Skip to main content

Implementation of Two-Layered Dynamic Pragmatics

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
  • 700 Accesses

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Networks and Systems ((LNNS,volume 544))

Abstract

The paper presents a program that models information exchange in natural language via a multiagent system in which – parallel to a changing model of the outside world – relevant segments of information states of Agents communicating with each other can be monitored by Users from step to step. The theoretical background is provided by ℜeALIS, ‘Reciprocal and Lifelong Interpretation System’: a two-layered dynamic pragmasemantic theory. The software executes generalized truth evaluation in a set of possible-world-like objects partially ordered via a label system defined by a recursive technique. The dynamic character is captured as follows: the program essentially models intensional profiles associated with Agents’ Utterances as transition rules of finite-state automata, the states of which are Phases, sums of moments of information states of the Agents thinking about the world outside and each other. It is also a crucial feature of ℜeALIS that it is a two-layered interpretation system: the Agents who can function as Speakers and Hearers take conventionalized Addresser and Addressee roles, defined in ℜeALIS as complex intensional profiles. As for practical applications of programs implementing the ℜeALIS model of human communication, it is of great importance in several areas of life and work to store information so that not only the pieces of information themselves be saved but, for each piece of data, information on such circumstances as who knows it, who knows about whom that the latter person knows or does not know it, who is authorized to reveal it, and who is assumed to be interested in its modification. It is worth learning from human ways of storing and organizing information as much as possible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Oishi [16] offers (p. 338) a (terminological re-) interpretation of Austin’s [14 felicity conditions (pp. 14–15) as follows: “To clarify how an illocutionary act is performed felicitously and brings about an effect, let us specify the terminology. A particular speaker in a given case who makes an utterance… is distinguished from the performer who performs a particular illocutionary act…, whom we call the addresser of the act. The hearer to whom the speaker speaks… is also distinguished from the person to whom the illocutionary act is performed…, whom we call the addressee of the act. The circumstances of the situation in which an utterance is made… Are distinguished from the context of the act… The illocutionary act brings about its conventional effect when (i) the speaker, the hearer, and the circumstances of the speech situation are assumed to be the addresser, the addressee, and the context of the act, respectively…, (ii) the speaker follows the procedure correctly…, (iii) the hearer ratifies the act (or the speaker makes a specific sequel) for the procedure to be completed…, (iv) the speaker has the thought or feeling, or intention of the addresser of the act…, and (v) the speaker or the hearer conducts her/himself subsequently as is specified for the addresser/addressee of the act.”.

  2. 2.

    Lauer’s formal-semantics based Dynamic Pragmatics [19] has the same point of departure as that of ℜeALIS, in contrast to less formal branches of pragmatics (pp. 4–5): “There is surprisingly little work on the conventional link between clauses of different types and their use, at least in the formally-oriented semantics literature. There was some early work on this issue in philosophy …, but soon, it seems, researchers abandoned the issue. In part this was likely due to the fact that the dominant paradigm in speech act theory … made the project of assigning a conventionally-specified use to sentences based on their type seem hopeless: Sentences of any given type can be used to perform acts of almost any given Searlean illocutionary type. Developing a systematic framework for studying the conventionally specified use of sentences of different types is thus a very timely project. Secondly, it is this conventional connection between sentences and their use that connects semantic content, as it is studied in linguistics, with language use, and inferences about utterance choice. As I just pointed out, the classical Gricean account of implicatures [18] starts from the assumption that a speaker utters a (declarative) sentence in order to convey information, and thus… Presupposes an answer to the question of how sentences are conventionally associated with a certain use. And if we want to take a Gricean perspective more generally – if we want to investigate how interlocutors reason about each other’s action choices – we need to know how the contents we study in linguistic semantics relate to the use of sentences. An understanding of clause typing thus is central to developing a formal framework that lets us take a pragmatic perspective in general.” Lauer qualifies his approach (p. 1) as “pragmatics, in a broadly Gricean sense. It is not… About conversational implicatures, at least not in the classical sense of the term. [It concentrates]… on a question that may seem quite un-Gricean, due to its focus on linguistic convention: What kind of linguistic convention makes it so that sentences of different types – such as declaratives, interrogatives and imperatives – are used in different ways, and support different kinds of pragmatic inferences? This question, however, will be addressed from a very Gricean angle. Pragmatic inference is construed as language users’ reasoning about utterance events. Or, more precisely, as language users’ reasoning about how utterance events are chosen. A central aim… is to show that consistently taking such a perspective is fruitful, indeed, necessary if we want to understand language use.”.

References

  1. Szeteli, A., Alberti, G., Kleiber, J., Dóla, M.: The World is Built with our Words to Each Other – Basic and Fine-Tuned Intensional Profiles in Hungarian. XIV. MSZNY, pp. 78–88 (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Nőthig L., Szeteli A.: Nagyfelbontású pragmaszemantikai igazságértékelés egy játékprogramban [High-Resolution Pragmasemantics Truth-Evaluation in a Game Program]. XIV. MSZNY [annual conference of Hungarian computational linguistc] pp. 456–465 (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Alberti G.: ℜeALIS: Interpretálók a világban, világok az interpretálóban (ℜeALIS: Interpreters in the World, Worlds in the Interpreter). Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Farkas, D., Roelofsen, F.: Division of labor in the interpretation of declaratives and interrogatives. J. Semant. 34(2), 237–289 (2017)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Alberti G., Dóla M., Kárpáti E., Kleiber J., Viszket A., Szeteli A.: Lehetséges lehetséges világaink (Our Possible Possible Worlds). Jelentés és Nyelvhasználat (Meaning and Language Use) 8/1, pp. xx–yy (2021)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Szeteli, A., Dóla, M., Alberti, G.: Pragmasemantic analysis of the Hungarian inferential – evidential expression ‘szerint.’ Stud. Polish Linguist. 14, 207–225 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Gyuris, B.: A hangsúlyos csak diskurzuspartikula interpretációja (Interpretation of the Stressed Version of the Hungarian Discourse Particle csak ‘only’). In: Maleczki M., Németh T. E. (szerk.): A mai magyar nyelv leírásának újabb módszerei (New Methods in the Description of Present-Day Hungarian) 7. SZTE, Szeged, pp. 157–179 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Kárpáti, L., Kleiber, J., Alberti, G.: The polysemous system of the Hungarian csak ‘only’, with special emphasis on its metacognitive use. Talk at the Linguistics Beyond and Within Conference. Lublin, 14–15 October (2021)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Benz, A.: Chains and the Common Ground. In: Poesio M., Traum D. (eds.) GötaLog 2000 — Gothenburg Papers in Computational Linguistics 00–5, pp. 181–184 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Farkas, J., Ohnmacht, M.: Aspect and eventuality structure in a representational dynamic semantics. In Alberti, G., Farkas, J., Kleiber, J. (eds.) Vonzásban és változásban, pp. 353–379. Doctoral School of Linguistics at Univ. of Pécs, Hungary (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Dowty, D.R., Wall, R.E., Peters, S.: Introduction to Montague Semantics. Reidel, Dordrecht (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Kamp, H., Genabith, J., Reyle, U.: Discourse representation theory. In: Gabbay, D., Guenthner, F. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 15, pp. 125–394 Springer, Heidelberg (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0485-5_3

  13. Maier, E.: Attitudes and Mental Files in DRT. Rev. Phil. Psych 7, 473–490 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Austin, J.L.: How to Do Things with Words. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1975/1962)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Partee, B.H., ter Meulen, A., Wall, R.P.: Mathematical Methods in Linguistics. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1990)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Oishi, E.: Austin’s speech acts and Mey’s pragmemes. In: Allan, K., Capone, A., Kecskes, I. (eds.) Pragmemes and Theories of Language Use. PPPP, vol. 9, pp. 335–350. Springer, Cham (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43491-9_18

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Searle, J.R.: A classification of illocutionary acts. Lang. Soc. 5(1), 1–23 (1976)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Grice, P.: Logic and conversation. In: Cole, P., Morgan, J.L. (eds.) Syntax and Semantics 3, pp. 41–58. Academic Press, New York (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Lauer, S.: Towards a Dynamic Pragmatics. Dissertation at Stanford University (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Alberti, G.: A világ nyelvei, a nyelv világai (Languages of the world, worlds of the language). In: Böhm, G., Czeferner, D., Fedeles, T. (eds.) Bölcsész Akadémia (Academy of Humanities), vol. 4. Pécs, BTK KTDT, pp. 126–150 (2020)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Aijmer, K., Foolen, A., Simon-Vandenbergen, A.-M.: Pragmatic markers in translation: a methodological proposal. Approach. Discourse Part. 1, 101–114 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Alberti, G., Nőthig, L.: HumInA projektcsoport a ℜeALIS1.1 bázisán (HumInA Groups of Projects on the Basis of ℜeALIS1.1). XI. MSZNY (Annual Conference of Hungarian Computational Linguists), pp. 326–332 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Szécsényi, T., Kovács, V.: Dinamikus szemantikai modell megszorított predikátumokkal (Dynamic Semantics Model with Restricted Predicates). XVIII. MSZNY (Annual Conference of Hungarian Computational Linguists), pp. 561–571 (2022)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

Supported by the ÚNKP-21–2-I New National Excellence Program of the Ministry for Innovation and Technology from the source of the National Research, Development and Innovation Fund.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gábor Alberti .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Szeteli, Á. et al. (2023). Implementation of Two-Layered Dynamic Pragmatics. In: Arai, K. (eds) Intelligent Systems and Applications. IntelliSys 2022. Lecture Notes in Networks and Systems, vol 544. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-16075-2_42

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics