Skip to main content
Log in

Realism, Constructivism, and Intuitionism. Outline of an Unorthodox Hybrid Theory

  • Essay
  • Published:
Zeitschrift für Ethik und Moralphilosophie Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I will suggest an unorthodox hybrid theory of ethical justification that combines, on an ontological level, a realist approach with constructivist elements. On an epistemological level, the realist part of the theory will be squared with an intuitionist account. Eventually, the suggested hybrid theory will take the form of an intuitionist ethics of persons. I will start with briefly sketching the ontological shape of the relevant concept of person whereby I will extensively draw on Kant and endorse a realist reading of his ethical theory (2.). Subsequently, I will explain why and how constructivist elements must complement the picture (3.). Then, I will focus on the epistemological shape of the theory. In particular, I will suggest an intuitionist reading of Kant’s doctrine of “the fact of reason” (4.). Next, I will briefly comment on classical intuitionism and on Bernard William’s notion of convergence in ethics (5.). Subsequently, I will compare my approach with Robert Audi’s attempt to refine a Rossian type of intuitionism (6.). Finally, I will revisit the charge of dogmatism that has traditionally been raised against intuitionism (7.).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I have presented a more elaborate version of this account in Heinrichs 2013.

  2. In her Essay Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Moral Philosophy (2008), Korsgaard has refined her view. In particular, she highlights that the difference between realism and constructivism does not lie in their views about the truth-values of moral sentences. The difference remains, according to Korsgaard, in their understanding of the function of concepts.

  3. Quotations of Kant’s work are based on the editions indicated at the end of the paper, including the used abbreviations. Volume and page numbers refer to the Akademie-Ausgabe.

  4. Notably, this also means that non-human animals are not part of the “moral community” (at least if they do not qualify as persons). However, this does not necessarily imply that we do not have duties to non-human animals. In Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals Christine Korsgaard develops a constructivist argument which is compatible with the present approach. There she maintains: “In taking ourselves to be ends-in-ourselves we legislate that the natural good of a creature who matters to itself is the source of normative claims. Animal nature is an end-in-itself, because our own legislation makes it so. And that is why we have duties to the other animals.” (Korsgaard 2004, 106).

  5. Platts has coined a concise formula for characterizing moral realism: “[…] if a moral judgement is true, it is true in virtue of the (independently existing) real world, and is true in virtue of that alone.” (Platts 1979, 243).

  6. “It is impossible to think of anything at all in the world, or indeed even beyond it, that could be considered good without limitation except a good will.” (GMM, AA 4, 393).

  7. This may be taken merely as an epistemological claim. Then it is, of course, compatible with “strong” versions of ethical realism. If, however, our (present) understanding of the conditio humana partly constitutes material ethical principles, then they are constructions in a sense that is incompatible with “strong” ethical realism.

  8. A constructivist element can be found in the following passage: “The aim of ethical thought, however, is to help us to construct a world that will be our world, one in which we have a social, cultural, and personal life.” (Williams 1993, 111). A realist element is – as Korsgaard has correctly observed – noticeable in the phrase “best social world for human beings” (Williams 1993, 155).

  9. Sometimes Williams is seen as a proponent of a Neo-Aristotelian type of ethics. A number of passages in Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy are suitable to confirm this categorization. Williams himself, however, has spoken critically against this (Williams 1996, 213).

  10. “Contractual ethical theory cannot provide the basic method of understanding ethics, because it needs itself to be understood. If applied too widely, it does not give any, or enough, results; applied too narrowly, it insistently raises the question of the special conditions required to make it appropriate.” (Williams 1993, 104).

  11. Hans Joas has recently presented a historical and sociological study in which he suggests to consider universal human rights as the result of a specific process of sacralization, i. e. a history of sacralization of person (Joas 2011, 18). This is another way of describing the conversion in ethics. Moreover, Joas strives to keep the concepts of construction and discovery at an equal distance. This means that in metaethical terms he is committing himself neither to realism nor to constructivism (Joas 2011, 15). Nevertheless his study can be seen as a socio-historical support for the hybrid theory outlined here.

  12. This does not mean that there is no way of justifying or giving evidence for this fact. One could, for example, use a counterfactual conditional (“Suppose persons do not have dignity, then…”) to defend that persons have dignity. Such an analysis could, of course, be useful. It would, however, not lead to premises from which the proposition in question could be logically inferred.

References

  • Ameriks, Karl. 1981. Kant’s Deduction of Freedom and Morality. Journal of the History of Philosophy 19: 53-79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 2004. The Good in the Right. A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, Thomas. 2002. The Three Phases of Intuitionism. In Ethical Intuitionism. Re-evaluations. Ed. Philip Stratton-Lake, 92-112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Lewis White. 1961. Das Faktum der Vernunft: Zur Rechtfertigungsproblematik in der Ethik. Kant-Studien 52: 271-282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinrichs, Bert. 2013. Moralische Intuition und ethische Rechtfertigung. Eine Untersuchung zum ethischen Intuitionismus. Münster: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joas, Hans. 2011. Die Sakralität der Person. Eine neue Genealogie der Menschenrechte. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1804. Preisschrift über die Fortschritte der Metaphysik. In Akademie-Ausgabe, Bd. XX, 253-332 [=Preisschrift].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= MM].

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Critique of Practical Reason. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= CpR].

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= GMM].

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996a. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996b. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. 2004. Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Delivered at University of Michigan February 6, 2004. https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/k/korsgaard_2005.pdf (25.11.2018).

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. 2008. Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Moral Philosoohy. In The Constitution of Agency. Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. 302-326. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Luków, Pawel. 1993. The Fact of Reason. Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge. Kant-Studien 84: 204-221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, John Leslie. 1990. Ethics. Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1998. Two Sorts of Naturalism. In Mind, Value, and Reality. 167-197. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, George Edward. 1993. Principia Ethica. Revised Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowell-Smith, Patrick H. 1954. Ethics. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2010. Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity. Ethics 121: 116-147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platts, Mark. 1979. Ways of Meaning: An Introduction to a Philosophy of Language. London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, Harold Arthur. 2002. Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? In Moral Writings. 7‑20. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1980. Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory. Journal of Philosophy 77: 515-572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, Henry S. 1990. Specifying Norms as a Way to resolve Concrete Ethical Problems. Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 279-310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, William David. 2002. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schmucker, Josef. 1997. Der Formalismus und die materialen Zweckprinzipien in der Ethik Kants. In Kant. Analysen – Probleme – Kritik, Bd. III. Ed. Hariolf Oberer, 99-156. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, Henry. 1981. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter F. 1949. Ethical Intuitionism. Philosophy 24: 23-33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturma, Dieter. 1997. Philosophie der Person. Die Selbstverhältnisse von Subjektivität und Moralität. Paderborn: Schöningh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturma, Dieter. 2008. Die Natur der Freiheit: Integrativer Naturalismus in der theoretischen und praktischen Philosophie. Philosophisches Jahrbuch 115: 385-396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturma, Dieter; Heinrichs, Bert. 2015. Bioethik – Hauptströmungen, Methoden und Disziplinen. In Handbuch Bioethik. Ed. Dieter Sturma und Bert Heinrichs, 1‑8. Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1993. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 1996. History, morality, and the test of reflection. In The Sources of Normativity. Ed. Christine M. Korsgaard, 210-218. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Allen W. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bert Heinrichs.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heinrichs, B. Realism, Constructivism, and Intuitionism. Outline of an Unorthodox Hybrid Theory. ZEMO 1, 263–277 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42048-018-0019-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42048-018-0019-7

Keywords

Navigation