Skip to main content
Log in

Rational egoism versus adaptive egoism as fundamental postulate for a descriptive theory of human behavior

  • Presidential Address
  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Summary and conclusions

What I have proposed for consideration is a view of human behavior which is a complement to both the rational egoist model of individual behavior, and the sociobiological model of species behavior. Cooperative behavior can benefit all members of a group and increase each individual's chances of survival. Rather complicated cooperative behavior patterns are observed in some species, and give testimony to the importance of genetic heritage in explaining behavior. But anyone who has ever observed small children at play must believe that the instincts for selfish action dominate those to cooperate in humans. What humans inherit is a capacity to learn, to discriminate one situation from another, to generalize from past experience. But cooperative behavior among humans is learned.

The usual depiction of this learning process by modelers of rational egoistic behavior is to assume that learning takes place within the context of the game. Since learning takes time, a repeated game is required to achieve cooperation. The most successful strategy for teaching one's fellow-player to cooperate appears to be the tit-for-tat strategy. It is interesting how closely Axelrod's (1984) description of tit-for-tat's success in bringing about cooperation parallels the psychologist's description of learning. The cooperative behavior of one player is rewarded by the cooperative behavior of the other. Noncooperative behavior is punished. ‘The emergence, growth, and maintenance of cooperation ... require an individual to be able to recognize another player who has been dealt with before [read stimulus]. They also require that one's prior history of interactions with this player can be remembered, so that a player can be responsive' [read one has a conditioned behavior pattern] (p. 174).

Axelrod emphasizes that ‘there is no need to assume that the players are rational. They need not be trying to maximize their rewards. Their strategies may simply reflect standard operating procedures, rules of thumb ... habits ... The actions that players take are not necessarily even conscious choices’ (p. 18, and again at p. 173). Axelrod thus clearly believes that the tit-for-tat strategy as a description of behavior applies to situations, in which the rational portion of the rational egoism assumption is inappropriate. Throughout the book he moves back and forth from examples for which rational egoism in a prisoners' dilemma might fit, and others where it will not. He spends a whole chapter on ‘The Evolution of Cooperation in Biological Systems’ (written with William D. Hamilton, Chapter 5). The parallel between the basic principle of the evolutionary approach, ‘whatever is successful is likely to appear more often in the future’ (p. 169), and the basic principle of behaviorist psychology, ‘positive reinforcement increases the future likelihood of operant behavior,’ is again obvious. Operant conditioning describes the learning process of the individual in adapting to the environment, natural selection describes the evolutionary process of species adaptation (Notterman, 1970: 13).

The common thread running through each of these paradigms from selfish gene, through thirsty rat, to homo economicus is egoism. And, I submit, the only assumption essential to a descriptive and predictive science of human behavior is egoism. What then of the rationality assumption? A moment's reflection will reveal that the only use to which we put the rationality assumption is to add precision to the predictions stemming from the egoism postulate, as when we operationalize rational egoism by assuming the individual maximizes an objective function. Now rigor is an important and useful property of a model, so long as it does not come at the expense of realism. Fortunately, the public choice analyst can have both the rigor of mathematical modeling and the realism of assuming only egoistic motivation, if he/she treats the rationality assumption as an as if behavioral assumption.

Over 35 years ago, Armen Alchian (1950), answered critics of the profits maximization assumption in the theory of the firm by arguing that in a competitive environment the less profitable firms perish, and the surviving firms adopt decision rules as if they had been consciously trying to maximize profits, whatever the criteria actually employed to make decisions. Competition for survival selects gene structures as if the evolution of the species were maximizing the probability of survival. Where cooperation has significant advantages for all members of a group, the group will adopt mores and laws which condition people to behave as if they were maximizing a function like (1) with θ = 1. Over time, those social institutions for conditioning cooperative behavior will survive that maximize group survival chances. The weaker the social conditioning of cooperative behavior is, the more individual behavior will resemble the maximization of (1) with some θ < 1. In the limit, when individual decisions do not impinge of the welfare of others, individual behavior resembles the maximization of (1) as if θ = 0. Thus, behavior can be modeled as if it was motivated by conscious choices to maximize different objective functions, with the specification of the objective function varying to reflect the level of analysis (species, group, individual), the adaptive history of the subjects, and the context of the actions.

For most of us this is a comforting thought, since we have been conditioned to working with optimization models. But there is an important difference between as if maximization based on a pure egoism postulate and rational egoism as usually employed. The difference lies in determining what goes into the objective function.

A model of man based on as if maximization of a socially conditioned or an evolutionarily molded objective function, is a model of adaptive behavior. Thus, what I am proposing is that the rational egoism postulate be replaced by an adaptive egoism postulate to model human behavior. The difference between these assumptions is similar to the difference between the rational expectations and adaptive expectations assumptions used in economics. To describe an individual's expectations at time t using the rational expectations assumption we look at what happens after t, to describe them under adaptive expectations we look at what happened before t. Rational egoism, as usually modeled, considers only the consequences of different actions, the payoffs in the strategy matrix. When modeling the behavior of an individual, who has played the game several times before, who has been rewarded for choosing certain strategies, and punished for others, this forward looking objective function can give accurate predictions of an individual's actions. For much of what we do in public choice as in economics, this rarefied setting for making choices may come close enough to matching the context in which isolated individuals act to give us reasonable descriptions of human behavior. But when we attempt to explain behavior in more complicated social contexts, as we so often do in public choice, charity, voting, crime, then we shall add to the descriptive power of our models by recognizing that man has not only a future, but also a past.

George C. Homans (1958, 1962, 1964, 1967, 1974) has argued for many years that a unified sociological theory can and should be built on behavioralist psychology principles to displace the many discordant theories of modern sociology. Were economics and rational politics to replace rational egoism with adaptive egoism as their fundamental behavioral postulate, the possibility would exist for constructing a common methodological foundation for all of the social sciences. For once interdisciplinary research within the social sciences would not be hampered by basic differences in methodologies. The potential gains in knowledge from cross-fertilization are enormous. Certainly these gains are worth the costs of revising our modeling of human behavior, where necessary, as the replacement of rational egoism by adaptive egoism dictates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alchian, A.A. (1950). Uncertainty, evolution and economic theory. Journal of Political Economy 58 (June) 211–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alger, D. (1986). Investigating oligopolies within the laboratory. Washington: FTC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J. (1963). Social choice and individual values, rev. ed. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J. (1982). Risk perception in psychology and economics. Economic Inquiry: 20 (January) 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1984). The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. (1976). Altruism, egoism, and genetic fitness. Journal of Economic Literature: 14 (September) 817–826.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgeman, P. (1955). Reflections of a physicist, 2nd ed. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chamberlin, J.R. (1978). The logic of collective action: Some experimental results. Behavioral Science 23: 441–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, R. (1978). Altruism: Human, cultural, or what? In L. Wispe (Ed.), Altruism, sympathy, and helping, 79–98. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coughlin, P. (1982). Pareto optimality of policy proposals with probabilistic voting. Public Choice 39(3): 427–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coughlin, P. and Nitzan, S. (1981). Electoral outcomes with probabilistic voting and Nash social welfare maxima. Journal of Public Economics 15 (February): 113–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A. (1986). The case for a multiple utility conception. George Washington University, Mimeo.

  • Ferejohn, J.A., and Fiorina, M.P. (1974). The paradox of not voting: A decision theoretic analysis. American Political Science Review 68: (June): 525–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grether, D.M., and Plott, C.R. (1979). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review 69 (September): 623–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, R. (1982). Collective action. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J.C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy 63 (August): 309–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, E., Walster, G.W., and Piliavin, J.A. (1978). Equity theory and helping relationships. In L. Wispe (ed.), Altrusim, sympathy, and helping. New York: Academic Press. 115–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heiner, R.A. (1983). The origin of predictive behavior. American Economic Review 73 (September): 560–595.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschleifer, J. (1977). Economics from a biological viewpoint. Journal of Law and Economics 20 (April): 1–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschleifer, J. (1980). Privacy: Its origin, function, and future. Journal of Legal Studies 9 (December): 649–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschleifer, J. (1985). The expanding domain of economics. American Economic Review 75 (December): 53–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, E., and Spitzer, M.L. (1985). Experimental law and economics: An introduction. Columbia Law Review 85 (June): 991–1036.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homans, G.C. (1958). Social behavior as exchange. American Journal of Sociology 62 (May) 597–606.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homans, G.C. (1962). Sentiments and activities: Essays in social science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homans, G.C. (1964). Bringing men back in. American Sociological Review 29 (December) 809–818.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homans, G.C. (1967). The nature of social science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homans, G.C. (1974). Social behavior: Its elementary forms, rev. ed. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hummell, H.J., and Opp, K.-D. (1971). Die Reduzierbarkeit von Soziologie auf Psychologie. Braunschweig: Vieweg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, R.M., McCue, K.F., and Plott, C.R. (1985). Public goods provision in an experimental environment. Journal of Public Economics 26 (February): 51–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (1984). Nicht-explanative Funktionen eines Homo Oeconomicus' und Beschränkungen seiner explanativen Rolle. In M.J. Holler (ed.) Homo Oeconomicus II, 7–49. Munich: N. Leudemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1963). ‘The development of children's orientations toward a moral order, I. Sequence in the development of moral thought. Vita Humana, 6: 11–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunreuther, H., et al. (1978). Disaster insurance protection. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ledyard, J.O. (1984). The pure theory of large two candidate elections. Public Choice 44(1): 7–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macauley, J.R., and Berkowitz, L. (1970). Altruism and helping behavior: Social psychological studies of some antecedents and consequences. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, H. (1982). Selfishness, altruism, and rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marwell, G., and Ames, R.E. (1979). Experiments on the provision of public goods I: Resources, interest, group size, and the free rider problem. American Journal of Sociology 84 (May): 1335–1360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marwell, G., and Ames, R.E. (1980) Experiments on the provision of public goods II: Provision points, stakes, experience and the free rider problem. American Journal of Sociology 85: 926–937.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marwell, G., and Ames, R.E. (1981) Economists free ride, does anyone else? Journal of Public Economics 15 (June): 295–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, L.S., and Good, I.J. (1975). Is minimax regret applicable to voting decisions? American Political Science Review. 69 (September): 916–917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millenson, J.R. (1967). Principles of behavioral analysis. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Notterman, J.M. (1970). Behavior: A systematic approach. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, O.R., Battalio, R.C., and Holcomb, J.H., Jr. (1985). Observations on history and market signalling in duopoly markets. University of Wyoming. Mimeo.

  • Plott, C.R. (1982). Industrial organization theory and experimental economics. Journal of Economic Literature 20 (December): 1485–1527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pommerehne, W.W., Schneider, F., and Zweifel, P. (1982). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon: A reexamination. American Economic Review 72 (June): 569–574.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, F., and Pommerehne, W.W. (1981). On the rationality of free riding: An experiment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 96 (November): 689–704.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, B., and Lacey, H. (1982). Behaviorism, science, and human nature. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P., and Lichtenstein, S. (1983). Preference reversals: A Broader perspective. American Economic Review 73 (September): 596–605.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V.L. (1979a). Incentive compatible experimental processes for the provision of public goods. V.L. Smith, (ed.), Experimental economics, vol. 1, 59–168. Greenwich: JAI Press'.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, V.L. (1979b). An experimental comparison of three public good decision mechanisms. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 81(2): 189–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staddon, J.E.R. (1983). Adaptive behavior and learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1976). Anarchy and cooperation. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1981).; Why so much stability? Public Choice 37(2): 189–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review 76 (January): 31–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211 30 (January): 453–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. (1975). Die zwei Soziologien. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. (1983). ‘The rebirth of utilitarian sociology. Social Science Journal 20 (July): 71–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O.E. (1985). The economic institutions of capitalism. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E.O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt, U. (1985). Economic behavior and biological evolution: Some remarks on the sociobiology debate. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft 141 (September): 365–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt, U. (1986). Evolution and stability of cooperation without enforcable contracts. Kyklos 38(2).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

Revised version of the Presidential Address presented to the Public Choice Society, Baltimore, March 22, 1986. Support for the research on this paper was received in part from the Thyssen Foundation of Germany and the Sloan Foundation Workshop grant to the Department of Economics, University of Maryland, and the Thyssen Foundation of Germany. Helpful comments were received from Jack Hirschleifer, Norbert Hornstein, Hartmut Kliemt, Viktor Vanberg, and Ulrich Witt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mueller, D.C. Rational egoism versus adaptive egoism as fundamental postulate for a descriptive theory of human behavior. Public Choice 51, 3–23 (1986). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141682

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141682

Keywords

Navigation