Skip to main content
Log in

Are there limits to scientists’ obligations to seek and engage dissenters?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Dissent is thought to play a valuable role in science, so that scientific communities ought to create opportunities for receiving critical feedback and take dissenting views seriously. There is concern, however, that some dissent does more harm than good. Dissent on climate change and evolutionary theory, for example, has confused the public, created doubt about existing consensus, derailed public policy, and forced scientists to devote resources to respond. Are there limits to the extent to which scientific communities have obligations to seek and engage dissenting views? We consider the two main criteria that have been offered for what constitutes “normatively appropriate dissent” or the sort of dissent that ought to have the opportunity to be heard and taken seriously. Many have argued that dissenters must (1) engage in uptake of criticism against their own views and (2) share some standards for theory appraisal. We argue these criteria ultimately are unsuccessful.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some may contend that here may be important differences between these cases of dissent and thus that scientific communities might approach them differently. For example, one might argue that there is significantly more uncertainty in the cases of climate change science than in the case of evolutionary theory. Perhaps under conditions of uncertainty, we have greater obligations to seek and engage dissenting views because when there is greater uncertainty, there is also presumably more disagreement and less consensus. We agree that such differences might indeed exist and be relevant. However we use these cases to assess obligations to seek and engage dissent because they are the cases that proponents of normatively appropriate dissent take to be cases where consensus exists and where engagement with dissenters is limited by the criteria they offer.

  2. Thanks to Boaz Miller for suggesting this distinction.

  3. We are not claiming that a scientific consensus actually exists on the safety of GMOs. Indeed, some might argue that the current “consensus” is among molecular biologists and scientists who collaborate with agribusiness corporations mainly in the US and is not sufficiently diverse or representative to be an indicator of knowledge (Miller 2013). Large numbers of ecologists, agricultural scientists, sociologists, and medical practitioners in areas where GMOs are grown in many poor countries would deny that this is genuine consensus. Our point here is thus not to defend the existence of a consensus on the safety of GMOs. Rather, we are interested in determining what conception of shared standards underlies Kitcher’s contention that we have no obligations to seek and engage dissent on GMO safety. We thank a reviewer for forcing us to clarify this point.

References

  • Anderson, E. (2006). The epistemology of democracy. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 3(1), 8–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J., & Moore, A. (2010). Should we aim for consensus? Episteme, 7(3), 198–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (1996). Darwin’s black box : The biochemical challenge to evolution. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (2000). Self-organization and irreducibly complex systems: A reply to Shanks and Joplin. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 155–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (2001). Reply to my critics: A response to reviews of Darwin’s Black Box: The biochemical challenge to evolution. Biology & Philosophy, 16(5), 685–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (2007). The edge of evolution : The search for the limits of Darwinism. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borgerson, K. (2011). Amending and defending critical contextual empiricism. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(3), 435–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brockman, J. (2006). Intelligent thought : Science versus the intelligent design movement. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. A., & Meyer, S. C. (2003). Darwinism, design, and public education, rhetoric and public affairs series. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. M., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne, J. A. (2009). Why evolution is true. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlberg, F. (1981). Woman the gatherer. New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Dawkins, R. (2009). The greatest show on Earth : The evidence for evolution. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeFrancesco, L. (2013). How safe does transgenic food need to be? Nature Biotechnology, 31(9), 794–802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delborne, J. A. (2008). Transgenes and transgressions: Scientific dissent as heterogeneous practice. Social Studies of Science, 38(4), 509–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, W. A. (1999). Intelligent design : The bridge between science & theology. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, W. A. (2002). No free lunch : Why specified complexity cannot be purchased without intelligence. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, W. A., & McDowell, S. (2008). Understanding intelligent design. Eugene, OR: Harvest House Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, W. A., & Ruse, M. (2004). Debating design : From Darwin to DNA. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fall, S., Watts, A., Nielsen-Gammon, J., Jones, E., Niyogi, D., Christy, J. R., & Pielke Sr, R. A. (2011). Analysis of the impacts of station exposure on the US Historical Climatology Network temperatures and temperature trends. Journal of Geophysical Research: Atmospheres, 116, D14120.

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method : Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice : Power and the ethics of knowing. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gero, J. (1991). Genderlithics: Women’s roles in stone tool production. In J. Gero & M. W. Conkey (Eds.), Engendering Archaeology (pp.163-192). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

  • Gish, D. T. (1985). Evolution : The challenge of the fossil record. El Cajon, CA: Creation-Life Publishers, Master Book Division.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(1), 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1977). Ontogeny and phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. G. (1993). Rethinking standpoint epistemology: What is strong objectivity? In L. Alcoff & E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. G. (2008). Sciences from below: Feminisms, postcolonialities, and modernities. Durham: Duke University Press.

  • Irwin, A., & Wynne, B. (1996). Misunderstanding science? : The public reconstruction of science and technology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (2004). States of knowledge : The co-production of science and social order, International library of sociology. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. (2005). Challenging expert rule: The politics of global governance. Sydney Journal of International Law, 27, 5–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science : Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy, Oxford studies in philosophy of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2002). The third way: Reflections on Helen Longino’s the fate of knowledge. Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 549–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2007). Living with Darwin : Evolution, design, and the future of faith, philosophy in action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures: How the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2010). Philosophy of science after feminism. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). The essential tension : Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2005). Values in science. Lanhm, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laughlin, W. S. (1968). Hunting: An integrating biobehavior system and its evolutionary importance. In Lee & I. DeVore (Eds.), Man the Hunter (pp. 304–320). Chicago, IL: Aldine.

  • Lomborg, B. (2008). Cool it: The skeptical environmentalist’s guide to global warming. New York: Vintage Books.

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge : Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1995). Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese, 104(3), 383–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, B. (1999). Suppression of dissent in science. In W. R. Freudenburg & T. I. K. Youn (Eds.), Research in social problems and public policy. Stamford, CT: JAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, S. C. (2009). Signature in the cell : DNA and the evidence for intelligent design. New York: HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, D. (2008). Doubt is their product : How industry’s assault on science threatens your health. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, P. J. (2009). How to manufacture a climate consensus. The Wall Street Journal. http://online.wsj.com/news/articles/SB10001424052748704398304574598230426037244

  • Miller, B. (2013). When is consensus knowledge-based: Distinguishing shared knowledge from mere agreement. Synthese, 190(7), 1293–1316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, L. H. (1990). Who knows : From Quine to a feminist empiricism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M. (2010). Merchants of doubt : How a handful of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to global warming. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, F. (2010). Climate change emails between scientists real flaws in peer review. The Guardian. http://www.theguardian.com/environment/2010/feb/02/hacked-climate-emails-flaws-peer-review

  • Plutynski, A. (2005). Parsimony and the Fisher-Wright debate. Biology & Philosophy, 20(4), 697–713.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1993). Pluralism : Against the demand for consensus, Clarendon library of logic and philosophy. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1982). Darwinism defended: A guide to the evolution controversies. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program/World Science Division.

  • Ruse, M. (2005). The evolution-creation struggle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2007). Doubting Darwin? : Creationist designs on evolution, Blackwell public philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selinger, E., & Crease, R. P. (2006). The philosophy of expertise. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sewell, G. (2010). In the beginning: And other essays on intelligent design. Seattle, WA: Discovery Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution, and inference. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2006). Norms of epistemic diversity. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 3(1), 23–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2008). Norms of Dissent. Centre for the Philosophy of Natural and Social Science Contingency and Dissent in Science.Te chnical Report 09/08. http://www.lse.ac.uk/CPNSS/projects/CoreResearchProjects/ContingencyDissentInScience/DP/SolomonNormsOfDissent0908Online.pdf:2--21.

  • Steel, D. (2009). Testability and Ockham’s razor: How formal and statistical learning theory converge in the new riddle of induction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38(5), 471–489.

    Google Scholar 

  • Washburn, S. L., & Lancaster, C. S. (1968). The evolution of hunting. In R. B. Lee & I. De Vore (Eds.), Man the Hunter (pp. 293-303). Chicago, IL: Aldine.

  • Wells, J., & Dembski, W. A. (2007). The design of life. Dallas: Foundation for Thought and Ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  • Witt, J. (2005). The intelligent approach: Teach the strengths and weakness of evolution. The Discovery Institute. http://www.discovery.org/a/2743.

  • Wylie, A. (2001). Doing social science as a feminist: The engendering of archaeology. In A. N. H. Creager, E. Lunbeck & Schiebinger L (Eds.), Feminism in twentieth century science, technology, and medicine (pp. 23-45). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Wylie, A., & Nelson, L. H. (2007). Coming to terms with the values of science: Insights from feminist science studies scholarship. In H. Kincaid, J. Dupre & A. Wylie (Eds.), Value-free science: Ideals and illusions (pp. 58-86). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Zellner, A., Keuzenkamp, H. A., & McAleer, M. (2001). Simplicity, inference and modeling: Keeping it sophisticatedly simple. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Boaz Miller and Sharon Crasnow for providing helpful feedback on earlier drafts of this manuscript. This paper also greatly benefited from the comments and suggestions of three anonymous referees.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Inmaculada de Melo-Martín.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Intemann, K., de Melo-Martín, I. Are there limits to scientists’ obligations to seek and engage dissenters?. Synthese 191, 2751–2765 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0414-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0414-5

Keywords

Navigation