Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contemporary Social Theory

Abstract

The principal issue with which I shall be concerned in this paper is that of connecting a notion of human action with structural explanation in social analysis. The making of such a connection, I shall argue, demands the following: a theory of the human agent, or of the subject; an account of the conditions and consequences of action; and an interpretation of ‘structure’ as somehow embroiled in both those conditions and consequences.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. See, for instance, G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Blackwell, 1963);

    Google Scholar 

  2. Theodore Mischel, Human Action (New York: Academic Press, 1969);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Richard Taylor, Action and Purpose (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Arthur C. Danto, Analytical Philosophy of Action (Cambridge University Press, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Emile Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1964) pp. xlvii–xlix.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe: Free Press, 1949); cf. ‘Durkheim’s contribution to the theory of integration of social systems’, in Kurt H. Wolff, Emile Durkheim (New York: Harper, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  7. In Hollis’s terms, however, the ‘action frame of reference’ would constitute a form of ‘weak actionism’, defined as a view which ‘takes the actor to be plastic and his actions to be caused by the normative structures requiring them’. Martin Hollis, Models of Man (Cambridge University Press, 1977) p. 85.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. Louis Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital (London: New Left Books, 1970) p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  9. E. Paci, The Function of the Sciences and the Meaning of Man (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  10. For an attempt to place Paci’s writings in a general sociological context, see Barry Smart, Sociology, Phenomenology and Marxian Analysis (London: Routledge, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  11. In non-Marxist sociology, Berger and Luckmann’s Social Construction of Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1967) is closest to this type of standpoint. Their approach, however, completely lacks a conception of the critique of ideology. Moreover, notwithstanding the interest of some of their formulations, their work remains close to Parsonianism in stressing the centrality of ‘internalisation’ of values as crucial to the existence of ‘order’.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Marx, Grundrisse (Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1973) p. 712.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Charles M. Sherover, Heidegger, Kant and Time (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1971) p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  14. This is pointed out by Schutz. Alfred Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World (London: Heinemann, 1972) pp. 8ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. For the conception of durée, see Henri Bergson, Time and Free Will (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1910).

    Google Scholar 

  16. See, for example, R. S. Peters, The Concept of Motivation (London: Routledge, 1958) pp. 12ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Peter Marsh, Elisabeth Rosser and Rom Harré, The Rules of Disorder (London: Routledge, 1978) p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. Harold Garfinkel, Studies in Ethnomethodology (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Garfinkel, Studies in Ethnomethodology: see also Garfinkel’s contribution to Roy Turner, Ethnomethodology (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1974) pp. 15–18.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. Jerome Neu, ‘Genetic explanation in Totem and Taboo’, in Richard Wollheim, Freud, a Collection of Critical Essays (New York: Doubleday, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cyril Barrett, Wittgenstein: Lectures and Conversations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1967) pp. 42ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. A well-known example discussed by Davidson is a good case in point. I move a switch, turn on a light, illuminate the room, and at the same time alert a prowler. Davidson’s interest in this is purely confined to the problem of action descriptions: do I do four different things, or only one that can be described in different ways? ‘Actions, reasons and causes’, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 60 (1963). One of the few philosophical discussions of action that approaches a concern with unintended consequences is Alvin I. Goldman, A Theory of Human Action (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1970) pp. 22ff, where he analyses the ‘generation’ of acts by other acts or ‘act-tokens’.

    Google Scholar 

  23. R. K. Merton, ‘Manifest and latent functions’, in Social Theory and Social Structure (New York: Free Press, 1957); for comments see ‘Functionalism: après la lutte’.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Raymond Firth, Elements of Social Organisation (London: Watts, 1956) pp. 30 and 39 (italics not in original).

    Google Scholar 

  25. The conception of structure I advance seems to me close to that advocated by Bauman, save that he uses ‘structure’ as more or less synonymous with ‘culture’. Zygmunt Bauman, Culture as Praxis (London: Routledge, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See, for instance, John R. Searle, Speech Acts (Cambridge University Press, 1969), pp. 33ff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  27. Raymond D. Gumb, Rule-governed Linguistic Behaviour (The Hague: Mouton, 1972) reaches the same conclusion that I do, in respect of language rules: ‘all linguistic rules have both a regulative and a constitutive aspect’ (p. 25).

    Google Scholar 

  28. For other relevant considerations, see Joan Safran Ganz, Rules, a Systematic Study (The Hague: Mouton, 1971); and Hubert Schwyzer, ‘Rules and practices’, Philosophical Review, vol. 78 (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Paul Ziff, Semantic Analysis (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1960);

    Google Scholar 

  30. also Pierre Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge University Press, 1977). It might be noted that the notion of rule appears frequently in the symbolic interactionist literature, but with very little cross-referencing to the parallel literature in philosophy to do with rules.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  31. See, for instance, the various contributions to George J. McCall et al., Social Relationships (Chicago: Aldine, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics (London: Methuen, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972) p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972) pp. 80–1.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Georg Lukács, Die Zerstörung der Vernunft (Berlin: Aufbau-Verlag, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  36. The nature of Weber’s conceptualisation of power is still a matter of some controversy. Weber says ‘Macht bedeutet jede Chance, innerhalb einer sozialen Beziehung den eigenen Willen auch gegen Widerstreben durchzusetzen, gleichviel worauf diese Chance beruht’ (Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft (Tübingen: Möhr, 1956) p. 28). Although most English translations render Chance as ‘capacity’, it has been argued that, understood as ‘chance’ or ‘possibility’, the definition is less individualistic than appears to be the case. See Niklas Luhmann, Macht (Stüttgart: Enke, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ernst Bloch, A Philosophy of the Future (New York: Herber, 1970) p. viii.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Georges Gurvitch, Déterminismes sociaux et liberté humaine (Paris: Presses Universitaires, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  39. G. L. S. Shackle, Decision, Order and Time (Cambridge University Press, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. Howard S. Becker, Sociological Work (London: Allen Lane, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  41. For one of the most acute pieces of research reporting around this theme, see Paul Willis, Learning to Labour (Westmead: Saxon House, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Alfred Schutz, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970) pp. 120ff and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Amitai Etzioni, The Active Society (New York: Free Press, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Talcott Parsons, The Social System (London: Routledge, 1951).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ludwig von Bertalanffy, General System Theory (London: Allen Lane, 1968) p. xvii.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See also John W. Sutherland, Systems: Analysis, Administration, and Architecture (New York: Van Nostrand, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  47. For comments on this, see Russell L. Ackoff, ‘General system theory and systems research: contrasting conceptions of system science’, in Mihajlo D. Mesarovic (ed.), Views on General Systems Theory (New York: Wiley, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cf. Jürgen Habermas and Niklas Luhmann, Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie? (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1973). Bertalanffy stresses the importance of approaching systems theory with ‘humanistic concerns’ in mind, recognising the very real ‘fear that system theory is indeed the ultimate step towards mechanisation and devaluation of man and towards technocratic society’ (General System Theory, p. xxi).

    Google Scholar 

  49. See also Bertalanffy, Perspectives on General System Theory (New York: Brazillier, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  50. See, for example, W. Ross Ashby, An Introduction to Cybernetics (London: Chapman and Hall, 1956).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  51. Walter Buckley, Sociology and Modern Systems Theory (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  52. See M. L. Minsky, Computation, Finite and Infinite Machines (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  53. F. G. Varela et al., ‘Autopoiesis: the organisation of living systems, its characterisation and a model’, Systems, vol. 5 (1974). See also M. Gardner, ‘On cellular automata, self-reproduction, the Garden of Eden, and the game “life”’, Scientific American, no. 224 (1971); M. Zeleny and N. A. Pierre, ‘Simulation of self-renewing systems’, in E. Jantsch and C. H. Waddington (eds), Evolution and Consciousness (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  54. G. Spencer Brown, The Laws of Form (London: Allen and Unwin, 1969). I have also drawn upon an unpublished paper by Hayward R. Alker, ‘The new cybernetics of self-renewing systems’, Center for International Studies, MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  55. David Lockwood, ‘Social integration and system integration’, in George K. Zollschan and W. Hirsch, Exploitations in Social Change (London: Routledge, 1964). I do not, however, understand the differentiation in the same way as Lockwood.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Anthony Giddens, Class Structure of the Advanced Societies (London: Hutchinson, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  57. See, in particular, Erving Goffman, Frame Analysis (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  58. Peter Winch, The Idea of a Social Science (London: Routledge, 1958) pp. 32–3.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Cf. Astri Heen Wold, Decoding Oral Language (London: Academic Press, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ziff, Semantic Analysis. See also Ziff, ‘About what an adequate grammar could not do’, in Philosophical Turnings (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1966);

    Google Scholar 

  61. Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, Language and Information (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1964) pp. 175–6.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Steven Lukes, Power, a Radical View (London: Macmillan, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  63. W. B. Gallie, ‘Essentially contested concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 56 (1955–6). Gallie gives (pp. 171–2) five criteria of ‘essential contestedness’.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies, vol. 2 (London: Routledge, 1966) p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  65. An idiosyncratic contribution to these issues has recently been offered by Cutler et al. in their Marx’s ‘Capital’ and Capitalism Today (London: Routledge, 1977). ‘There is nothing’, they say, ‘in the concept of agent to ensure that all agents must be conceived as human subjects …’ (p. 266). Thus the capitalist is recognised as an agent in company law: however such a category is not limited to human individuals, but can include the business firm. ‘The joint-stock company is a legal agent and a locus of economic decision distinct from its shareholders … As for the other attributes required of an entity if it is to function as an agent of capitalist possession, it is clear that these do not require that the agent be a human individual’ (p. 277). These comments are unobjectionable, but also wholly unenlightening; they do not address the philosophical problem of agency at all. It is perfectly true that a corporation can be an agent in law. But laws have to be interpreted, and applied; it takes human agents to do that, as well as to frame them in the first place. In the sections where the authors do confront the issue of agency more directly, they make claims that simply seem to me wrong. Thus they say that, if we impute any universal attributes to human subjects, it follows that social relations ‘are relations between subjects and they exist in and through the will and consciousness of subjects’ (p. 268). But it does not follow at all; although certainly no approach which ignores the will and consciousness of human subjects is likely to be of much use in social theory.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1979 Anthony Giddens

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Giddens, A. (1979). Agency, Structure. In: Central Problems in Social Theory. Contemporary Social Theory. Palgrave, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-16161-4_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics