(\mathrm {WK2}_{\varphi }\). Thus, we can expect that \(\varSigma ^0_1\mathsf{-VeDet1} ^*\) is equivalent to \(\varDelta ^0_0\mathsf{-WFT} \). Actually, this equivalence was proved by Veldman [24] over his base theory, which has full induction scheme and hence much stronger than ours \(\mathbf {EL}_0^-\). By modifying our previous proofs, we can show that the equivalence is provable in \(\mathbf {EL}_0^-\).

Lemma 17

\(\varSigma ^0_1\mathsf{-VelDet} ^*\) and \(\varDelta ^0_0\mathsf{-WFT} \) are equivalent over \(\mathbf {EL}_0^-\).

Proof

Our strategy is to modify the proofs of Lemmata 7, 8 (2) and 11 so that implications among the “strong negations” of the second disjuncts (in the reverse direction), where as the “strong negation” of \(\mathrm {SIDic2}_\varphi (x)\) we take

$$\begin{aligned} \forall F\exists y (x\,{\in }\,F\,{\vee }\, (\varphi (y,F)\,{\wedge }\,y\,{\notin }\,F)). \end{aligned}$$

First, to modify Lemma 7, assuming this, for any \(\pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}\) we show \(\exists y \lnot \psi (x,\pi {\upharpoonright }y)\), where \(\psi \) is as in Lemma 7. Let \(F\,{:=}\, \{y\,{:}\,\pi (y)\,{=}\,0\}\). By assumption, either \(\pi (x)\,{=}\,0\) and so \(\lnot \psi (x,\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1))\) or \(\lnot \psi (x,\pi {\upharpoonright }(t(y){+}1))\) for some y, where t is as given in the proof of Lemma 7.

Next, to modify Lemma 8 (2), assume \((\forall \tau \,{<}\,\underline{2})(\exists \pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}) (\mathrm {Ob2}(\pi ,\tau )\,{\wedge }\,\varphi (\pi ))\). For any F, define \(\tau \,{<}\,\underline{2}\) as in Lemma 8 (2). The assumption yields u with \(\mathrm {Ob2fr}(u,\tau ,\langle \,\rangle ) \,{\wedge }\,\theta (u)\). If \(u{\upharpoonright }0\,{=}\, \langle \,\rangle \,{\notin }\,F\) and \((\forall y\,{\le }\,|u|) (\mathrm {DetO}[\theta ](u{\upharpoonright }y,F)\,{\rightarrow }\, u{\upharpoonright }y\,{\in }\,F)\), then \(u{\upharpoonright }y\,{\notin }\,F\,{\wedge }\, \lnot \theta (u{\upharpoonright }y)\) by induction on y, contradicting \(\theta (u)\). Thus, either \(\langle \,\rangle \,{\in }\,F\) or \((\exists y\,{\le }\,|u|) (\mathrm {DetO}[\theta ](u{\upharpoonright }y,F)\,{\wedge }\, u{\upharpoonright }y\,{\notin }\,F)\).

Finally to modify Lemma 11, assume \((\forall \pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}) \exists x\lnot \varphi (\pi {\upharpoonright }x)\), where we may assume \(\varphi (\langle \,\rangle )\). For any \(\tau \,{<}\,\underline{2}\), define \(\rho \,\) as in the proof of Lemma 11, and \(\pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}\) so that \(\pi (y)\,{=}\,\tau (\rho (\pi \upharpoonright y))\) for any y. The assumption yields x with \(\lnot \varphi (\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1))\), and we may assume \((\forall y\,{\le }\,x)\varphi (\pi {\upharpoonright }y)\). By induction on \(z\,{\le }\,x{+}1\), we now show the following, which is equivalent to a \(\varDelta ^0_0\) formula:

$$\begin{aligned}&(\exists y\,{<}\,z)\exists u \begin{pmatrix}\mathrm {Bin}(u,y) \,{\wedge }\,\tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{-}y)){*}\langle 1{-}\pi (x{-}y)\rangle {*}u) \\ {\wedge }\,\forall v(\mathrm {Bin}(v,y)\,{\rightarrow }\,\lnot \tilde{\varphi }(\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1{-}y)){*}v) \end{pmatrix} \\&\,\,{\vee }\; \forall v \begin{pmatrix} \mathrm {Bin}(v,z)\,{\rightarrow }\lnot \tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1{-}z)){*}v) \end{pmatrix}. \end{aligned}$$

If \(z\,{=}\,0\), the latter disjunct is obviously the case. For \(z\,{>}\,0\), if the former is the case for \(z{-}1\) then it is the case for z. So assume \(\forall v(\mathrm {Bin}(v,z{-}1)\,{\rightarrow }\,\lnot \tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}2{-}z)){*}v))\) with \(z\,{>}\,0\). If \(\forall v(\mathrm {Bin}(v,z)\,{\rightarrow }\,\lnot \tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1{-}z)){*}v))\) is not the case, then by \(\varDelta ^0_0\mathsf{-LEM} \) we have u with \(\mathrm {Bin}(u,z{-}1)\,{\wedge }\, \tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{+}1{-}z)) {*}\langle 1{-}\pi (x{-}z)\rangle {*}u))\), and hence the pair of this u and \(y\,{:=}\,z{-}1\) witnesses the former disjunct for z. Once the induction is completed, with \(z\,{=}\,x{+}1\), we have

$$\begin{aligned}&(\exists y\,{\le }\,x)\exists u\begin{pmatrix}\mathrm {Bin}(u,y) \,{\wedge }\,\tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{-}y)) {*}\langle 1{-}\pi (x{-}y)\rangle {*}u) \,{\wedge }\\ \forall v(\mathrm {Bin}(v,y)\,{\rightarrow }\, \lnot \tilde{\varphi }((\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{-}y)) {*}\langle \pi (x{-}y)\rangle {*}v)) \end{pmatrix}\\&\quad \quad \;\;\;\;{\vee }\; \forall v(\mathrm {Bin}(v,x{+}1)\,{\rightarrow }\,\lnot \tilde{\varphi }(v)). \end{aligned}$$

In the former case, \(\mathrm {Ob2}(\pi ',\tau )\,{\wedge }\,\mathrm {WKG}[\varphi ](\pi ')\) for a play \(\pi '\) in which Player I chooses \(\pi {\upharpoonright }(x{-}y)\) in the first phase and u in the third phase. In the latter case, \(\mathrm {Ob2}(\pi '',\tau )\,{\wedge }\,\mathrm {WKG}[\varphi ](\pi '')\) for a play \(\pi ''\) in which Player I chooses \(\pi {\upharpoonright }x\) in the first phase. \(\square \)

The last part of the proof clarifies the connection between the main disjunction of our game \(\mathrm {WKG}[\varphi ]\) and the disjunctive formula to which induction is applied in [24, Lemma 5.3].

On the other hand, we do not know the strength of the result of applying the same modification to \(\varSigma ^0_1\mathsf{-DetImp2} ^*\): for any \(\varSigma ^0_1\) formula \(\varphi (\pi )\) with a distinguished variable \(\pi \),

$$\begin{aligned} (\forall \sigma \,{<}\,\underline{2})(\exists \pi \,{<}\,\underline{2}) (\mathrm {Ob1}(\sigma ,\pi )\,{\wedge }\,\lnot \varphi (\pi ))\, {\rightarrow }\,(\exists \tau \,{<}\,\underline{2})\mathrm {WS2}^*_\varphi (\tau ). \end{aligned}$$

Similarly to the comment concerning the first question raised at the end of the last section, we can point out that some mystery happens for the first disjuncts, but that the situation for the second disjuncts is rather straightforward.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sato, K. Bounded inductive dichotomy: separation of open and clopen determinacies with finite alternatives in constructive contexts. Arch. Math. Logic 61, 399–435 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-021-00795-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-021-00795-2

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation