Skip to main content

Shifting Attention from Theory to Practice in Philosophy of Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Directions in the Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective ((PSEP,volume 5))

Abstract

Traditional approaches in philosophy of biology focus attention on biological concepts, explanations, and theories, on evidential support and inter-theoretical relations. Newer approaches shift attention from concepts to conceptual practices, from theories to practices of theorizing, and from theoretical reduction to reductive retooling. In this article, I describe the shift from theory-focused to practice-centered philosophy of science and explain how it is leading philosophers to abandon fundamentalist assumptions associated with traditional approaches in philosophy of science and to embrace scientific pluralism. This article comes in three parts, each illustrating the shift from theory-focused to practice-centered epistemology. The first illustration shows how shifting philosophical attention to conceptual practice reveals how molecular biologists succeed in identifying coherent causal strands within systems of bewildering complexity. The second illustration suggests that analyzing how a multiplicity of alternative models function in practice provides an illuminating approach for understanding the nature of theoretical knowledge in evolutionary biology. The third illustration demonstrates how framing reductionism in terms of the reductive retooling of practice offers an informative perspective for understanding why putting DNA at the center of biological research has been incredibly productive throughout much of biology. Each illustration begins by describing how traditional theory-focused philosophical approaches are laden with fundamentalist assumptions and then proceeds to show that shifting attention to practice undermines these assumptions and motivates a philosophy of scientific pluralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 219.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The idea that there is parity among genes and other elements takes several subtle forms in philosophical discussions and I will not analyze them here.

  2. 2.

    I say “largely” because often in Eukaryotes, differences in other molecules, including splicing agents, also determine actual differences in polypeptides.

  3. 3.

    See Waters (2007) for a detailed analysis.

  4. 4.

    A few biologists have written on this issue and drawn conclusions similar to those of philosophers (e.g. see Portin 1993; Fogle 2000). Stotz et al. (2004) have put the question “what is a gene?” to biologists through surveys, keeping track of how biologists in different groups (for example different fields, of different ages, etc.) answer this question. They have explored how biologists answer the question in the context of different kinds of examples. As I read the empirical results, their study indicates that biologists are all over the place. But I have reservations about drawing philosophical conclusions from such studies. See Waters (2004a, b) for a critique of using surveys to analyze scientific concepts.

  5. 5.

    I am using the term partition in the set theoretical sense of a division into elements that do not overlap.

  6. 6.

    To be more precise, I believe we should be asking two questions: (1) “what concepts of the gene are at work in successful biological practices?” (2) “what concepts of the gene help us understand the success of biological investigations without inflating the knowledge that makes this success possible?”

  7. 7.

    For example, a symposium at the most recent Philosophy of Science Association meeting examined experimental modeling in evolutionary biology (Waters et al. 2012).

  8. 8.

    Consider, for example, the two most recent books in philosophy of biology to win the Lakatos Award, Okasha (2006) and Godfrey-Smith (2009). Both books adopt what I call a fundamentalist perspective.

  9. 9.

    Okasha claims that “unlike most formal descriptions of the evolutionary process, it [Price’s equation] rests on no contingent biological assumptions, so always holds true” (p. 19). He also claims that the Price formalism “subsumes all more specific models as special cases” (p. 3). But he contradicts this latter claim later in his book, and there is good reason to think that the kind of toolbox theorizing I am advocating with respect to model types MLS1 and MLS2 applies at the level of the Price equation and its formal rivals such as contextual analysis (see Waters 2010).

  10. 10.

    I thank Marc Ereshefsky for reminding me that theory-focused philosophers of biology have done a good job critiquing the fundamentalist conception of natural kinds and that they have developed promising alternatives for understanding kinds of entities.

  11. 11.

    Maxwell (manuscript), Cartwright et al. (1995), Cartwright (1999), Suárez and Cartwright (2008) and Wimsatt (2007) offer ideas about theorizing similar to the one I am advancing here and also use the “toolbox” term and metaphor.

  12. 12.

    Some recent accounts of reduction frame reduction in different ways, but still with the emphasis on theoretical and/or explanatory relations. For example, Hüttemann and Love (2011) couch it in terms of explanations in which an outcome described at a higher level (explandum) is explained by earlier states described at lower level(s). This article illustrates that focusing on the theories and explanations does not necessarily presuppose fundamentalism, and that paying attention to theoretical and explanatory practices undermines the fundamentalist ideals.

  13. 13.

    Kitcher (1984) offers an alternative, theory-focused, non-reductive account of how molecular genetics contributes to the science of genetics. But Hull (1974) implied that there was something reductive happening in genetics, but that what was happening did not fit Nagel’s model.

  14. 14.

    Many of the points in this section are developed in more detail in Waters (2008a).

  15. 15.

    Not all reductionists accept the layer-cake image (e.g., Weber 2005), and some antireductionists seem more interested in advancing holism than multileveled holism (e.g., various contributors to Oyama et al. 2001). Nevertheless, many philosophers cling to the idea that biology is organized into separate sciences, each of which is focused on a particular level of organization.

  16. 16.

    This epistemology is generally presupposed even by reductionists and antireductionists who reject the layer-cake image (e.g. Weber 2005; Oyama et al. 2001).

  17. 17.

    Debates in philosophy of science are sometimes framed as disagreements about “the aim” of science. For example, van Fraassen (1980) characterizes his disagreement with scientific realists as centering on the aim of science. I reject the idea that there is something called “science” that has a single aim.

  18. 18.

    See Waters (2004b) for an elaboration of this account.

  19. 19.

    As in the case of classical genetics (see Waters 2004b), investigators carry out their work on model organisms that have been adapted for laboratory practice.

  20. 20.

    Given the possibility of redundant pathways to the development of the neurons, the results did not prove that ß-spectrin has no role in the growth if these neuronal extensions, but the results did show that the role was not essential.

References

  • Bird, A., and E. Tobin. 2012. Natural kinds. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta (Winter 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/natural-kinds/.

  • Boyd, R. 1999. Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In Species: New interdisciplinary essays, ed. R. Wilson, 141–186. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R.M. 1986. On conceptual change in biology: The case of the gene. In Evolution at a crossroads, ed. D.J. Depew and B.H. Weber, 21–42. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1999. The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., T. Shomar, and M. Suárez. 1995. The tool box of science. In Theories and models in scientific processes, ed. W. Herfel, W. Krajewski, I. Niiniluoto, and R. Wojcicki, 137–149. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damuth, J., and I.L. Heisler. 1988. Alternative formulations of multi-level selection. Biology and Philosophy 3: 407–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., and N. Maul. 1977. Unifying science without reduction. Philosophy of Science 8: 43–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieckmann, U., and M. Doebeli. 2005. Pluralism in evolutionary theory. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 18(5): 1209–1213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. 1981. Natural kinds and biological taxa. The Philosophical Review 90: 66–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. 1998. Species pluralism and anti-realism. Philosophy of Science 65: 103–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogle, T. 2000. The dissolution of protein coding genes in molecular biology. In The concept of the gene in development and evolution. Historical and epistemological perspectives, ed. P. Beurton, R. Falk, and H.-J. Rheinberger, 3–25. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 2001. Genetic information: A metaphor in search of a theory. Philosophy of Science 68(3): 394–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and E.M. Neumann-Held. 1999. The many faces of the gene. BioScience 49(8): 656–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1983. Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hammarlund, M., E.M. Jorgensen, and M.J. Bastiani. 2007. Axons break in animals lacking ß-spectrin. Journal of Cell Biology 176(3): 269–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herron, M.D., and R.E. Michod. 2007. Evolution of complexity in the volvocine algae: Transitions in individuality through Darwin’s eye. Evolution 62(2): 436–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C.A. 1981. Towards a general theory of reduction. Part I: Historical and scientific setting, Part II: Identity in reduction, Part III: Cross-categorical reduction. Dialogue 20: 38–59, 201–236, 496–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D.L. 1974. The philosophy of biological science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A., and A.C. Love. 2011. Aspects of reductive explanation in biological science: Intrinsicality, fundamentality, and temporality. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science 62: 519–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E.F. 2000. Century of the gene. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, D.L. 2005. A twelve-step program for evolving multicellularity and a division of labor. BioEssays 27: 299–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P.S. 1984. 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. Philosophical Review 43: 335–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P.S. 1992. Gene: Current usages. In Keywords in evolutionary biology, ed. E. Keller and L. Lloyd, 128–131. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohler, R.E. 1994. Lords of the fly: Drosophila genetics and the experimental life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. manuscript. Toolbox theorizing. Maxwell Archive, Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D.G., and N.L. Gilinsky. 1987. Models of group selection. Philosophy of Science 54(4): 515–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. 1961. The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. 2006. Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., P.E. Griffiths, and R.D. Gray. 2001. Introduction: What is developmental systems theory? In Cycles of contingency, ed. S. Oyama, P.E. Griffiths, and R.D. Gray, 1–12. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Portin, P. 1993. The concept of the gene: Short history and present status. The Quarterly Review of Biology 68: 173–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, W.C., R.F. Denison, M. Borrello, and M. Travisano. 2012. Experimental evolution of multicellularity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 109(5): 1595–1600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. 1985. The structure of biological science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. 1996. Biological information: A skeptical look at some central dogmas of molecular biology. In The philosophy and history of molecular biology: New perspectives, ed. S. Sarkar, 187–231. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. 1969. The Watson-Crick model and reductionism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20: 235–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1984. The nature of selection: Evolutionary theory in focus. Cambridge, MA: Bradford/The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 1996. Explanatory pluralism in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy 11(2): 193–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K., P.E. Griffiths, and R.D. Knight. 2004. How scientists conceptualise genes: An empirical study. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35(4): 647–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M., and N. Cartwright. 2008. Theories: Tools versus models. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39: 62–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 1994a. Tempered realism about the force of selection. Philosophy of Science 58: 553–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 1994b. Genes made molecular. Philosophy of Science 61: 163–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2000. Molecules made biological. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 54(214): 539–564.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2004a. What concept analysis should be. History and Philosophy of the Life Science 26: 29–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2004b. What was classical genetics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35: 783–809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2005. Why genic and multilevel selection theories are here to stay. Philosophy of Science 72(2): 311–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2007. Causes that make a difference. The Journal of Philosophy CIV(11): 551–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2008a. Beyond theoretical reduction and layer-cake antireduction: How DNA retooled genetics and transformed biological practice. In Oxford handbook to the philosophy of biology, ed. M. Ruse, 238–262. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K. 2008b. Molecular genetics. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta (Fall 2013 Edition), forthcoming http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/molecular-genetics/.

  • Waters, C.K. 2010. Okasha’s unintended argument for toolbox theorizing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82(1): 232–240 [pre-print of unabridged version on PhilSci-Archive.pitt.edu].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, C.K., K. Hillesland, M. Weber, and M. Travisano. 2012. Can experimental modeling play the role of theorizing in evolutionary biology? Philosophy of science association 2012 biennial meeting, San Diego.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. 2005. Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 1976. Reductive explanation: A functional account. In PSA 1974 proceedings of the 1974 biennial meeting Philosophy of Science Association, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 32, ed. R.S. Cohen, C.A. Hooker, A.C. Michalos, and J.W. Van Evra, 671–710. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 1980. Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In Scientific discovery: Case studies, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 60, ed. T. Nickles, 213–259. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 1987. False models as means to truer theories. In Neutral models in biology, ed. M. Nitecki and A. Hoffman, 23–55. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 2007. Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to C. Kenneth Waters .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Waters, C.K. (2014). Shifting Attention from Theory to Practice in Philosophy of Biology. In: Galavotti, M., Dieks, D., Gonzalez, W., Hartmann, S., Uebel, T., Weber, M. (eds) New Directions in the Philosophy of Science. The Philosophy of Science in a European Perspective, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04382-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics