Skip to main content
Log in

From Welfare to Rights without Changing the Subject

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I introduce the ‘changing the subject’ problem. When proponents of animal protection use terms such as dignity and respect they can be fairly accused of shifting debate from welfare to rights because the terms purportedly refer to properties and values that are logically distinct from the capacity to suffer and the moral significance of causing animals pain. To avoid this problem and ensure that debate proceeds in the familiar terms of the established welfare paradigm, I present an expressivist analysis of animal rights vocabulary. When terms such as dignity and respect are understood in line with the theory of moral language use known as expressivism, proponents of animal protection that use these terms can escape the charge of changing the subject. Drawing upon Helm’s theory of love, I show how the usage of rights vocabulary can be respectable way for people to register their concern for the welfare of animals, even at times when it is unlikely that the animals concerned are suffering. Tying rights vocabulary to welfare via expressivism aligns the aims of animal rights with welfare without the theoretical problems associated with attempts to ‘reduce’ dignity or respect to natural behaviour or inherent value.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Nussbaum (2006) and Gruen (2010), for example, ground dignity in species-typical or natural behavior; Regan (2004) grounds respect in inherent value – a value that is ‘not reducible to experiences’. Regan’s rationale for postulating inherent value was to ensure that moral patients could have the same protection from being used or painlessly killed as moral agents. His point was that the morality of ‘using as a means’ and painless killing is conceptually distinct from the morality of suffering. See Regan 2004: xxii. Arguably, it is most appropriate to use terms like dignity and respect when animals are not suffering at all.

  2. This claim should be read in the pragmatic or non-ideal spirit in which it is intended. As Jonathan Wolf (cited in Garner 2013, p.167) puts it: “The task of the political philosopher is not to design the best possible world, but to design the best possible world starting from here.”

  3. Hedonism can be understood as both a theory of value in general and a theory of well-being or welfare for individuals. Roughly, it is the view that “all and only positive experiences are good and all and only negative experiences are bad “(Gregory 2015).

  4. Animal welfare theory can be similarly cast as hedonistic. After all, two key ideas in animal welfare theory are (1) the principle that animals are held as having moral worth in virtue of being sentient and (2) the necessary/unnecessary suffering distinction (Garner 2013:80–81).

  5. The hedonistic orientation of the feelings view needs little explanation. A hedonistic interpretation of the biological functioning view is that good or proper biological function points to the animal being free of distress or pain. Likewise natural behaviour can be interpreted as a proxy for the absence of pain or the presence of pleasurable feeling. Rice (2015: 385) casts the reduction of each welfare position to hedonism as prioritizing subjective views over objective views. He cites Hursthouse’s virtue-inspired view and Nussbaum’s capabilities view as the paradigmatic examples of objective views (381–384).

  6. Two related accounts are the dislike theory (Parfit 1984), according to which pain is bad because the bodily sensation associated with it is undesired; and the felt aversion theory (Kahane 2016), according to which the badness of pain is analyzed as the experience of having a bodily sensation that is disliked giving rise to a special kind of emotion which is itself aversive. In his account of pain, Adam Swenson (2009) casts pain as a usurper – it is bad because it usurps an agent’s autonomy understood as their ‘user control’.

  7. Both papers report a public concern for the expression of natural behaviour. While natural behaviour is interpreted by welfare scientists as a utility proxy, that is, as indicative of the absence of suffering; arguably, public concern to ensure factory farm animals express natural behaviour can be interpreted as a nonhedonistic consideration. The idea that natural behaviour is a nonhedonisitic consideration is also supported by its positing by Cataldi (2002) and Nussbaum (2004) as the grounds for dignity. See the discussion in Part II.

  8. By ‘folk’ I mean simply common sense or the pre-reflective views of ordinary citizens. My hypothesis is that folk concern for animals is not as hedonistically-focused as proponents of welfare orthodoxy assume. I presuppose that animal welfare legislation and norms are meant to reflect the content of folk views. In so far as existing welfare paradigm has an exclusive hedonistic orientation then its democratic legitimacy can be called into question.

  9. For Helm, some nonhuman animals are members of the relevant class, ‘agents’: “What it is to be an agent is to have and exercise the capacities not only to have beliefs and desires but also to care about things…(84)

  10. Garner makes a similar point when he contrasts the views of research scientists with the views of a “majority of the public” (2013: 139). He identifies the former with the standard animal welfare ethic and the later with the ‘sentience position’ he advocates. Garner suggests that the different approaches entail contrasting interpretations of the so-called Five Freedoms.

  11. If Cataldi were to align her usage of ‘dignity’ only to practices that required animals to suffer then she would face what Zuolo calls the redundancy problem. The use of the term dignity is redundant because the purported ‘wrongness’ of the practice is ‘already explained’ as a violation of a right not to suffer. See Zuolo 2016

  12. Bear in mind that my claim is not that they are wrong to do this; rather, my aim is show how their concerns can be met within the confines of the welfare paradigm.

  13. And also to the metaphysical and semantic problems mentioned above.

References

  • Aristotle (1999) Nicomachean ethics. Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis

  • Bracke MBM, Hopster H (2006) Assessing the importance of natural behavior for animal welfare. J Agr Environ Ethic 18:77–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cataldi S (2002) Animals and the concept of dignity: critical reflection on a circus performance. Ethics & the Environment 7(2):104–126. https://doi.org/10.2979/ETE.2002.7.2.104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochrane A (2010) Undignified bioethics. Bioethics 24(5):234–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1993) Life’s dominion: an argument about abortion, euthanasia and individual freedom. Knopf, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Favre D (2016) The history of anti-cruelty laws: concepts of animal welfare and animal rights. In: Brewster MP, Reyes CL (eds) Animal cruelty, a multidisciplinary approach to understanding, 2nd edn. Carolina academic press, Durham, pp 25–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Francione G (2000) Introduction to animal rights: your child or the dog. Temple University Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser D (2003) Assessing farm animal welfare at the farm and group level: the interplay of science and values. Anim Welf 12:433–443

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser D, Weary D (2004) Quality of life for farm animals: linking science, ethics and animal welfare. In: Benson J, Rollin B (eds) The well-being of farm animals: challenges and solutions. Blackwell, Oxford. https://doi.org/10.1002/9780470344859.ch3

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner R (2013) A theory of justice for animals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory A (2015) Hedonism. In: Fletcher G (ed) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of well-being. Taylor and Francis, pp 113–123

  • Gruen L (2011) Ethics and animals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haynes RP (2008) Animal welfare: competing conceptions and their ethical implications. Springer, Dordrecht

  • Helm BW (2010) Love, friendship and the self. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard C, Scott K (2011) Do farmers and scientists differ in their understanding and assessment of farm animal welfare? Anim Welf 20:79–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys R (2016) Dignity and its violation examined within the context of animal ethics. Ethics Environ 21(2):143–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane G (2015) Pain, experience and well-being in: the Routledge handbook of the philosophy of wellbeing. Fletcher G (ed) Taylor Francis, pp. 209-220

  • Mellor DJ, Beausoleil NJ (2015) Extending the ‘five domains’ model for animal welfare assessment to incorporate positive welfare states. Anim Welf 24:241–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller A (2003) An introduction to contemporary metaethics. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1993) Principia ethica new edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2004) Beyond ‘compassion and humanity’: justice for nonhuman animals. In: Sunstein CR, Nussbaum MC (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford university press, Oxford, pp 299–320

  • Nussbaum MC (2006) Frontiers of justice: disability, nationality, species membership. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Prickett RW, Bailey NF, Lusk JL (2010) Consumer preferences for farm animal welfare: results from a telephone survey of US households. Anim Welf 19:335–347

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan T (2004) The case for animal rights, 2nd edn. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice CM (2015) Well-being and animals. In: The Routledge handbook of the philosophy of wellbeing, fletcher G (ed) Taylor Francis, pp 378–388

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollin BE (2006) Regulation of animal research and the emergence of animal ethics: a conceptual history. Theor Med 27:285–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz-Bergin M (2017) The dignity of diminished animals: species norms and engineering to improve welfare. Ethical Theory Moral. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9828-8

  • Swenson A (2009) Pain’s evils. Utilitas 21(2):197–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeke W (2009) Stakeholder, citizen and consumer interests in farm animal welfare. Anim Welf 18:325–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuolo F (2016) Dignity and animals. Does it make sense to apply the concept of dignity to all sentient beings? Ethical Theory Moral 19(5):1117–1130. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-016-9695-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Hadley.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hadley, J. From Welfare to Rights without Changing the Subject. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 20, 993–1004 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9856-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9856-4

Keywords

Navigation