The Hamiltonian view of social evolutionThe philosophy of social evolution,
Birch Jonathan
, Oxford University Press, Oxford (2017), p. 224, Hardcover, ISBN: 9780198733058

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2018.05.005Get rights and content

Introduction

In the obituary of her mentor Bill Hamilton, the American entomologist and evolutionary biologist Marlene Zuk wrote that the difference between Hamilton and everyone else was “not the quality of his ideas, but their sheer abundance” (Zuk, 2000). The proportion of his ideas that were actually any good was about the same as anyone else, “the difference between Bill and most other people was that he had a total of over one hundred ideas, with the result that at least ten of them were brilliant, whereas the rest of us have only four or five ideas as long as we live, with the result that none of them are”. Hamilton indeed had many good ideas. Over the years he made substantial contributions to the study of the origin of sex, sex ratios, genetic conflicts, and the evolution of senescence (Ågren, 2013). His best idea, and the one that bears his name, is about the evolution of social behaviour, especially altruism. Hamilton's Rule, and the related concepts of inclusive fitness and kin selection, have been the bedrock of the study of social evolution for the past half century (Fig. 1).

Jonathan Birch's recent book The philosophy of social of evolution is a superb exploration of philosophical implications of Hamilton's work. The philosophy of biology has a long-standing close relationship with evolutionary biology (maybe too close, some have argued (Pradeu, 2017)). Within evolutionary biology, the study of social evolution has been especially important. In a recent interview (Marshall, 2016), Elliot Sober, one of the founders of the field, described how he came to the philosophy of biology after being intrigued by William Wimsatt's review of George C. Williams's classic critique of group selection Adaptation and natural selection (Williams, 1966; Wimsatt, 1970). Pioneering books in the field of philosophy of biology, like Sober's The nature of selection (Sober, 1984), Elizabeth Lloyd's The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory (Lloyd, 1988), and Daniel Dennett's Darwin's dangerous idea (Dennett, 1995) all dedicated large chunks to the issues of causality, altruism and selfishness, and the levels of selection, raised by influential books on social evolution, especially Williams' Adaptation and natural selection and Richard Dawkins' The selfish gene (Dawkins, 1976). These authors belong to the finest tradition in the philosophy of science. They are deeply informed about the biology in question and their work contributed to the advancement of not only philosophy of biology but practice as well. Early on in The philosophy of social evolution (p. 9), Birch aligns his book to this tradition, to which Brandon (1990), Okasha (2006), and Godfrey-Smith (2009) also belong, and in my view the book fits squarely in that company.

In The philosophy of social Evolution Birch provides a comprehensive introduction to the conceptual foundations of the Hamiltonian view of social evolution, and a passionate defence of its enduring value in face of recent high profile criticism. The book is divided into two parts: Foundations (five chapters) and Extensions (three chapters). The early parts lay out the Hamiltonian approach to social evolution. In particular, Birch takes his starting point in David Queller's formulation of Hamilton's Rule (Queller, 1992), dubbed Hamilton's Rule General (HRG). This version is central to the arguments throughout the book and in this review essay I will therefore first outline HRG and its derivation. With this in place, I will then navigate through the intense disagreements that Hamilton's Rule, including HRG, generates and evaluate Birch's central argument of the book that HRG serves as an organizing framework for social evolution research under which we can compare and interpret more detailed causal models. The book also contains novel insights on group vs. kin selection models, conceptions of social fitness, and recent developments in the study of the origin of multicellularity and cultural evolution. These chapters are all stimulating, but in the interest of space I will spend the remainder of the review on what I take to be three of the most exciting implications of Hamilton's thinking raised by Birch: (1) the extension of Hamilton's Rule to mobile genetic elements, (2) maximization of inclusive fitness models and the idea of adaptation as organism design, and (3) the relationship between Hamilton's approaches to social behaviour and the gene's-eye view of evolution.

Section snippets

Defining Hamilton's rule

One of the most famous anecdotes in evolutionary biology involves the Orange Tree pub, once located around the corner from the University College London at the intersection of Gower Street and Euston Road.1 In it, sometime in the 1950s, JBS Haldane is meant to have proclaimed (after “calculating on the back of

Hamilton's rule as an organizing framework in social evolution

The heart of Birch's defence of the Hamiltonian approach to social evolution is the proposition that HRG can act as an organizing framework that allows us to identify common mechanisms in the origin of social behaviours. It offers a classificatory scheme and common vocabulary to translate between models, which means that more detailed theoretical models can be interpreted, compared, and contrasted in a unified way (Fig. 2).

Hamilton's Rule, however, has been subject to plenty of criticism. As I

Hamilton's rule and mobile genetic elements

In the first volume of his collected papers, Narrow roads of gene land, Hamilton (1996) reflected on the inevitability of genomic conflicts:

”Seemingly inescapable conflict within diploid organisms came to me as both a new agonizing challenge and at the same time as a release from a personal problem I had had all my life (…) Given my realization of an eternal disquiet within, couldn't I feel better about my own inability to be consistent in what I was doing, about indecision in matters ranging

Maximization of inclusive fitness and adaptation as organism design

Some of the most prolific of Hamilton's current defenders take the question of complex adaptation, the appearance of organisms as if they were designed, to be the central question of evolutionary biology (Gardner, 2009; Grafen, 2014; Kohn, 2004). I am in many ways sympathetic to this tendency. There really is something special about organisms. Subject to all known laws of physics, they are nonetheless different from any other physical entity. Organisms are what make biology unique as a distinct

Hamilton and the gene's-eye view of evolution

A chief insight of the Hamiltonian approach to social evolution is that individual organisms can affect the transmission of their genes both through personal reproductive success, but also through the success of close relatives (direct vs. indirect fitness; Fig. 2). Inclusive fitness provides a way to view this process from the perspective of the individual organism, but it can also be seen from a gene's-eye view (Dawkins, 1976). Indeed, Hamilton himself sometimes used this perspective. In his

Conclusion

In the introductory essay to the 50th anniversary edition of Thomas Kuhn's The structure of scientific revolutions, Ian Hacking describes biology as having replaced physics as science's “top dog”. Physics used to have a very productive relationship with philosophy (Schilpp, 2001), but has in recent years been characterized by high profile public animosity, perhaps best exemplified by the declaration by Stephen Hawking that “philosophy is dead” (Hawking & Mlodinow, 2010) and the ill-tempered

Acknowledgements

I thank Ellen Clarke for the invitation to write this review, and Andrew G. Clark and Carl Veller for comments and discussion on an earlier draft. I am supported by a fellowship from the Sweden-America Foundation.

References (75)

  • J.A. Ågren et al.

    Selfish genes

  • D. Albert

    On the origin of everything

    The New York Times Sunday Book Review

    (2012)
  • B. Allen et al.

    Limitations of inclusive fitness

    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America

    (2013)
  • R. Andersen

    Has physics made philosophy and religion obsolete

    The Atlantic

    (2012)
  • R. Axelrod et al.

    The evolution of cooperation

    Science

    (1981)
  • J. Birch

    Hamilton's rule and its discontents

    The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science

    (2014)
  • J. Birch

    Gene mobility and the concept of relatedness

    Biology and Philosophy

    (2014)
  • J. Birch

    The philosophy of social evolution

    (2017)
  • A.F.G. Bourke

    Principles of social evolution

    (2011)
  • R.N. Brandon

    Adaptation and environment

    (1990)
  • R.N. Brandon et al.

    The empirical nonequivalence of genic and genotypic models of selection: A (decisive) refutation of genic selectionism and pluralistic genic selectionism

    Philosophy of Science

    (2006)
  • A. Burt et al.

    Genes in conflict: The biology of selfish genetic elements

    (2006)
  • R. Dawkins

    The selfish gene

    (1976)
  • R. Dawkins

    The extended phenotype: The long reach of the gene

    (1982)
  • R. Dawkins

    Brief candle in the dark: My life in science

    (2015)
  • D.C. Dennett

    Darwin's dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life

    (1995)
  • A.W.F. Edwards

    R.A. Fisher's gene-centred view of evolution and the fundamental theorem of natural selection

    Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society

    (2014)
  • W.J. Ewens

    What is the gene trying to do?

    The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science

    (2010)
  • R.A. Fisher

    The genetical theory of natural selection

    (1930)
  • S.A. Frank

    Natural selection. IV. The Price equation

    Journal of Evolutionary Biology

    (2012)
  • A. Gardner

    Adaptation as organism design

    Biology Letters

    (2009)
  • A. Gardner et al.

    Capturing the superorganism: A formal theory of group adaptation

    Journal of Evolutionary Biology

    (2009)
  • A. Gardner et al.

    The genetical theory of kin selection

    Journal of Evolutionary Biology

    (2011)
  • P. Godfrey-Smith

    Darwinian populations and natural selection

    (2009)
  • A. Grafen

    The formal darwinism project: A mid-term report

    Journal of Evolutionary Biology

    (2007)
  • A. Grafen

    The formal darwinism project in outline

    Biology and Philosophy

    (2014)
  • D. Haig

    Genetic dissent and individual compromise

    Biology and Philosophy

    (2014)
  • Cited by (0)

    View full text