Skip to main content

Conflicting Values in Design for Values

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Ethics, Values, and Technological Design

Abstract

Designers are regularly confronted with conflicting values in design: different values select different design options as best. This contribution deals with how one can deal with such value conflicts in design for values. A characterization of value conflict in design is given, and the notion is compared with the notion of moral dilemmas. It is further argued that value conflicts in design entail a kind of multi-criteria decision problems to which Arrow’s impossibility theorem applies. This theorem says that there is no procedure to aggregate scores on individual criteria (values) into an overall score unless one is willing to violate one of more minimally reasonable conditions for any such an aggregation procedure. Six methods to deal with value conflicts (cost-benefit analysis, direct trade-offs, maximin, satisficing, judgment, and innovation) are discussed. Three of these avoid Arrow’s theorem by assuming a form of value commensurability, although they may be too informationally demanding and have other disadvantages as well. The other three are non-optimizing methods that do not result in one best solution and therefore do not entirely solve the value conflict, although they are a way forward in some respects. In conclusion, an approach that combines the several methods is proposed as a way to deal with cases of conflicting moral values in design and which avoids many of the disadvantages of the single methods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 499.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 699.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is exactly why moral dilemmas have been characterized as hard choices (Levi 1986) and, also, why some philosophers deny the possibility of moral dilemmas because according to them there is always an overall point of view in which only one ought applies.

  2. 2.

    What makes the assumption problematic is not just the assumption that “more value is better than less” but also the assumption that there is an obligation (an “ought”) rather than just a recommendation to choose the highest value. Even if “more value is better than less,” we might not be obliged to choose the object with higher value.

  3. 3.

    A more detailed discussion can be found in van de Poel (1998).

  4. 4.

    A more detailed discussion can be found in van de Poel (2001). The data for GWP given in Table 3 are based on a more recent IPCC report (Solomon et al. 2007, Table 2.14) and therefore deviate from the data in van de Poel (2001). The GWP for a 100-year time horizon is given in the table.

  5. 5.

    It should be noted that coolants in the same flammability class are not necessarily equally flammable; neither are coolants in the same toxicity class necessarily equally toxic. Membership of certain flammability or toxicity class is determined by certain threshold values, and therefore does not reflect degrees of flammability or toxicity that follow the patterns shown in Fig. 1.

  6. 6.

    To this social choice problem, the Arrow’s theorem also applies (Kroes et al. 2009).

  7. 7.

    According to some ethical theories (e.g., Kantianism), all people would come to the same conclusion if they take an ethical point of view. In that case, the earlier assumption of there being just one decision-maker would be justified.

  8. 8.

    The requirements given are somewhat weaker than those originally formulated by Arrow. See, e.g., Sen (1970). See also Franssen (2005).

  9. 9.

    A difference is that the values have different degrees of importance, whereas in the original Arrow choice situation, each individual has equal weight. We can, however, repair this by replacing each value by x values where x is the (relative) degree of importance of that value (cf. Franssen 2005).

  10. 10.

    If we assume only nonnegative utilities, ratio scale measurement is enough. However, if we also allow negative utilities, an additional commensurability assumption is needed for a reasonable aggregation procedure to be available (Tsui and Weymark 1997).

  11. 11.

    Cost-benefit analysis does not only suppose ratio measurability but also value commensurability because the various values are measured on a common scale (i.e., money). Theoretically, it would be possible to construct a method that only supposes ratio measurability (but see also note 10). Such a method could, for example, proceed by multiplying the score on one value dimension (measured on a ratio scale) with the score on another value dimension (measured on another ratio scale) and then selecting the alternative with the highest score so attainted. It seems, however, doubtful whether that leads to a meaningful decision procedure for design, and as far as I know, no such decision methods have been proposed in the design literature. The multiplication of, for example, safety and sustainability, both measured on a (positive) ratio scale, for example, does not seem meaningful as a decision criterion. Note that in physics, such multiplications are sometimes meaningful, e.g., mass times velocity is a measure of momentum.

  12. 12.

    The three non-optimizing methods discussed are the same as in Van de Poel (2009). There, I also discuss a fourth (diversity) that is not discussed here as it cannot be employed in a single design process (which I take to be the focus of this chapter). The discussion follows Van de Poel (2009) but has been updated and somewhat revised in several respects.

  13. 13.

    The resulting costs can then be interpreted as the amount of money that one should be willing to pay for the increase in safety that is obtained by realizing the Delta plan.

  14. 14.

    Note that GWP should be as low as possible, while LFL should be as high as possible.

  15. 15.

    For a more detailed discussion, see the chapter “Design for Values and the Definition, Specification, and Operationalization of Values.”

  16. 16.

    This paragraph draws from Van de Poel (2009).

  17. 17.

    This and the next paragraph draw from Van de Poel (2013).

  18. 18.

    Based on van de Poel (2001). See also the chapter “Design for Values and the Definition, Specification, and Operationalization of Values.”

References

  • Arrow KJ (1950) A difficulty in the concept of social welfare. J Polit Econ 58:328–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ, Raynaud H (1986) Social choice and multicriterion decision-making. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • ASHRAE (2013) Designation and safety classification of refrigerants, ANSI/ASHRAE standard, 34-2013. ASHRAE, Atlanta

    Google Scholar 

  • Ball LJ, Evans JSBT, Dennis I (1994) Cognitive processes in engineering design: a longitudinal study. Ergonomics 37(11):1753–1786

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron J, Spranca M (1997) Protected values. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 70(1):1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyce RR, Brown TC, McClelland GH, Peterson GL, Schulze WD (1992) An experimental examination of intrinsic values as a source of the WTA-WTP disparity. Am Econ Rev 82(5):1366–1373. doi:10.2307/2117484

    Google Scholar 

  • Franssen M (2005) Arrow’s theorem, multi-criteria decision problems and multi-attribute preferences in engineering design. Res Eng Des 16:42–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (1998) Should we avoid moral dilemmas? J Value Inq 32(3):407–416. doi:10.1023/a:1004329011239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (2007) Philosophical problems in cost–benefit analysis. Econ Philos 23:163–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz JK, McConnell KE (2002) A review of WTA/WTP studies. J Environ Econ Manag 44(3):426–447. doi:10.1006/jeem.2001.1215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hylland A (1980) Aggregation procedure for cardinal preferences: a comment. Econometrica 48(2):539–542. doi:10.2307/1911117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs JF, Van de Poel I, Osseweijer P (2014) Clarifying the debate on selection methods for engineering: Arrow’s impossibility theorem, design performances, and information basis. Res Eng Des 25(1):3–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keeney RL (2002) Common mistakes in making value trade-offs. Oper Res 50(6):935–945. doi:10.2307/3088614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroes P, Franssen M, Bucciarelli L (2009) Rationality in design. In: Meijers A (ed) Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences, vol 9, Handbook of the philosophy of science. Elsevier, Oxford, pp 565–600

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levi I (1986) Hard choices. Decision making under unresolved conflict. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell A, Sonnenschein H (1972) General possibility theorems for group decisions. Rev Econ Stud 39(2):185–192. doi:10.2307/2296870

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May KO (1954) Intransitivity, utility, and the aggregation of preference patterns. Econometrica 22(1):1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLinden MO, Didion DA (1987) Quest for alternatives. ASHRAE J 29(11):32–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1986) Value incommensurability: some preliminaries. Proc Aristot Soc 86:117–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson HS (1997) Practical reasoning about final ends. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts KWS (1980) Interpersonal comparability and social choice theory. Rev Econ Stud 47(2):421–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Oliver & Boyd, Edinburg/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1955) A behavioral model of rational choice. Q J Econ 69:99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1956) Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychol Rev 63:129–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon S, Qin D, Manning M, Chen Z, Marquis M, Averyt KB, Tignor M, Miller HL (eds) (2007) Climate change 2007: the physical science basis: contribution of Working Group I to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock PE (2003) Thinking the unthinkable: sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends Cogn Sci 7(7):320–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen J (1959) Sociaal-economische aspecten van het Deltaplan. In: Deltacomissie (ed) Rapport Deltacommissie, Bijdrage VI, Onderzoekingen van belang voor het ontwerpen van dijken en dammen. Staatsdrukkerij- en Uitgeverijbedrijf, Den Haag, pp 61–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsui K-Y, Weymark JA (1997) Social welfare orderings for ratio-scale measurable utilities. Econ Theory 10(2):241–256. doi:10.1007/s001990050156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel I (1998) Changing technologies. A comparative study of eight processes of transformation Of technological regimes. University of Twente, Enschede

    Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel I (2001) Investigating ethical issues in engineering design. Sci Eng Ethics 7(3):429–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Poel I (2009) Values in engineering design. In: Meijers A (ed) Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences, vol 9, Handbook of the philosophy of science. Elsevier, Oxford, pp 973–1006

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Poel I (2013a) Translating values into design requirements. In: Mitchfelder D, McCarty N, Goldberg DE (eds) Philosophy and engineering: reflections on practice, principles and process. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 253–266

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van de Poel I (forthcoming) Dealing with moral dilemmas through design. In: Van den Hoven J, Miller S, Pogge T (eds) The design turn in applied ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Poel I, Royakkers L (2011) Ethics, technology and engineering. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Hoven J, Lokhorst G-J, Van de Poel I (2012) Engineering and the problem of moral overload. Sci Eng Ethics 18(1):143–155. doi:10.1007/s11948-011-9277-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams B (1973) Problems of the self. Philosophical papers 1956–1972. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ibo van de Poel .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

van de Poel, I. (2015). Conflicting Values in Design for Values. In: van den Hoven, J., Vermaas, P., van de Poel, I. (eds) Handbook of Ethics, Values, and Technological Design. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6970-0_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6970-0_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-6969-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-6970-0

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics