Skip to main content
Log in

Heidegger, subjectivity, disability

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Subjectivity Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, I ask what a Heideggerian analysis of subjectivity can do for disability politics, and to the investigation of subject formation more generally. I begin by outlining the historically dominant ‘social model of disability’, which frames disability as a form of oppression. In the section ‘Michael Oliver and the politics of disablement’, I suggest that a re-reading of Heidegger on subjectivity allows us to chart aspects of disabled personhood missed by the social model. Heidegger argues human existence (Dasein) defies subjectivity; I argue it is more primordial, but that the two can co-exist, particularly when disabled persons shape their own subjectivity. I provide a threefold ontological structure, Dasein-Mitdasein-Subjectivity, sensitive to the politics of subject formation. Finally, I turn to two cases of ontological disability politics, those of the French Muscular Dystrophy Association and global thalidomider politics, to show how my reading of subjectivity is preferable to the social model’s.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are, of course, many frameworks used to study disability sociologically; the social model is not the only one. It is, however, the most prominent: in the early days of Disability, Handicap, & Society (now Disability & Society), the journal edited by Oliver until his retirement, the social model was the dominant framework for studying disability, and is still taught in disability studies courses worldwide. Because of this ubiquity, it is also the most critiqued approach to studying disability.

  2. In this way, social model thinking is very close to so-called ‘standpoint epistemology’, particularly that of Hartsock (1983). They differ in that hers is formed on the participation of women in two forms of labor, generating both exchange-value outside the home and use-value inside it, whereas Oliver’s is predicated on the inability of disabled persons to participate in the production and circulation of surplus value. Despite his proximity to such thinking, he does not cite Hartsock in the Politics.

  3. More devoted Heideggerians will call this the difference between the ‘ontological’ and the ‘ontic’, between the Being of beings and their properties.

  4. Dreyfus (1991) suggests threefold fundamental ontology – that of Dasein, things-present-at-hand, and merely present objects. I do not find this additional distinction helpful, as the latter two forms are available to human beings only because of the care-structure found in the first. Dasein is fundamental and only in its being do the other forms gain shape or meaning.

  5. This is not a article about or against cognitive science and its purview. For a comprehensive account of cognitivism in cognitive science and a phenomenological way forward, see Thompson’s (2007) Mind in Life.

  6. Here I use ‘rational’ not in reference to Cartesian philosophical rationalism, but rather to all members’ activities perpetuating social organization. I take this formulation from one of Harold Garfinkel’s Studies in Ethnomethodology, ‘The rational properties of scientific and common sense activities’ (1967, Ch. 8, pp. 262–284).

  7. The term ‘Cartesianism’ is often used to describe this sort of thinking. I worry that this attributes too much to Descartes, who died in 1650, and not enough to each described position and the development of thought since the seventeenth century (I borrow this objection from Hacking, 2007). Heidegger does indeed discuss Descartes at length in Being and Time, but does so as part of Western philosophical history. I avoid the term because it attributes too much to one (straw) man, whereas the tradition should be our object. That said, Heidegger nonetheless dismisses Descartes as legitimate philosopher of human Being. For a more charitable reading of Descartes, as a ‘proto-phenomenologist’, who reads some but not all aspects of human bodily existence in his Meditations, see Leder’s (1990) The Absent Body. I find this reading more accurate – and thus preferable.

  8. I requested permission to use an image of the statue in a previous article (Abrams, 2014a), but Grünenthal declined this request. Interested readers of Subjectivity can search images.google.com for ‘thalidomide sculpture’ to see the statue.

References

  • Abberley, P. (1987) The concept of oppression and the development of a social theory of disability. Disability, Handicap & Society 2 (1): 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahmed, S. (2006) Queer Phenomenology: Orientations, Objects, Others. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, G. and Elias, S. (1999) Thalidomide and the titanic: Reconstructing The technology tragedies of the twentieth century. American Journal of Public Health 89 (1): 98–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, T. (2013a) Being-towards-death and taxes: Heidegger, disability, and the ontological difference. Canadian Journal of Disability Studies 2 (1): 28–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, T. (2013b) Taking tragic measures? Disability studies’ Anti-Metrology and the global government of Thalidomide. Theoria and Praxis 1 (2): 27–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, T. (2014a) Boon or Bust? Heidegger, disability aesthetics and the Thalidomide memorial. Disability & Society 20 (5): 751–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, T. (2014b) Is everyone upright? Erwin Straus’ ‘The Upright Posture’ and disabled phenomenology. Human Affairs 24 (4): 564–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, T. (2014c) Flawed by Dasein? Phenomenology, Ethnomethodology, and the personal experience of physiotherapy. Human Studies 37 (3): 431–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, C. (1992) Qualitative research – Valuable or irrelevant. Disability & Society 11 (1): 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, C. (1996) Disability and the myth of the independent researcher. Disability & Society 11 (1): 107–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackman, L., Cromby, J., Hook, D., Papadopolous, D. and Walkerdine, V. (2008) Creating subjectivities. Subjectivity 22 (1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boss, M. (1963) Psychoanalysis and Daseinanalysis. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. (2008) Economic markets and the rise of interactive agencements: From prosthetic agencies to habilitated agencies. In: T. Pinch and R. Swedberg (eds.) Living in a Material World: Economic Sociology Meets Science and Technology Studies. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 29–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. and Rabeharisoa, V. (2004) Gino’s lesson on humanity: Genetics, mutual entanglements and the sociologist’s role. Economy and Society 33 (1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. and Rabeharisoa, V. (2008) The growing engagement of emergent Concerned groups in political and economic life: Lessons from the French association of neuromuscular disease patients. Science, Technology & Human Values 33 (2): 230–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dallamayr, F. (1993) Heidegger and Freud. Political Psychology 14 (2): 235–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (1991) Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (1992) What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. (Revised ed.) Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. and Wrathall, M.A. (2005) Martin Heidegger: An introduction to his thought, work and life. In: H.L. Dreyfus and M.A. Wrathall (eds.) A Companion to Heidegger. Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 1–16.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1978) The History of Sexuality Volume 1: An Introduction. Translated by R. Hurley. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, M.E., Macpherson, G.R. and Figg, W.D. (2004) Thalidomide. The Lancet 363 (9423): 1802–1811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, H. (1967) Studies in Ethnomethodology. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1967) Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face Behaviour. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, E. (1983) The interaction order: American sociological association, 1982 presidential address. American Sociological Review 48 (1): 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodley, D. (2001) ‘Learning difficulties’, the social model of disability and impairment: Challenging epistemologies. Disability & Society 16 (2): 207–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2007) Our Neo-Cartesian bodies in parts. Critical Inquiry 34 (1): 78–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartsock, N. (1983) The feminist standpoint: Developing the ground for a specifically feminist historical materialism. In: S. Harding and M. Hintikka (eds.) Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science. 2nd edn. Boston, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 283–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1971) Building, dwelling, thinking. Trans. and ed. by A. Hofstadter. In: Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: pp. 143–159. HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996) Being and Time. Translated by J. Stambaugh. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993) Letter on humanism. In: D.F. Krell (ed.) Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. 2nd edn. San Francisco, CA: Harper Collins, pp. 213–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2001) Zollikon Seminars. Translated by F. Mayr and R. Askay. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B. (2007) Being disabled: Towards a critical social ontology for disability studies. Disability & Society 22 (7): 673–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B. and Paterson, K. (1997) The social model of disability and the disappearing body: Towards a sociology of impairment. Disability & Society 12 (3): 325–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1992) Where are the missing masses? A sociology of a few Mundane artifacts. In: J. Law and W. Bijker (eds.) Shaping Technology/Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical Change. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp 225–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leder, D. (1990) The Absent Body. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962) Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by C. Smith. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mol, A. (2002) The Body Multiple: Ontology in Medical Practice. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, M. (1990) The Politics of Disablement. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (2005) Decentering sociology: Synthetic dyes and social theory. Perspectives on Science 13 (3): 352–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (2009) The politics of theory. Journal of Cultural Economy 2 (1): 197–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabeharisoa, V. and Callon, M. (2004) Patients and scientists in French muscular dystrophy research. In: S. Jasanoff (ed.) States of Knowledge: The Co-production of Science and Social Order. London and New York: Routledge, pp. 142–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2014) Heidegger’s influence on posthumanism: The destruction of metaphysics, technology and the overcoming of anthropocentrism. History of the Human Sciences 27 (1): 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schillmeier, M. (2010) Rethinking Disability: Bodies, Senses, Things. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shakespeare, T. (2006) Disability Rights and Wrongs. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shakespeare, T. (2012) Still a health issue. Disability and Health Journal 5 (3): 129–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007) Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmermans, S. and Leiter, V. (2000) The redemption of thalidomide: Standardizing the risk of birth defects. Social Studies of Science 30 (1): 41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, B.S. (2001) Disability and the sociology of the body. In: G. Albrecht, K. Seelman and M. Bury (eds.) Handbook of Disability Studies. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, pp. 252–266.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Union of the Physically Impaired Against Segregation (1975) Fundamental Principles of Disability. London: Union of the Physically Impaired Against Segregation.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abrams, T. Heidegger, subjectivity, disability. Subjectivity 8, 224–242 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1057/sub.2015.3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/sub.2015.3

Keywords

Navigation