Skip to main content

At the Potter’s Wheel : An Argument for Material Agency

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Material Agency

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I am referring to Walter’s (1953) creation of the first autonomous robotic devices (machina speculatrix) baptised as Elsie and Elmer (for ElectroMechanical Robot, Light-Sensitive) later nicknamed after an “Alice in Wonderland” character as “tortoise”. The devices though primitive from a mechanical and electronic point of view were capable of displaying unusual and unexpected forms of complex behaviour in the absence of any representational content. On the basis of their primitive circuitry, the tortoises were in a way structured to perform only two actions: (a) to avoid obstacles, retreating when they hit one and (b) to seek a light source. However, engaged with the environment, they were capable to produce emergent properties and in some cases what appeared as meaningful behaviour that could not be determined by their system components. Primitive as they might seem in the light of recent developments in the domain of AI the tortoise’s managed to effect in practice a cybernetic transgression of the mind-body-world divide, materially exemplifying an embodied, performative cognitive system, one in which the mind-body-world components are continuous and equally necessary, with none hierarchically controlling the others. A premise that resonates well and to some extent anticipates the perspective of embodied and situated cognition as developed the last two decades in the works of Clark (1997), Hutchins (1995), Brooks (1991) and Van Gelder (1995).

  2. 2.

    “The world is inseparable from the subject, but from a subject which is nothing but a project of the world, and the subject is inseparable from the world, but from a world which the subject itself projects” (Merleau-Ponty 1962, 430).

  3. 3.

    We are engaged in what Searle (1983) himself recognises as “Networks of Intentional states”, but with the requirement that those networks should be better perceived as actor-networks and as such irreducible to any of the constitutive elements in isolation.

References

  • Bateson, G., 1973. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. London: Granada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A., 1991. Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence 47: 39–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. and Latour, B., 1981. Unscrewing the Big Leviathan. In Advances in Social Theory and Methodology: Towards an Integration of Micro and Macro-Sociology, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and A. V. Cicouvel, pp. 277–303. Routledge, Boston, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S., 1998. The Mind’s Past. University of California Press, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. and Chalmers, D., 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58(1): 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennet, D. C., 1987. The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., 2005. How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4(1): 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gell, A., 1998. Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W., 2001. Intentions as emergent products of social interactions. In Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition, edited by F. Bertram, L. J. Moses and D. A. Baldwin. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J., 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howhy, J. and Frith, C., 2004. Can Neuroscience explain consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 180–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E., 1995. Cognition in the Wild. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knappett, C., 2005. Thinking Through Material Culture: An Interdisciplinary Perspective. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knappett, C., 2004. The affordances of things: A post-Gibsonian perspective on the relationality of mind and matter. In Rethinking Materiality: The Engagement of Mind with the Material World, edited by E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden and C. Renfrew, pp. 43–51. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knappett, C., 2006. Beyond Skin: Layering and Networking in Art and Archaeology. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 16(2): 239–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., 1995. The intelligent use of space, Artificial Intelligence 73(1–2): 31–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., 1996. Adapting the environment instead of oneself. Adaptive Behavior 4(3–4): 415–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., 1985. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8: 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., 1999. Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies 6: 47–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W. and Pearl, D. K., 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 102: 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L., 2004. The cognitive basis of material engagement: Where brain, body and culture conflate. In Rethinking Materiality: The Engagement of Mind with the Material World, edited by E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden and C. Renfrew, pp. 53–62. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L., in press. Linear B as distributed cognition: Excavating a mind not limited by the skin. In material culture. In Excavating the Mind: Cross-sections Through Culture, Cognition and Materiality, edited by M. Jessen, N. Johanssen and H. J. Jensen. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. and C. Renfrew, editors, in press. The Cognitive Life of Things: Recasting the Boundaries of the Mind. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M., 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, B. and Skibo, J. M., 1997. The explanation of artifact variability. American Antiquity 62: 27–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M. and Haggard, P., 2005. Experimenting with the acting self. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3/4): 387–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Leeuw, S. E., 1993. Giving the potter a choice: Conceptual aspects of pottery techniques. In Technological Choices: Transformations in Material Cultures since the Neolithic, edited by P. Lemonnier, pp. 238–288. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van der Leeuw, S. E., 1994. Cognitive aspects of technique. In The Ancient Mind, edited by C. Renfrew and E. Zubrow, pp. 135–142. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T., 1995. What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy 91: 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walter, W. G., 1953. The Living Brain. Duckworth, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., 2002. The Illusion of Conscious Will. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., 2003. The mind’s best trick: How we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive Science 7: 65–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., 2004. Precis of the illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27: 649–692.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertsch, J. V., 1998. Mind as Action. Oxford University Press, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L., 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lambros Malafouris .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Malafouris, L. (2008). At the Potter’s Wheel : An Argument for Material Agency. In: Knappett, C., Malafouris, L. (eds) Material Agency. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-74711-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics