Skip to main content
Log in

Absence of action

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. The example is from Brand (1971, pp. 45–46).

  2. I don’t mean to imply that omitting is the same thing as refraining, nor that every absence of action is an omission. In fact I believe neither of these things. I discuss differences between omitting and refraining, and in which cases an absence of action is an omission, in Clarke in press.

  3. The first and second points here are raised by Varzi (2006, p. 131).

  4. The example is from Mele (1997, p. 232), though he employs it for a different purpose.

  5. I’ve adapted the example from Varzi (2006, p. 135), making changes to illustrate my points here.

  6. Brownstein (1973) and Hochberg (1969) advance this sort of view.

  7. Beall (2000) and Priest (2000) propose views of this sort.

  8. Armstrong (1978, pp. 23–29) advances these reasons for rejecting negative properties.

  9. Priest says at one point that we needn’t think of the polarities “as objects. They simply code the fact that there are two ways in which [a property] may relate to [an object], namely, positively or negatively” (2000, pp. 317–318). Stating the view this way suggests that it distinguishes two kinds of ties–instantiation and non-instantiation–that can each bind an object and a property into a state of affairs.

  10. Both Beall and Priest cite Barwise and Perry (1983) as a source of their view. Barwise and Perry take each “abstract situation” to include as a constituent 1 or 0: 1 if the object or objects instantiate the property or relation at the location in question, 0 if they don’t.

    But abstract situations are introduced as representations of what are called “real situations.” The former are “abstract set-theoretic objects, built up from the individuals, properties, relations, and locations abstracted from real situations. They play no role in the causal order. People don’t grasp them, see them, move them, or even know or believe them” (1983, p. 9). In contrast, real situations “are not sets, but parts of reality” (p. 58).

    Barwise and Perry caution: “It is important…not to confuse real situations with their abstract counterparts” (1983, p. 58). When they list the things that make up real situations (7, 50), nothing corresponding to the 1- or 0-constituent of an abstract state of affairs appears in the list. What would it be?

    “The numbers 0 and 1,” Barwise and Perry say, “unlike the individuals [who partly make up real situations], are just tools we use to build up our system of classifying real situations” (1983, p. 8). They are, I take it, just constituents of representations of real situations.

  11. See Armstrong (2004, p. 62) and Mellor (1995, p. 164).

  12. Armstrong (2004, p. 59) makes a similar point. He posits “totality states of affairs” as truthmakers for truths such as (our imagined truth) that there are no wooden spheres. Such a totality might consist of positive states of affairs involving the sphere a together with the (higher-order) state of affairs of these being all the (lower-order) sphere-involving states of affairs. Totality states of affairs would be a kind of negative state of affairs, but none of the kinds we’ve considered here. They would, Armstrong says, give us limits but not absences.

    Might omissions be said to be limits of this sort? One difficulty concerns wrongly identifying certain omissions. The totality state of affairs consisting of all that I did during a certain interval on a certain day (and the state of affairs of that being all that I did) isn’t both my omitting to get the milk and my omitting to pick up the dry cleaning, for it isn’t true that these omissions are identical.

  13. Lewis (1992, p. 216) suggests this sort of treatment of negative existentials, such as that there are no unicorns.

  14. In comments on this paper for the Bellingham meeting, Sara Bernstein suggested that what she calls failures—absences of things that could have or should have been—are possibilia.

  15. Peter Forrest proposed this view during the discussion at Bellingham.

  16. Several members of the Bellingham audience seemed to like this idea.

  17. Another proposal is that omissions are things not identical with but constituted, at least in part, by the ways agents actually move their bodies at certain times (Fischer and Ravizza 1998, pp. 132–134). One difficulty for such a view lies in saying to what category of being these constituted entities belong. The constituting things are events, processes, or states of affairs; are the constituted things negative versions of one or another of these things? If so, my discussion in the text above bears on this view. A second kind of problem is that for many cases this view implies incorrect attributions of locations, times, causes, effects, and other features to omissions. I develop this criticism in Clarke (2011) and in press.

  18. Varzi (2006, pp. 138–139) makes similar points, but his focus is on analyses of sentences we might affirm regarding omissions. My concern here is not with analysis or logical form of sentences but with what entities must exist if those sentences are to be true.

  19. Dowe (2000, p. 132) and Lewis (2004, p. 285) make similar suggestions about apparent cases of causation of absences, though what I suggest here differs from both of their proposals. Dowe doesn’t think that such apparent causation is genuine, while Lewis does.

  20. The causal notion isn’t the only one. Philosophers fond of a view of the world as multi-leveled often take higher-level entities to result non-causally from lower-level things. And perhaps sums result from addition. But it isn’t either of these notions that I’m employing here.

  21. Compare Dowe (2000, p. 136) and Lewis (2004, p. 284). Again, my suggestion here differs somewhat from both of theirs.

  22. Weinryb (1980) argues that omissions have no consequences. His argument relies on a claim that omissions cause nothing. But ‘causal consequence’ isn’t pleonastic.

  23. Some writers have proposed views of absence causation aimed at selecting some among the many causally relevant absences that might be said to be causes. McGrath (2005) and Thomson (2003) advance views on which absence causation has a normative dimension. I find this doubtful. Dowe (2010) suggests that we might apply Yablo’s (1992, 1997) proportionality constraint to select which among various candidate absences to count as causes. However, as Dowe observes, the resulting view would commonly conflict with folk judgments about absence causation.

  24. Lewis (2004), in response to the problem of absence causation, denies that causation is always a matter of one thing standing in a causal relation to another, and Mellor (2004) rejects the view that causation is a relation.

  25. I’ve addressed the first of these questions in Clarke (2010) and the second in Clarke (2011).

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1978). Universals and scientific realism, Volume 2: A theory of universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C. (2000). On truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 264–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2004). Causing and nothingness. In J. Collins, N. Hal, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 291–308). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Brand, Myles. (1971). The language of not doing. American Philosophical Quarterly, 8, 45–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, D. (1973). Negative exemplification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 10, 43–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, C., & Pigden, C. (2006). Negative truths from positive facts. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 249–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2010). Intentional omissions. Noûs, 44, 158–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2011). Omissions, responsibility, and symmetry. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 594–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (in press). What is an omission? Philosophical Issues.

  • Dodd, J. (2007). Negative truths and truthmaker principles. Synthese, 156, 383–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2010). Proportionality and omissions. Analysis, 70, 446–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg, H. (1969). Negation and generality. Noûs, 3, 325–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukso, B. (2006). The reality of absences. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1992). Critical notice of D. M. Armstrong’s ‘A combinatorial theory of possibility’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 211–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2004). Void and object. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 277–290). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Martin, C. B. (1996). How it is: Entities, absences and voids. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 57–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A dilemma. Philosophical Studies, 123, 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1997). Agency and mental action. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 231–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1995). The facts of causation. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (2004). For facts as causes and effects. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 309–323). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Priest, G. (2000). Truth and contradiction. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 305–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 197–216). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (2003). Causation: Omissions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 81–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, A. C. (2006). The talk I was supposed to give…. In A. Bottani & R. Davies (Eds.), Modes of existence: Papers in ontology and philosophical logic (pp. 131–151). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

  • Weinryb, E. (1980). Omissions and responsibility. Philosophical Quarterly, 30, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1997). Wide causation. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 251–281.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments on earlier versions of the paper, I want to thank Kent Bach, Mark Balaguer, Sara Bernstein, John Heil, Stephen Kearns, Al Mele, Achille Varzi, and the audience at the 2011 Bellingham Summer Philosophy Conference.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Randolph Clarke.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Clarke, R. Absence of action. Philos Stud 158, 361–376 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9881-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9881-z

Keywords

Navigation