Testing fundamental evolutionary hypotheses

https://doi.org/10.1016/S0022-5193(03)00099-7Get rights and content

Abstract

Sober and Steel (J. Theor. Biol. 218, 395–408) give important limits on the use of current models with sequence data for studying ancient aspects of evolution; but they go too far in suggesting that several fundamental aspects of evolutionary theory cannot be tested in a normal scientific manner. To the contrary, we show examples of how some alternatives to the theory of descent can be formulated in such a way that they lead to predictions that can be evaluated (and rejected). The critical factor is a logical formulation of the alternatives, even though not all possible alternatives can be tested simultaneously. Similarly, some of the limits using DNA sequence data can be overcome by other types of sequence derived characters. The uniqueness (or not) of the origin of life, though still difficult, is similarly amenable to the testing of alternative hypotheses.

Introduction

Sober and Steel, in a recent contribution to this journal (2002) critically examine the “Hypothesis of Common Ancestry”—that all life on earth traces back to a single common ancestor. They rightly point out that this is accepted within biology without rigorous testing, and they present theoretical results as to why the theory may be difficult to test. Our paper is a response to their claims, and illustrates how the Hypothesis of Common Ancestry has been tested in the past, and how difficult aspects (such as whether more than one ancestral lineage contributed to modern life) can be tested further. Our conclusion is that the Hypothesis of Common Ancestry is testable in principle, and it is not intrinsically different from other scientific theories. Nevertheless, Sober and Steel's paper is an important challenge; the reliability of current methods for building evolutionary trees from DNA sequence data is rightly criticized, as is the notion of a single (lineage-based) origin of all modern life. Thus questions analysed by Sober and Steel are fundamental in evolution—issues too often neglected. What are the expected limits of reconstructing evolutionary trees from sequences? How many ancestors are there for life on earth? Are there tests that distinguish between single- and multiple-origin hypotheses? We accept fundamental points in their article but secondary problems distract from the key issues, and the problems identified are solvable by good science. We focus on four main themes:

  • (a)

    the theory of descent leads to testable predictions,

  • (b)

    science does not claim to have absolute tests of hypotheses,

  • (c)

    the limits to phylogeny reconstruction depend on the model, and

  • (d)

    are there one, or more than one, common ancestors of life?

Sober and Steel suggest that the hypothesis of common ancestry is so ingrained in the minds of biologists that, when attempting to reconstruct the relationships that link a set of species, “the typical question is which tree is the best one, not whether there is a tree in the first place” (Sober and Steel, 2002). Historically, this is certainly not the case; many forms of relationship between species are possible (Fig. 1) and there is no a priori reason to assume a Steiner tree (Fig. 2). The concept of species having a continuity through time was only developed in the late 17th century (and only after continuous spontaneous generation of complex organisms was invalidated, see Farley, 1977). Higher life forms were no longer thought to “transmute” into different kinds during the lifetime of an individual. Many proposals relating these new entities (species) are shown in Fig. 1 and/or discussed in Bowler (1984). It took over 2000 years (from the time of the ancient Greeks), and over 150 years from the concept of permanent species, before a rooted Steiner tree was proposed by Charles Darwin. Some of the earlier ideas had common ancestors for subgroups, others did not. By providing a mechanism (natural selection, and descent with modification), Darwin could suggest a scientific model (pattern and mechanism) for species relationships. Darwin's evolutionary tree was neither obvious, nor easy to find. We claim that any alternative (as in Fig. 1) is testable individually, but that it is logically impossible to compare any one hypothesis against “all possible alternatives” (including those not yet specified). Rejecting all possible alternatives is logically equivalent to “proving” the theory.

Section snippets

The theory of descent leads to testable predictions

Sober and Steel consider three previous arguments that have been used to argue in favour of the hypothesis of Common Ancestry. Two, related to the origin of life and the genetic codes, are dealt with in Section 4. The third is an analysis of Penny et al. (1982) in which the theory of descent was tested by examining evolutionary relationships of mammals using five independent datasets. We argue here that the specific criticisms of our analysis by Sober and Steel do not affect the validity of the

Science does not claim to have absolute tests of hypotheses

Sober and Steel appear to assume that there must be a “definitive test” of any major scientific hypothesis; this is a fundamental question on the nature of science. However, science does not have absolute tests that “prove” a theory, we can never even think of all possible hypotheses. Could a better hypothesis for the structure of water be developed in 100 years? Similarly, there is no simple test that will prove the general theory of relativity once and for all. In reality, we may be able to

The limits to phylogeny reconstruction depend on the model

The conclusion of Sober and Steel (their Theorem 1) that current models of sequence evolution eventually limit phylogeny reconstruction is both important and fundamental; it has major consequences for studies of ancient divergences. Indeed, this subject has already moved away from confidence in the accuracy of ancient divergences inferred from a single gene, towards cautious phylogenetic interpretation. Examples such as Microsporidia have been recognized—these are a group of simple eukaryotic

Are there one, or more than one, common ancestors of life?

Sober and Steel claim “It is a central tenet of modern evolutionary theory that all living things now on earth trace back to a single common ancestor”, and suggest that it is impossible to establish whether more than one start-up contributed to modern life (Fig. 4d of Sober and Steel, 2002). We suggest it is possible to investigate the question scientifically, as follows. On biochemical grounds, it is argued that genetically encoded protein synthesis preceded DNA synthesis (and therefore DNA

Conclusions

Sober and Steel's (2002) considerations on the difficulties in studying ancient evolutionary events are both timely and welcome. We disagree on details and think that clarifying some unfocused aspects in the paper helps get to key issues. Their Theorem 1 equally well supports the idea that there is strong evolutionary information in sequences for testing the theory of descent—as long as it is well within the limits imposed by the theorem. Importantly, it is time, not evolution, that is

Acknowledgements

We thank the New Zealand Marsden Fund for support.

References (41)

  • J.M. Bujnicki

    Phylogeny of the restriction endonuclease-like superfamily inferred from comparison of protein structures

    J. Mol. Evol.

    (2000)
  • B. Chor et al.

    Multiple maxima of likelihood in phylogenetic treesan analytic approach

    Mol. Biol. Evol.

    (2000)
  • L.J. Collins et al.

    Use of RNA secondary structure for evolutionary relationshipsthe case of RNase P and RNase MRP

    J. Mol. Evol.

    (2000)
  • D. Cieslik

    Steiner Minimal Trees

    (1998)
  • D. Cieslik

    The Steiner Ratio

    (2001)
  • J. Farley

    The Spontaneous Generation Controversy from Descartes to Oparin

    (1977)
  • B. Halstead

    Poppergood philosophy, bad science?

    New Scientist

    (1980)
  • I.M. Henderson et al.

    Models for the evolution of influenza viruses

    Nature

    (1987)
  • F. Hoyle et al.

    Living Comets

    (1984)
  • F. Hoyle et al.

    The case for life as a cosmic phenomenon

    Nature

    (1986)
  • Cited by (17)

    View all citing articles on Scopus
    1

    Current address: Department of Molecular Biology and Functional Genomics, Stockholm University, SE 106 91, Stockholm, Sweden.

    View full text