Skip to main content

Quasi-Quantization: Classical Statistical Theories with an Epistemic Restriction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Fundamental Theories of Physics ((FTPH,volume 181))

Abstract

A significant part of quantum theory can be obtained from a single innovation relative to classical theories, namely, that there is a fundamental restriction on the sorts of statistical distributions over physical states that can be prepared. This is termed an “epistemic restriction” because it implies a fundamental limit on the amount of knowledge that any observer can have about the physical state of a classical system. This article provides an overview of epistricted theories, that is, theories that start from a classical statistical theory and apply an epistemic restriction. We consider both continuous and discrete degrees of freedom, and show that a particular epistemic restriction called classical complementarity provides the beginning of a unification of all known epistricted theories. This restriction appeals to the symplectic structure of the underlying classical theory and consequently can be applied to an arbitrary classical degree of freedom. As such, it can be considered as a kind of quasi-quantization scheme; “quasi” because it generally only yields a theory describing a subset of the preparations, transformations and measurements allowed in the full quantum theory for that degree of freedom, and because in some cases, such as for binary variables, it yields a theory that is a distortion of such a subset. Finally, we propose to classify quantum phenomena as weakly or strongly nonclassical by whether or not they can arise in an epistricted theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We are here refering to the first part of Ref. [5]. In the second part, the author proposes a theory wherein there is a restriction on what can be known about the outcome of measurements, rather than a restriction on what can be known about some underlying ontic state. As such, the latter theory is not an epistricted theory.

  2. 2.

    Note that for the purposes of this article, the term “quantum theory” refers to a theory schema that can be applied to many different degrees of freedom: particles, fields and discrete systems.

  3. 3.

    Note that the theory of stochastic electrodynamics has some significant similarities to an epistricted theory of electrodynamics, but there are also significant differences. Many authors who describe themselves as working on stochastic electrodynamics posit a nondeterministic dynamical law for the fields, whereas an epistricted theory of electrodynamics is one wherein agents merely lack knowledge of the electrodynamic fields, which continue to evolve deterministically. That being said, Boyer’s version of stochastic electrodynamics [8] does not posit any modification of the dynamical law and so is closer to what we are imagining here. A second difference is that in stochastic electrodynamics, there is no epistemic restriction on the matter degrees of freedom. However, if one degree of freedom can interact with another, then to enforce an epistemic restriction on one, it is necessary to enforce a similar epistemic restriction on the other. In other words, the assumptions of stochastic electrodynamics were inconsistent. The sort of epistricted theory of electrodynamics we propose here is one that would apply the epistemic restriction to the matter and to the fields.

  4. 4.

    It should be noted that many researchers had previously recognized the possibility of recovering many of these quantum phenomena if one compared quantum states to probability distributions in a classical statistical theory [912].

  5. 5.

    This terminology comes from optics, where it was originally used to describe a pair of variables that are canonically conjugate to one another. It was inherited from the use of the expression in astronomy, where it applies to a pair of celestial bodies and describes the configuration in which they have an angular separation of 90\(^{\circ }\) as seen from the earth.

  6. 6.

    It seems that the quadrature epistricted theory of bits is about as close as one can get to the stabilizer theory for qubits while still being local and noncontextual.

References

  1. R.W. Spekkens, Evidence for the epistemic view of quantum states: a toy theory. Phys. Rev. A 75(3), 032110 (2007)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  2. S.D. Bartlett, T. Rudolph, R.W. Spekkens, Reconstruction of Gaussian quantum mechanics from Liouville mechanics with an epistemic restriction. Phys. Rev. A 86(1), 012103 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  3. M. Born, E. Wolf, Principles of Optics: Electromagnetic Theory of Propagation, Interference and Diffraction of Light (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. M.F. Pusey, Stabilizer notation for Spekkens’ toy theory. Found. Phys. 42(5), 688–708 (2012)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. S.J. Van Enk, A toy model for quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 37(10), 1447–1460 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. D. Gross, Hudson’s theorem for finite-dimensional quantum systems. J. Math. Phys. 47, 122107 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  7. O. Schreiber, R.W. Spekkens, The power of epistemic restrictions in reconstructing quantum theory: from trits to qutrits, unpublished, 2008. R.W. Spekkens, The power of epistemic restrictions in reconstructing quantum theory, Talk, Perimeter Institute, http://pirsa.org/09080009/, 10 August 2008

  8. T.H. Boyer, Foundations of Radiation Theory and Quantum Electrodynamics, Chapter A Brief Survey of Stochastic Electrodynamics (Plenum, New York, 1980)

    Google Scholar 

  9. C.M. Caves, C.A. Fuchs, Quantum information: how much Information in a state vector? (1996). arXiv:quant-ph/9601025

  10. J.V. Emerson, Quantum chaos and quantum-classical correspondence. Ph.D. thesis, Simon Fraser University, Vancouver, Canada (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  11. L. Hardy, Disentangling nonlocality and teleportation (1999). arXiv:quant-ph/9906123

  12. K.A. Kirkpatrick, Quantal behavior in classical probability. Found. Phys. Lett. 16(3), 199–224 (2003)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. W.K. Wootters, W.H. Zurek, A single quantum cannot be cloned. Nature 299(5886), 802–803 (1982)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. C.H. Bennett, G. Brassard, C. Crépeau, R. Jozsa, A. Peres, W.K. Wootters, Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen channels. Phys. Rev. Lett. 70(13), 1895 (1993)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. C.H. Bennett, G. Brassard et al., Quantum cryptography: public key distribution and coin tossing, in Proceedings of IEEE International Conference on Computers, Systems and Signal Processing, vol. 175, (New York 1984)

    Google Scholar 

  16. R. Horodecki, P. Horodecki, M. Horodecki, K. Horodecki, Quantum entanglement. Rev. Mod. Phys. 81(2), 865 (2009)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. C.H. Bennett, D.P. DiVincenzo, C.A. Fuchs, T. Mor, E. Rains, P.W. Shor, J.A. Smolin, W.K. Wootters, Quantum nonlocality without entanglement. Phys. Rev. A 59(2), 1070 (1999)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. C.H. Bennett, D.P. DiVincenzo, T. Mor, P.W. Shor, J.A. Smolin, B.M. Terhal, Unextendible product bases and bound entanglement. Phys. Rev. Lett. 82(26), 5385 (1999)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. M.D. Choi, Completely positive linear maps on complex matrices. Linear Algebra Appl. 10, 285–290 (1975)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. A. Jamiołkowski, Linear transformations which preserve trace and positive semidefiniteness of operators. Rep. Math. Phys. 3, 275–278 (1972)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. M.A. Naimark. Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR, Ser. Mat. 4:277–318 (1940)

    Google Scholar 

  22. W.F. Stinespring, Positive functions on C*-algebras. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 6(2), 211–216 (1955)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. J.S. Bell, On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1(3), 195–200 (1964)

    Google Scholar 

  24. S. Kochen, E.P. Specker, The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. J. Math. Mech. 17, 59 (1967)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. R.W. Spekkens, Contextuality for preparations, transformations, and unsharp measurements. Phys. Rev. A 71(5), 052108 (2005)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Y.C. Liang, R.W. Spekkens, H.M. Wiseman, Specker’s parable of the overprotective seer: a road to contextuality, nonlocality and complementarity. Phys. Rep. 506(1), 1–39 (2011)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. N. Harrigan, R.W. Spekkens, Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states. Found. Phys. 40, 125 (2010)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. C.M. Caves, C.A. Fuchs, R. Schack, Quantum probabilities as Bayesian probabilities. Phys. Rev. A 65(2), 022305 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. C.A. Fuchs, Quantum mechanics as quantum information, mostly. J. Mod. Opt. 50(6–7), 987–1023 (2003)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. C.A. Fuchs, R. Schack, Quantum-Bayesian coherence. Rev. Mod. Phys. 85(4), 1693 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  31. M.F. Pusey, J. Barrett, T. Rudolph, On the reality of the quantum state. Nat. Phys. 8(6), 475–478 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. P.G. Lewis, D. Jennings, J. Barrett, T. Rudolph, Distinct quantum states can be compatible with a single state of reality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 109(15), 150404 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  33. R. Colbeck, R. Renner, Is a system’s wave function in one-to-one correspondence with its elements of reality? Phys. Rev. Lett. 108(15), 150402 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  34. M.S. Leifer, R.W. Spekkens, Towards a formulation of quantum theory as a causally neutral theory of Bayesian inference. Phys. Rev. A 88(5), 052130 (2013)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  35. C.J. Wood, R.W. Spekkens, The lesson of causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: causal explanations of bell-inequality violations require fine-tuning (2012). arXiv:1208.4119

  36. A. Zeilinger, A foundational principle for quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 29(4), 631–643 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  37. T. Paterek, B. Dakić, Č. Brukner, Theories of systems with limited information content. New J. Phys. 12(5), 053037 (2010)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  38. B. Coecke, B. Edwards, R.W. Spekkens, Phase groups and the origin of non-locality for qubits. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 270(2), 15–36 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. S. Mansfield, T. Fritz, Hardy’s non-locality paradox and possibilistic conditions for non-locality. Found. Phys. 42(5), 709–719 (2012)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. S. Abramsky, L. Hardy, Logical bell inequalities. Phys. Rev. A 85(6), 062114 (2012)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  41. B. Schumacher, M.D. Westmoreland, Modal quantum theory. Found. Phys. 42(7), 918–925 (2012)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. J. Barrett, Information processing in generalized probabilistic theories. Phys. Rev. A 75(3), 032304 (2007)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  43. L. Hardy, Quantum theory from five reasonable axioms (2001). arXiv:quant-ph/0101012

  44. B. Coecke, E.O. Paquette, Categories for the practising physicist, in New Structures for Physics. Lecture Notes in Physics, ed. by B. Coecke (Springer, Berlin, 2009), pp. 173–286

    Google Scholar 

  45. B. Coecke, B. Edwards, Toy quantum categories. Electron. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 270(1), 29–40 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. G. Chiribella, G.M. DAriano, P. Perinotti, Probabilistic theories with purification. Phys. Rev. A 81(6), 062348 (2010)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  47. E. Wigner, On the quantum correction for thermodynamic equilibrium. Phys. Rev. 40(5), 749 (1932)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  48. C. Gardiner, P. Zoller, Quantum Noise: A Handbook of Markovian and Non-Markovian Quantum Stochastic Methods with Applications to Quantum Optics, vol. 56 (Springer, New York, 2004)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  49. K.S. Gibbons, M.J. Hoffman, W.K. Wootters, Discrete phase space based on finite fields. Phys. Rev. A 70(6), 062101 (2004)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  50. R.W. Spekkens, Negativity and contextuality are equivalent notions of nonclassicality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 101(2), 20401 (2008)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. N.D. Mermin, Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell. Rev. Mod. Phys. 65(3), 803 (1993)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  52. D.M. Greenberger, M.A. Horne, A. Zeilinger, Going beyond Bell’s theorem, Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Theory and Conceptions of the Universe (Springer, New York, 1989), pp. 69–72

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  53. D. Gottesman, The Heisenberg representation of quantum computers (1998). arXiv:quant-ph/9807006

Download references

Acknowledgments

I acknowledge Stephen Bartlett and Terry Rudolph for discussions on the quadrature subtheory of quantum mechanics, Jonathan Barrett for suggesting to define the Poisson bracket in the discrete case in terms of finite differences, and Giulio Chiribella, Joel Wallman and Blake Stacey for comments on a draft of this article. Much of the work presented here summarizes unpublished results obtained in collaboration with Olaf Schreiber. Research at Perimeter Institute is supported by the Government of Canada through Industry Canada and by the Province of Ontario through the Ministry of Research and Innovation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert W. Spekkens .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix A: Quadrature Quantum Subtheories and the Stabilizer Formalism

Appendix A: Quadrature Quantum Subtheories and the Stabilizer Formalism

In quantum information theory, there has been a great deal of work on a particular quantum subtheory for discrete systems of prime dimension (qubits and qutrits in particular) which is known as the stabilizer formalism [6, 53].

A stabilizer state is defined as a joint eigenstate of a set of commuting Weyl operators. By Eq. (53), two Weyl operators commute if and only if the corresponding phase-space displacement vectors have vanishing symplectic inner product,

$$ [ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}) , \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}') ]=0 \;\text { if and only if }\; \langle \mathbf{a}, \mathbf{a}'\rangle =0. $$

Consequently, the sets of commuting Weyl operators, and therefore the stabilizer states, are parametrized by the isotropic subspaces of \(\Omega \). Specifically, for each isotropic subspace M of \(\Omega \) and each vector \(\mathbf{v}\in {\textit{JM}}\equiv \{ J\mathbf{u} : \mathbf{u} \in M \}\), we can define a stabilizer state \(\rho ^{(\mathrm stab)}_{M,\mathbf{v}}\) as the projector onto the joint eigenspace of \(\{ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}): \mathbf{a} \in M\}\) where \(\hat{W}(\mathbf{a})\) has eigenvalue \(\chi (\langle \mathbf{v}, \mathbf{a} \rangle )\).

We will show here that the set of stabilizer states is precisely equivalent to the set of quadrature states.

To describe the connection, it is convenient to introduce some additional notions from symplectic geometry. The symplectic complement of a subspace V, which we will denote as \(V^C\), is the set of vectors that have vanishing symplectic inner product with every vector in V,

$$ V^{C}\equiv \{ \mathbf{m}' \in \Omega : \mathbf{m'}^T J \mathbf{m} =0, \; \forall \mathbf{m} \in V \}, $$

where J is the symplectic form, defined in Eq. (15). This is not equivalent to the Euclidean complement of a subspace V, which is the set of vectors that have vanishing Euclidean inner product with every vector in V,

$$ V^{\perp }\equiv \{ \mathbf{m}' \in \Omega : \mathbf{m'}^T \mathbf{m} =0, \; \forall \mathbf{m} \in V \}, $$

The composition of the two complements will be relevant in what follows. It turns out that the latter is related to V by an isomorphism; it is simply the image of V under left-multiplication by the symplectic form J,

$$ (V^{\perp })^{C}\equiv {\textit{JV}} = \{ J\mathbf{u} : \mathbf{u} \in V \}. $$

Note that if V is isotropic, then \((V^{\perp })^{C}\) is as well.

Proposition 1

Consider the quadrature state \(\rho _{V,\mathbf{v}}\), with V an isotropic subspace of \(\Omega \) and \(\mathbf{v}\in V\) a valuation vector, which is the joint eigenstate of the commuting set of quadrature observables \(\{ \mathcal {O}_{f} : \mathbf{f}\in V \}\), where the eigenvalue of \(\mathcal {O}_f\) is \(f(\mathbf{v})\). This is equivalent to the stabilizer state \(\rho ^{(\mathrm{stab})}_{M,\mathbf{v}}\), which is the joint eigenstate of the commuting set of Weyl operators \(\{ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}) : \mathbf{a} \in M\}\) where \(M \equiv (V^{\perp })^C\) is the isotropic subspace that is the symplectic complement of the Euclidean complement of V, and where the eigenvalue of \(\hat{W}(\mathbf{a})\) is \(\chi (\langle \mathbf{v},\mathbf{a} \rangle )\).

Proof

Consider first a single degree of freedom. Every quadrature observable \(\mathcal {O}_{f}\) can be expressed in terms of the position observable \(\mathcal {O}_q\) as follows: if \(S_f\) is the symplectic matrix such that \(\mathbf{f} = S_f \mathbf{q}\), then \(\mathcal {O}_{f} = \hat{V}(S_f) \mathcal {O}_{q} \hat{V}(S_f)^{\dag }\). Now note that the position basis can equally well be characterized as the eigenstates of the boost operators. Specifically, \(\hat{B}(\mathtt{p}) |\mathtt{q}\rangle _q = \chi (\mathtt{q p}) |\mathtt{q}\rangle _q\), that is, an element \(|\mathtt{q}\rangle _q\) of the position basis is an eigenstate of the set of operators \(\{ \hat{B}(\mathtt{p}): \mathtt{p}\in \mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}_d \}\) where the eigenvalue of \(\hat{B}(\mathtt{p})\) is \(\chi (\mathtt{qp})\). The element \(|\mathtt{f}\rangle _f\) of the basis associated to the quadrature operator \(\mathcal {O}_f\) is defined as \(|\mathtt{f}\rangle _f \equiv \hat{V}(S_f)|\mathtt{f}\rangle _q\) and consequently can be characterized as an eigenstate of the set of operators \(\{ \hat{V}(S_f) \hat{B}(\mathtt{g}) \hat{V}(S_f)^{\dag }: \mathtt{g}\in \mathbb {R}/\mathbb {Z}_d \}\) where the eigenvalue of \(\hat{V}(S_f) \hat{B}(\mathtt{g}) \hat{V}(S_f)^{\dag }\) is \(\chi (\mathtt{fg})\). This can be stated equivalently as follows: the element \(|\mathtt{f}\rangle _f\) of the basis associated to the quadrature operator \(\mathcal {O}_f\) is the eigenstate of the set of Weyl operators \(\{ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}): \mathbf{a}\in \mathrm{span}(S_f\mathbf{p}) \}\) where the eigenvalue of \(\hat{W}(\mathbf{a})\) is \(\chi ( \mathtt{f}\langle \mathbf{f},\mathbf{a}\rangle )\). Noting that

$$\begin{aligned} \mathrm{span}(S_f\mathbf{p})&=\mathrm{span}(S_f J\mathbf{q}),\nonumber \\&= \mathrm{span}({\textit{JS}}_f \mathbf{q}),\nonumber \\&= \mathrm{span}(J \mathbf{f}), \end{aligned}$$
(91)

we can just as well characterize \(\hat{\Pi }_f(\mathtt{f})\) as the projector onto the joint eigenspace of the Weyl operators \(\{ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}): \mathbf{a}\in \mathrm{span}(J \mathbf{f}) \}\).

Now consider n degrees of freedom. The quadrature state associated with \((V,\mathbf{v})\) has the form

$$\begin{aligned} \rho _{V,\mathbf{v}} = \frac{1}{\mathcal {N}} \prod _{\mathbf{f}^{(i)}: \mathrm{span}(\mathbf{f}^{(i)})=V} \hat{\Pi }_{f^{(i)}}\left( f^{(i)}(\mathbf{v})\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(92)

By an argument similar to that used for a single degree of freedom, this is an eigenstate of the Weyl operators \(\{ \hat{W}(\mathbf{a}): \mathbf{a}\in \mathrm{span}(J \mathbf{f}^{(i)}) \}\) where the eigenvalue of \(\hat{W}(\mathbf{a})\) is \(\chi ( \langle \mathbf{v}, \mathbf{a} \rangle )\). Noting that \(\mathrm{span}(J \mathbf{f}^{(i)}) = {\textit{JV}} = (V^{\perp })^C\), we have our desired isomorphism.\(\blacksquare \)

The stabilizer formalism allows all and only the Clifford superoperators as reversible transformations. The sharp measurements that are included in the stabilizer formalism are the ones associated with PVMs corresponding to the joint eigenspaces of a set of commuting Weyl operators, which, by Proposition 1, are precisely those corresponding to the joint eigenspaces of a set of commuting quadrature observables. It follows that the stabilizer formalism coincides precisely with the quadrature subtheory.

Gross has argued that the discrete analogue of the Gaussian quantum subtheory for continuous variable systems is the stabilizer formalism [6]. Our results show that the connection between the discrete and continuous variable cases is a bit more subtle than this. In the continuous variable case, there is a distinction between the Gaussian subtheory and the quadrature subtheory, with the latter being contained within the former. In the discrete case, there is no distinction, so the stabilizer formalism can be usefully viewed as either the discrete analogue of the Gaussian subtheory or as the discrete analogue of the quadrature subtheory. While Gross’s work showed that the stabilizer formalism for discrete systems could be defined similarly to how one defines Gaussian quantum mechanics, our work has shown that it can also be defined in the same way that one defines quadrature quantum mechanics.

To our knowledge, quadrature quantum mechanics has not previously received much attention. However, given that it is a natural continuous variable analogue of the stabilizer formalism for discrete systems, it may provide an interesting paradigm for exploring quantum information processing with continuous variable systems.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Spekkens, R.W. (2016). Quasi-Quantization: Classical Statistical Theories with an Epistemic Restriction. In: Chiribella, G., Spekkens, R. (eds) Quantum Theory: Informational Foundations and Foils. Fundamental Theories of Physics, vol 181. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7303-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7303-4_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-7302-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-7303-4

  • eBook Packages: Physics and AstronomyPhysics and Astronomy (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics