Skip to main content

Typed and Untyped Disquotational Truth

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 36))

Abstract

We present an overview of typed and untyped disquotational truth theories with the emphasis on their (non)conservativity over the base theory of syntax. Two types of conservativity are discussed: syntactic and semantic. We observe in particular that TB—one of the most basic disquotational theories—is not semantically conservative over its base; we show also that an untyped disquotational theory PTB is a syntactically conservative extension of Peano Arithmetic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It’s worth mentioning that Horwich attributes truth to propositions, not sentences or utterances.

  2. 2.

    Admittedly, it is not the only possible option. Cf. Beall (2009), where disquotationalism is understood as a view that truth is a “fully transparent device” (p. 3); more exactly: it’s “a device introduced via rules of intersubstitution: that \(Tr(ulcorner \alpha urcorner)\) and α are intersubstitutable in all (nonopaque) contexts” (p. 1). On this approach, adopting T-biconditionals as axioms might be just one of the possible ways to give justice to the disquotationalist’s intuitions.

  3. 3.

    See e.g. Halbach (2001), p. 188: “As far as I can see, neither have deflationists subscribed to conservativeness explicitly nor does it follow from one of their other doctrines. (…) But if the deflationist understands his claim that truth is not a substantial notion as implying that his truth theory has no substantial consequences, he commits a mistake.”

  4. 4.

    For a philosophical discussion of conservativeness as a demand for deflationary truth theories, see also (Cieśliński 2010), (Ketland 2010) and (Tennant 2010).

  5. 5.

    Cf. Halbach (2011), p. 55, where the proof is given that UTB 1 is conservative over PA.

  6. 6.

    On partial truth predicates, see Kaye (1991), p. 119 ff.

  7. 7.

    Cf. (Kaye 1991), p. 228, Proposition 15.4.

  8. 8.

    Although we worked in M 2, the transition to M 1 is made possible by the fact that all formulas in our type belong to the language L n , i.e. they do not contain “T n ”, so if they are satisfied in M 2, they are also satisfied in M 1.

  9. 9.

    After obtaining Theorem 7, I found out that the result was proved earlier by Fredrik Engström. Engström’s work is unpublished.

  10. 10.

    For more about coded sets, see e.g. Kaye (1991) p. 141 ff.

  11. 11.

    More information about prime models can be found in Kaye (1991), p. 91 ff.

  12. 12.

    One path could consist in considering maximal conservative sets of substitutions of a T-schema. It has been shown however, that there are uncountably many such sets and none of them is axiomatizable. See Cieśliński (2007).

  13. 13.

    In Curry’s paradox we consider a sentence ψ satisfying the condition: \(\psi \equiv [T(ulcorner \psi urcorner) \rightarrow 0 = 1]\). It turns out then that adopting a T-biconditional for ψ results in a contradiction. However, a Curry sentence ψ constructed by diagonalization contains an occurrence of the truth predicate which is not negated.

  14. 14.

    A presentation of KF can be found in Halbach (2011), starting on p. 195.

  15. 15.

    The proof of Theorem 13 was presented on the “Truth be told” conference in Amsterdam (2011), and also in (Cieśliński 2011).

  16. 16.

    Strictly speaking, T 0 will contain not only (codes of) arithmetical sentences true in M, but also these nonstandard numbers a, for which the formula “\(a \in d_0\)” is satisfied in M.

  17. 17.

    In this respect the situation of an adherent of a typed disquotational theory is quite comfortable; his problems lie elsewhere: in the deductive weakness of his theory.

References

  • Beall, Jc. (2009). Spandrels of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cieśliński, C. (2007). Deflationism, conservativeness and maximality. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36, 695–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cieśliński, C. (2010). Truth, conservativeness, and provability. Mind, 119, 409–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cieśliński, C. (2011). T-equivalences for positive sentences. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4, 319–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1994). Deflationist views of meaning and content. Mind, 103, 249–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V. (2001). How innocent is deflationism? Synthese, 126, 167–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V. (2009). Reducing compositional to disquotational truth. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 2, 786–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V. (2011). Axiomatic theories of truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L. (1995). The semantical paradoxes, the neutrality of truth and the neutrality of the minimalist theory of truth. In P. Cortois (Ed.), The many problems of realism of studies in the general philosophy of science (Vol. 3, pp. 173–187). Tilburg: Tilburg University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1990). Truth. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaye, R. (1991). Models of Peano arithmetic. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ketland, J. (1999).Deflationism and tarski’s paradise. Mind, 108, 69–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ketland, J. (2010). Truth, conservativeness, and provability: Reply to Cieslinski. Mind, 119, 423–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (1992). Maximal consistent sets of instances of Tarski’s schema (T). Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21, 235–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V. (2006). In praise of the free lunch: Why disquotationalists should embrace compositional semantics. In V. F. Hendricks, S. A. Pedersen, & T. Bollander (Eds.), Self reference (pp. 95–120) Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1998). Proof and truth: Through thick and thin. Journal of Philosophy, 95, 493–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tennant, N. (2010). Deflationism and the Gödel-Phenomena: Reply to Cieslinski. Mind, 119, 437–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by a grant number N N101 170438 by the Polish Ministry of Science and Education (MNiSW).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cezary Cieśliński .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cieśliński, C. (2015). Typed and Untyped Disquotational Truth. In: Achourioti, T., Galinon, H., Martínez Fernández, J., Fujimoto, K. (eds) Unifying the Philosophy of Truth. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9673-6_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics