Skip to main content

Science and Anti-Science: Objectivity and Its Real Enemies

  • Chapter
Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 256))

Abstract

As political activist Ti-Grace Atkinson wrote in 1970: “whenever the enemy keeps lobbing bombs into some area you consider unrelated to your defense, it’s always worth investigating.”1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Amazon Odyssey (New York, NY: Links Books, 1974), p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Gerald Holton,Science and Anti-Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Holton, pp. 152–154; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Holton, p. 181; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Lewis Wolpert,The Unnatural Nature of Science: Why science does not make (common) sense (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992), p. 101; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Wolpert, p. 103; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Wolpert, p. 115; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Wolpert, p. 117; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  9. M. F. Perutz, “The Pioneer Defended”; Review of Gerald L. Geison’s The Private Science of Louis Pasteur’ (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press),New York Review of Books, XLII (20) (December 21, 1995), p. 54; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Perutz, p. 54; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Paul Gross and Norman Levitt,Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins UP, 1994), p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Gross and Levitt, p. 2; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gross and Levitt, pp. 45–46. That is, strong cultural constructivists “view science as a wholly social product, a mere set of conventions generated by social practice” (1994, p. 11, their emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Gross and Levitt, p. 45; my emphasis. Or, it “affords no special leverage among competing versions of the story of the world” (1994, p. 38; my emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Gross and Levitt, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gross and Levitt, p. 4. Cf. p. 15, on the potential for these authors having a “great and pernicious social effect.”

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gross and Levitt, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See David Hull’s important analysis and documentation of a variety of dynamics in scientific inquiry, in David L. Hull,Science as a Process (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  19. In describing the value of social analyses of science to scientific success, Sandra Harding writes: “we can hold that certain social conditions make it possible for humans to produce more reliable explana tions of patterns in nature just as other social conditions make it more difficult to do so,” ‘Why “Physics” is a Bad Model for Physics,’ in The End of Science? Attack and Defense (25th Nobel Conference, 1989) (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1992), p. 7. Cf. Gross and Levitt’s claim: “scientists welcome the sort of ‘social’ explanation that examines minutely and honestly the intellectual, attitudinal, and … the moral preconditions of culture that encourage and sustain the practice of science” (1994, p. 128).

    Google Scholar 

  20. E.g., Holton, 1993, pp. 114–123

    Google Scholar 

  21. 155–156

    Google Scholar 

  22. 181–184

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gross and Levitt, 1994, p. 110

    Google Scholar 

  24. Wolpert, 1992, Ch. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See their section heading, “The Face of the Enemy” (1994, p. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  26. “The central appeal of [science studies] is the pretext is provides to disparage the natural sciences — to dismiss their astounding achievements as so much legerdemain on the part of a ruling elite” (Gross and Levitt, 1994, p. 240; my emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Helga Nowotny and Hilary Rose, ed. (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  28. 1994, pp. 245–257.

    Google Scholar 

  29. “Modern science is seen, by virtually all of its critics, to be both a powerful instrument of the reigning order and an ideological guarantor of its legitimacy” (Gross and Levitt, 1994, p. 12; my emphasis). Do they think the sciences play important, legitimating, social roles, or not?

    Google Scholar 

  30. Quoted in Wolpert, 1992, p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Wolpert, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Gross and Levitt, p. 68; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Wolpert, pp. 113–114.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Wolpert, p. 110; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Harding, 1992, p. 19; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Again, these authors claim they’re not against pursuing the questions asked in history, philosophy, anthropology, or sociology of science; they are only against how these studies are actually done (Gross and Levitt, 1994, p. 69; but see nn. 21 and 23). Their proposals for a proper or more appropriate standard of practice for these studies will be discussed in later sections; at this point, however, the burden of proof is on them to reject the present standards in science studies.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Gross and Levitt, p. 58; their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Gross and Levitt, p. 58; their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Harding, 1992, p. 14. Harding also emphasizes the unsuitability of the training of natural scientists for the task at hand: “Natural scientists are trained in context stripping, while the science of science, like other social sciences, requires training in context seeking” (1992, p. 16).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Shapin and Schaffer, p. 283, quoted in Gross and Levitt, p. 63; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Gross and Levitt, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Gross and Levitt, p. 63; surely Gross and Levitt would not want to deny this.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Gross and Levitt, p. 64; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Shapin and Schaffer, p. 344, quoted in Gross and Levitt, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Gross and Levitt, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Gross and Levitt, p. 67; their emphasis. One hotly debated question at the time concerned the proper role of mathematics, scientifically; the issue was especially pressing, given the prominent place that Descartes had given mathematics in the definition of knowledge itself, contrasted with the deficiencies of his physics. Gross and Levitt ignore this.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Gross and Levitt, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Gross and Levitt, p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Gross and Levitt, p. 65; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Gross and Levitt, p. 234.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Gross and Levitt, p. 49.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Gross and Levitt, p. 49; my emphasis. Given this view of appropriate explanation and evidence, we must wonder about the ingenuousness of Gross and Levitt’s disclaimer that “working scientists are not entitled to special immunity from the scrutiny of social science” (1994, p. 42).

    Google Scholar 

  54. Gross and Levitt, p. 49; their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Wolpert, p. 116

    Google Scholar 

  56. my emphasis. Andrew Pickering,Constructing Quarks: a sociological history of particle physics (Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Wolpert, p. 116; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  58. “We are accusing a powerful faction in modern academic life of intellectual dereliction. This accusa tion has nothing to do with political correctness or ‘subversion’; it has to do, rather, with the craft of scholarship” (Gross and Levitt, p. 239).

    Google Scholar 

  59. See Gross and Levitt’s appeal to scientists’ right to judge, as experts, all work concerning “scientific methodology, history of science, or the very legitimacy of science” (1994, p. 255).

    Google Scholar 

  60. The majority of adult Americans receive their information about the world from TV news, with radio news running second. Among the science scandals aired on national network news within the past 24 months, I would mention: the manufacture of data for the Pittsburgh Breast Cancer study; the reinstatements of eggs into the recommended anti-cholesterol diet; the well-publicized omission of women from nearly all of the most extensive and expensive heart disease studies, which led to a special initiative by Congress; and earlier, the Dalkon Shield devastation; the fanciful claim by President Ronald Reagan that there is no evidence that radiation causes cancer (see Philip Fradkin,Fallout (Tuscon, AZ: University of Arizona Press, 1989)); or the revelations of the horror of radiation experiments done on unsuspecting civilians from the 1940s through the 1970s. The public perceptions of some of the scientists involved in these events is far from the genius with special insight into nature, and closer to Drs Frankenstein or Mengele.

    Google Scholar 

  61. The fact that ‘executive deniability’ has been an essential part of CIA operations policy since its inception is well-documented; see John Ranelagh’s sympathetic history,The Agency: The Rise and Decline of the CIA, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Perutz, 1995, p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  63. John F. W. Herschel,A Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy (London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown, and Green, 1831). I must note that this distinction has come under sustained criticism within philosophy of science, especially by feminists. My focus here, however, is on the most conservative views of science held by working scientists. The point is that even under these views, objections to the feminist source of specific scientific contributions violates the canons of scientific conduct.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  64. Friedrich A. Kekule, ‘Origin of the Benzene and Structural Theory,’ Chemistry, 38 (1965): 9.

    Google Scholar 

  65. See sections 4.2 and 5.2 for elaboration. For the most recent work on why sexist science is not properly characterized as ‘bad’ science, see Synthese, 104 (September 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Anne Fausto-Sterling,Myths of Gender: Biological Theories about Women and Men, (New York: Basic Books, 1985), p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Fausto-Sterling, pp. 8, 60.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ruth Bleier, ‘Sex Differences Research: Science or Belief?’ Ruth Bleier, ed.,Feminist Approaches to Science, (New York, NY: Pergamon, 1986), p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Also, Ruth Bleier,Science and Gender: A Critique of Biology and Its Theories on Women (New York: Pergamon Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  70. See esp. Helen Longino, ‘The Essential Tensions — Phase Two: Feminist, Philosophical, and Social Studies of Science,’ A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, ed. Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1993), 257–272

    Google Scholar 

  71. Longino,Science as Social Knowledge (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990)

    Google Scholar 

  72. John Dupre,The Disorder of Things (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)

    Google Scholar 

  73. Sandra Harding,Whose Science? Whose Knowledge? (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991)

    Google Scholar 

  74. Harding, ‘Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: What is Strong Objectivity?,’ Feminist pistemologies, ed. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter (New York, NY: Routledge, 1993), 49–82

    Google Scholar 

  75. Harding, ‘“Strong Objectivity”: A Response to the New Objectivity Question,’ Synthese, 104.3 (1995), 331–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  76. Longino J, ‘Gender, Politics, and the Theoretical Virtues,’ Synthese, 104.3 (1995), 383–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  77. Lynn Hankinson Nelson,Who Knows: From Quine to a Feminist Empiricism (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1990)

    Google Scholar 

  78. Lynn Hankinson Nelson, ‘Epistemological Communities,’ Feminist Epistemologies, ed. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter (New York, NY: Routledge, 1993), 121–159

    Google Scholar 

  79. Nancy Tuana, ‘The Values of Science: Empiricism from a Feminist Perspective,’ Synthese, 104.3 (1995): 441–461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  80. Tuana, ed.,Feminism and Science (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1989)

    Google Scholar 

  81. Alison Wylie, ‘Methodological Essentialism: Comments on philosophy, sex and feminism,’ Atlantis, 13.2 (1988), 11–14

    Google Scholar 

  82. Cf. Paul Feyerabend,Against Method (London, UK: New Left Bookstore, 1975)

    Google Scholar 

  83. John Stuart Mill,On Liberty.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Longino, 1993, p. 266.

    Google Scholar 

  85. 1993, p. 266; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Treated at length in E. Lloyd, ‘Objectivity and the Double Standard for Feminist Epistemologies,’ Synthese, 104 (September 1995), 351–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. 1993, p. 265. See also Longino,Science as Social Knowledge, 1990, esp. Chapters 4 and 9.

    Google Scholar 

  88. 1995, p. 384. Cf. Wolpert, on science’s “rigorous set of unstated norms for acceptable behaviour”: “Included in these norms are the ideas that science is public knowledge, freely available to all; that there are no privileged sources of scientific knowledge — ideas in science must be judged on their intrinsic merits; and that scientists should take nothing on trust, in the sense that scientific knowledge should be constantly scrutinized” (1992, p. 88). Like Longino, Wolpert emphasizes the community-level process over the individual traits of researchers: “leaving aside the question of whether scientists are more objective, rational, logical and so forth, scientists have developed a procedure in which there are free discussion, accepted standards of behaviour and a means of ensuring that truth will, in the long run, win. Truth will win in the sense that open discussion and observing nature constitute the best way of making progress” (1992, pp. 122–123; my emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  89. Gross and Levitt assert: “there are as yet no examples…of scientific knowledge informed, reformed, enhanced by feminism” (1994, p. 112). Their strategies for dealing with the numerous feminist contributions to the sciences they subsequently cite are instructive: briefly put, if feminist work is persuasive and is accepted as correct, it’s simply good science; if not, it’s bad science tainted by ideology. In other words, the feminist contributions to science are either not feminist or not contributions.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Fausto-Sterling, p. 213; her emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Fausto-Sterling, p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  92. See Donna Haraway,Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science, (New York, NY: Routledge, 1989), for a comprehensive bibliography and analysis. I have borrowed from Haraway’s discussion of J. Altmann in presenting this case.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Jeanne Altmann, ‘Observational Study of Behavior: Sampling Methods,’ Behaviour, 49, 227–267.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Haraway, p. 307.

    Google Scholar 

  95. ‘Empathy, Polyandry, and the Myth of the Coy Female,’ Feminist Approaches to Science, Ruth Bleier, ed. (New York, NY: Pergamon), 135–136

    Google Scholar 

  96. cf: Linda Fedigan,Primate Paradigms (Montreal, Can: Eden, 1982)

    Google Scholar 

  97. Shirely Strum,Almost Human: A Journey into the World of Baboons (New York, NY: Random House, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  98. Margarita Levin, ‘Caring New Science: Feminism and Science,’ American Scholar, 57 (Winter 1988), 100; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Levin, p. 100; her emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Levin, p. 104; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Clifford Geertz, ‘A Lab of One’s Own,’ NY Review of Books, 37 (8 November 1990), 19; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Geertz, p. 23; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Gross and Levitt, p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Gross and Levitt, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Gross and Levitt, p. 162; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Gross and Levitt, p. 123; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Gross and Levitt, pp. 145–146.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Gross and Levitt, p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Gross and Levitt, p. 147; their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Gross and Levitt, p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Other instances can be found in: Levin, 1988

    Google Scholar 

  112. Michael Ruse,Is Science Sexist? And Other Problems in the Biomedical Sciences, (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981); and

    Google Scholar 

  113. John R. Searle, ‘Rationality and Realism: What is at Stake?,’ Daedalus, 122.4 (1993), 55–84.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Longino, 1990, pp. 119

    Google Scholar 

  115. Longino, 1990, 127

    Google Scholar 

  116. Longino, 1990, 131

    Google Scholar 

  117. Longino, 1990, 134

    Google Scholar 

  118. Helen Longino and Ruth Doell, ‘Body, Bias and Behavior: A Comparative Analysis of Reasoning in Two Areas of Biological Science,’ Signs, 9 (1983), 206–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  119. (See block quote, above). Bleier, 1984,Science and Gender, Fausto-Sterling, 1985, 133–141. The work of Harvard biologist and feminist Ruth Hubbard is also very important, especially

    Google Scholar 

  120. Anne Fausto-Sterling,Myths of Gender: Biological Theories about Women and Men, (New York: Basic Books, 1985, 133–141. The work of Harvard biologist and feminist Ruth Hubbard is also very important, especially

    Google Scholar 

  121. Ruth Hubbard, Mary Sue Henifen, and Barbara Fried, eds,Biological Woman, the Convenient Myth: A Collection of Feminist Essays and a Comprehensive Bibliography (Cambridge, MA: Schenkman, 1982)

    Google Scholar 

  122. Ruth Hubbard,The Politics of Women’s Biology (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  123. Gross and Levitt, p. 125. Since Fausto-Sterling acknowledges the existence of biological differences between males and females throughout her book, it remains mysterious how Gross and Levitt could defend this statement, unless they put all the weight for its truth on whatever they mean by “significant”.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Gross and Levitt, p. 11, their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Gross and Levitt, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Gross and Levitt, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Gross and Levitt, p. 122

    Google Scholar 

  128. quoting the Biology and Gender Study Group, ‘The Importance of Feminist Critique for Contemporary Cell Biology,’ Hypatia, 3 (1): 61–76 (Spring 1988).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  129. Reprinted in Nancy Tuana, ed.,Feminism and Science (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  130. Gross and Levitt, p. 274

    Google Scholar 

  131. also Levin, p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Gross and Levitt, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Gross and Levitt, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Gross and Levitt, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Gross and Levitt, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Gross and Levitt, p. 56; their emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Levin, p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Gross and Levitt, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  139. My analysis of the inconsistencies and grave evidential problems in recent evolutionary theorizing about women’s orgasm has been met repeatedly with the response that it is ‘simply good science’; this reaction fails to engage the problem I address, namely,why it took decades for these able scientists to become aware that the evidence they cited undermined their own explanations. Elisabeth A. Lloyd, ‘Pre-theoretical Assumptions in Evolutionary Explanations of Female Sexuality,’ Philosophical Studies, 69(1993), 139–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  140. Paul Gross and Norman Levitt,Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins UP, 1994), p. 131. They also admit that women’s scientific “contributions have often in the past been undervalued” (1994, p. 123). How do they account for the fact that this happened in the first place? How do they account for the fact that it has, according to them, changed?

    Google Scholar 

  141. Gross and Levitt, pp. 32

    Google Scholar 

  142. Gross and Levitt, pp. 108

    Google Scholar 

  143. Holton, pp. 152, The targets are Evelyn Fox Keller and Sandra Harding, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Holton, pp. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  145. 1990, p. 193, my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Harding, 1992, p. 1. She also states, “it’s a very conservative notion of objectivity that I’m … proposing here … there are important aspects of the traditional notion of [scientific] objectivity which need not be challenged in order to accomplish the goals that I have in mind” (p. 20).

    Google Scholar 

  147. Gross and Levitt, p. 109; my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Gross and Levitt, p. 108, my emphasis.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Gross and Levitt, pp. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Gross and Levitt, pp. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Gross and Levitt, pp. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Gross and Levitt, pp. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Gross and Levitt, pp. 235.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Gross and Levitt, pp. 236.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Gross and Levitt, pp. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  156. While Holton clearly is referring to Keller’s work, he perveresely refuses to name her or to cite any of her books or articles (1993, p. 154).

    Google Scholar 

  157. Gross and Levitt’s inclusion of Haraway and Keller among the four chief representatives for feminist views of science belies their earlier aside that “a handful of figures with scientific credentials, as well as the occasional refugee from an unsatisfactory scientific career, can be found on the movement’s fringes” (p. 14; p. 6, my emphasis).

    Google Scholar 

  158. “Sciences will not, in any serious way, be influenced, deflected, restricted, or even inconvenienced by these critics and those they influence” (1994, p. 236; see pp. 3, 11, 112, 253–256).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lloyd, E.A. (1996). Science and Anti-Science: Objectivity and Its Real Enemies. In: Nelson, L.H., Nelson, J. (eds) Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science. Synthese Library, vol 256. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1742-2_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1742-2_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-4611-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-1742-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics