Skip to main content
Log in

Economic Rationality and a Moral Science of Business Ethics

  • Published:
Philosophy of Management Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article examines the relationship between economic rationality and the possibility of a moral science of business ethics. The purpose of this inquiry is to consider whether a universal and non-controversial moral science of business ethics can be defined satisfactorily, and linked to economic rationality of managers and other stakeholders of firms operating in market economies. Economic rationality connotes economic efficiency, meaning a strictly instrumental maximization of actor utility from limited resources. This rationality is a universal and value free (or value neutral) axiom: actors should and generally will be rationally efficient. Utilitarianism accepting aggregation across values is the moral framework associated with market exchange. Business ethics is about normative valuation of motives, actions, and consequences. This article argues that the common foundation across relevant ethical frameworks – moral common sense, Kantianism, virtue theory, religion as a belief system, and utilitarianism – is a first or axiomatic principle of no harm without acceptable justification. A moral science of business ethics proceeds from this no harm axiom.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hartman (2015) explains arguments as to why psychology is not a science, and how to make psychology a science. Many academic psychologists presumably view themselves as scientists; and there is scientific method in psychological research.

  2. Behavioral economics and behavioral finance, drawing on psychology, investigate the bounds on economic rationality in human behavior in markets (see Chen et al. 2006).

  3. Windsor (2015) argues that as distinct from studying prescriptive philosophy (whether scientific, professional, or moral), managers develop personal operating philosophies focused on career survival and advancement within firms.

  4. J. S. Mill, On Liberty (1859) and the 1789 “Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen” constrain the natural right to liberty to a condition of no harm or injury to others. This constraint might define ethical egoism, aligned with utilitarianism in competitive markets. Ethical egoism is not a justification for harm to others.

  5. Belgium regulates reduction in force, for example, in ways that can make such reduction costly for a company.

  6. In Pareto efficiency, a change from the status quo benefiting one actor is non-controversial if there is no harm to any other actor. Such a condition is proof of an efficiency improvement. In contrast, Kaldor-Hicks efficiency involves a change from the status quo benefiting some and harming others: the change might be defensible if the gains are greater than the harms, such that the gainers could hypothetically compensate the losers. Justifications are the essence of the Kaldor-Hicks criterion.

  7. One can compare Smith’s definition to W. H. Vanderbilt and J. P. Morgan. W. H. Vanderbilt (1821–85) allegedly expressed to a reporter that “The public be damned!” Quoted in J. R. Daughen and P. Binzen, The Wreck of the Penn Central (Beard Books, 1999), pp. 34–35. Vanderbilt denied making the statement; and more certainly the profanity. J. P. Morgan (1837–1913) allegedly expressed to a reporter that “I owe the public nothing.” Quoted in New York World (11 May 1901) during the Northern Pacific “corner.” S. Gittelman, J. P. Morgan and the Transportation Kings (University Press of America, 1912), at p. 49, citing C. Lewis, The House of Morgan (1930). “Alleged” means that the statements might or might not have been made, depending on one’s view of journalistic standards of the time.

  8. The “Adam Smith Problem” concerns whether The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) and The Wealth of Nations (1776) conflict or are compatible in vital aspects (Paganelli 2008). The present article presumes sufficient compatibility.

  9. “Moral imagination refers to the ability to perceive that a web of competing economic relationships is, at the same time, a web of moral relationships. Developing moral imagination means becoming sensitive to ethical issues in business decision making, but it also means searching out places where people are likely to be hurt by decision or behavior of managers. This moral imagination is a necessary first step, but because of prevailing methods of evaluating managers on bottom-line results, it is extremely challenging” (Werhane 1999: 5). “One of the most consistent findings is that good people do bad things. We’re not talking about an issue of character; that oversimplifies matters. Good people do horrendous things in the workplace because they don’t see the situation as an ethical dilemma. They see it as a business problem to be solved.” – Professor Arthur Brief (Director of the Burkenroad Institute for the Study of Ethics and Leadership in Management, Tulane U.), quoted by Teuke (2004: 58).

  10. Banfield (1958) reported for a South Italian village practice interpreted as “amoral familism” which he defined as morality within the family and absence of citizenship toward others. Miller (1974) reported no empirical support for Banfield’s interpretation of the conditions in a South Italian village.

  11. Wilk (1993) points out that the debate over whether human nature is self-interested or altruistic dates back to Hobbes and Locke. He provides the three models of motivation - selfish, social, and moral - referenced here. Wilk argues that the problem of human nature should be recast from philosophical to empirical.

  12. Frankena cites Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (London, Macmillan, 1907).

  13. “When Mill pointed out that economics had no ultimate solution to the problem of distribution, that society might do with the fruits of its toil as it saw fit, he introduced into the mechanical calculus of the market a conflicting calculus of moral judgment. … the assertion of independent conscious decision about the ends we desired from the economic process …” (Heilbroner 1953: 307).

  14. John J. Fernandes, President & CEO, AACSB International (retiring), “Looking Back on a Legacy,” BizEd (February 26, 2015), describes the 2013 AACSB revised accreditation standards (adopted April 8, 2013 and revised January 31, 2015) for business programs (Standard 9 – curriculum content) as follows: “Now, we want schools not only to help their students develop a strong sense of ethics, but also to make sure students understand social responsibility and sustainability—of the planet, of the organization, and of society. Someone could be highly ethical without being socially responsible or committed to having a positive effect on society.”

  15. “Today’s employees think their number one objective is to be thought of as decent people doing quality work. We all have a much greater consciousness of ethical issues. With the [Martin Marietta ethics] program, you are less likely to get into trouble, and you feel better about yourself. The [ethics] program has also helped us compete. We have been afforded opportunities because we were trusted.” – Norman R. Augustine (CEO of Martin Marietta, later CEO of Lockheed Martin), quoted in Paine, Choy, & Santoro, “Martin Marietta: Managing Corporate Ethics (A),” HBS Case 9-393-016 (1992, revised 081704), p. 1.

  16. July 4, 1938 letter to Roy Harrod, #787, http://economia.unipv.it/~dbesomi/edition/editionstuff/rfh.346.htm

  17. July 10, 1938 letter to Roy Harrod, #791 http://economia.unipv.it/harrod/edition/editionstuff/rfh.34a.htm#36302

  18. J. R. Weinstein authored Adam Smith’s Pluralism: Rationality, Education and the Moral Sentiments. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2013. See review by Smith (2014).

  19. Gert (2011): “My definition of what I take to be the universal normative sense of “morality,” requires a normative sense of “rationality,” such that no moral agent would ever advise anyone for whom he is concerned, including himself, to act irrationally. The concept of rationality described earlier satisfies this condition because no moral agent would ever advise anyone for whom he cares, including himself, to act in any way that harms himself with no compensating benefit to anyone.”

  20. Spinoza (1677) developed a systematic approach to ethics by geometrical demonstration, drawing on Euclid and Descartes. The present study is narrowly focused on business ethics.

  21. Strine is Chief Justice of the Delaware Supreme Court (2014–2026) and previously Chancellor of the Delaware Court of Chancery,

  22. George W. Merck, CEO, Merck & Co. (during 1929–57): “We try never to forget that medicine is for the people. It is not for the profits. The profits follow, and if we have remembered that, they have never failed to appear. The better we have remembered it, the larger they have been.” Address to the Medical College of Virginia, Richmond (December 1, 1950); quoted in J. Collins and J. I. Porras, Built to Lastn Successful Habits of Visionary Companies (New York: HarperBusiness, 1994), p. 48. Steve Jobs, CEO, Apple: “My passion has been to build an enduring company where people were motivated to make great products. Everything else was secondary. Sure, it was great to make a profit, because that was what allowed you to make great products. But the products, not the profits, were the motivation. It’s a subtle difference, but it ends up meaning everything. The people you hire, who gets promoted, what you discuss in meetings.” Told to biographer Walter Isaacson, quoted in R. Foroohar, “What Would Steve Do? Jobs was a jerk, but his leadership lesson is more about product than personality,” Time (27 February 2012), p. 18.

  23. “I mean not, however, by anything which I have here said, to throw any odious imputation upon the general character of the servants of the East India Company, and much less upon that of any particular persons. It is the system of government, the situation in which they are placed, that I mean to censure, not the character of those who have acted in it. They acted as their situation naturally directed, and they who have clamoured the loudest against them would probably not have acted better themselves.” Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (1776), Book Four, Ch. 7, Part 3.

References

  • Arrow, K.J. 1987. Economic theory and the hypothesis of rationality. In The New Palgrave: A dictionary of economics (first edition).

  • Atkinson, A.B. 2009. Economics as a moral science. Economica New Series 76(Supplement 1: Robbins’s Essay at 75): 791–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Backhouse, R.E., and S.G. Medema. 2009. Defining economics: The long road to acceptance of the Robbins definition. Economica 76(302): 805–820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banfield, E.C. 1958. The moral basis of a backward society. Glencoe: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, M.L., and R.M. Salomon. 2012. Does it pay to be really good? Addressing the shape of the relationship between social and financial performance. Strategic Management Journal 33(11): 1304–1320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, D.P. 2010. Morally-motivated self-regulation. American Economic Review 100(4): 1299–1329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W.J. 1976. Smith vs. Marx on business morality and the social interest. American Economist 20(2): 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M.H., and F. Gino. 2012. Behavioral ethics: Toward a deeper understanding of moral judgment and dishonesty. Annual Review of Law and the Social Sciences 8: 85–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M.H., and J.D. Greene. 2010. In favor of clear thinking: Incorporating moral rules into a wise cost-benefit analysis. Perspectives on Psychological Science 5(2): 209–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bazerman, M.H., and A.E. Tenbrunsel. 2011. Ethical breakdowns: Good people often let bad things happen. Why? Harvard Business Review 89(4): 58–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. 1976a. Altruism, egoism, and genetic fitness: Economics and sociobiology. Journal of Economic Literature 14(3): 817–826.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. 1976b. The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, M.W. 1997. The complete moral person: Anatomy and formation. In Moral issues in psychology: Personalist contributions to selected problems, ed. J.M. DuBois, 11–41. Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, M.W. 2002. The science of character development. In Bringing in a new era in character education, ed. W. Damon, 43–63. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, M.W., and M.C. Bier. 2004. Research-based character education. Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 591(1): 72–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, K.E. 1969. Economics as a moral science. American Economic Review 59(1): 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brekke, K.A., S. Kverndokk, and K. Nyborg. 2003. An economic model of moral motivation. Journal of Public Economics 87(9–10): 1967–1983.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J.A., and W.R. Forster. 2013. CSR and stakeholder theory: A tale of Adam Smith. Journal of Business Ethics 112(2): 301–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, M.K., V. Lakshminarayanan, and L.R. Santos. 2006. How basic are behavioral biases? Evidence from capuchin monkey trading behavior. Journal of Political Economy 114(3): 517–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coase, R.H. 1960. The problem of social cost. Journal of Law and Economics 3: 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coase, R.H. 1976. Adam Smith’s view of man. Journal of Law and Economics 19(3): 529–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. 2011. The inescapability of a minimal version of normative stakeholder theory. In Stakeholder theory: Impact and prospects, ed. R. Phillips, 30–39. Cheltenham and Northampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., and T.W. Dunfee. 1994. Toward a unified conception of business ethics: Integrative social contracts theory. Academy of Management Review 19(2): 252–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., and T.W. Dunfee. 1995. Integrative social contracts theory: A communitarian conception of economic ethics. Economics and Philosophy 11(1): 85–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., and T.W. Dunfee. 1999. Ties that bind: A social contracts approach to business ethics. Boston: Harvard University Business School Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunfee, T.W. 2000. Corporate governance in a market with morality. Duke Law Review 62(3): 129–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elhauge, E. 2005. Sacrificing corporate profits in the public interest. New York University Law Review 80(3): 733–869.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W.K. 1974. Sidgwick and the dualism of practical reason. The Monist 58(3): 449–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1953 (1970). The methodology of positive economics. In Essays in positive economics: 3–43. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Friedman, M. 1970. The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. The New York Times Magazine.

  • Gardner, H. 2007. The ethical mind: A conversation with psychologist Howard Gardner. Harvard Business Review 85(3): 51–56. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, H., M. Csikszentmihalyi, and W. Damon. 2001. Good work: When excellence and ethics meet. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentile, M.C. 2012. Giving voice to values: How to speak your mind when you know what’s right. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gert, B. 2011. The definition of morality. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/

  • Ghoshal, S. 2005. Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education 4(1): 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S., and C.A. Bartlett. 1997. A new moral contract: Companies as value-creating institutions. In The individualized corporation: A fundamentally new approach to management – great companies are defined by purpose, process, and people: Ch. 10, 273–299. New York: Harper Business.

  • Gino, F., L.L. Shu, and M.H. Bazerman. 2010. Nameless + Harmless = Blameless: When seemingly irrelevant factors influence judgment of (un)ethical behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 111(2): 102–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K.E. 1983. Ethical frameworks for management. Harvard Business School 9: 384–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K.E. 1984. Some avenues for ethical analysis in general management. Harvard Business School 9: 383–007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, J.R., C.R. Harvey, and S. Rajgopal. 2005. The economic implications of corporate financial reporting. Journal of Accounting and Economics 40(1–3): 3–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruchy, A.G. 1949. J. M. Keynes’ conception of economic science. Southern Economic Journal 15(3): 249–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerrera, F. 2009. Welch condemns share price focus. Financial Times.

  • Hartman, E.M. 2015. Rationality in management theory and practice: An Aristotelian perspective. Philosophy of Management 14(1): 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heilbroner, R.L. 1953. The worldly philosophers: The lives, times, and ideas of the great economic thinkers. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, L., and S. Wetlaufer. 1998. Leadership when there is no one to ask: An interview with Eni’s Franco Bernabè. Harvard Business Review 76(4): 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, H., P. Lorange, and J. Sheth. 2013. The business school in the twenty-first century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, S. 2004. The origins of Lionel Robbins’s essay on the nature and significance of economic science. History of Political Economy 36(3): 413–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutt, W.H. 1936. Economists and the public: A study of competition and opinion. London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutt, W.H. 1940. The concept of consumers’ sovereignty. The Economic Journal 50(197): 66–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M.C. 2002. Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Business Ethics Quarterly 12(2): 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanter, R. 2005. What theories do audiences want? Exploring the demand side. Academy of Management Learning & Education 4(1): 93–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. H. 1922. Ethics and the economic interpretation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 22: 454–481. Reprinted in F. H. Knight, The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays: 19–40. New York: Harper & Brothers 1935.

  • Knight, F. H. 1923. The ethics of competition. Quarterly Journal of Economics 37: 579–624. Reprinted in F. H. Knight, The ethics of competition and other essays: 41–75. New York: Harper & Brothers, 1935.

  • Lad, L.J., and C.B. Caldwell. 2009. Collaborative standards, voluntary codes and industry self-regulation. Journal of Corporate Citizenship 35(Fall): 67–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • London, J. 1904. The sea-wolf. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macey, J.R. 2008. A close read of an excellent commentary on Dodge v. Ford. Virginia Law & Business Review 3(1): 177–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, O. 2000. What is Sidgwick’s dualism of practical reason? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81(3): 273–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R.A. 1974. Are familists amoral? A test of Banfield’s amoral familism hypothesis in a South Italian village. American Ethnologist 1(3): 515–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, T.V. 1997. If Aristotle ran general motors: The new soul of business. New York: Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. 1999. Judging other cultures: The case of genital mutilation. In Sex and social justice: 118–129. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Paganelli, M.P. 2008. The Adam Smith problem in reverse: Self-interest in The Wealth of Nations and The Theory of Moral Sentiments. History of Political Economy 40(2): 365–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paganelli, M.P. 2010. The moralizing role of distance in Adam Smith: The Theory of Moral Sentiments as possible praise of commerce. History of Political Economy 42(3): 425–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persky, J. 1993. Retrospectives: Consumer sovereignty. Journal of Economic Perspectives 7(1): 183–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piper, T., M.C. Gentile, and S.D. Parks. 1993. Can ethics be taught? Perspectives, challenges, and approaches at Harvard Business School. Boston: Harvard Business School.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, R.A. 2009. A failure of capitalism: The crisis of’08 and the descent into depression. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. 1995. Moral preferences, moral constraints, and self-serving biases. Berkeley: Department of Economics, University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. 1932. An essay on the nature and significance of economic science. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S.A., R.W. Westerfield, and J. Jaffe. 2002. Corporate finance, 6th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill Irwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachdeva, S., R. Illiev, and D.L. Medin. 2009. Sinning saints and saintly sinners: The paradox of moral self-regulation. Psychological Science 20(4): 523–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S.V. 1999. Moral overridingness and moral subjectivism. Ethics 109(4): 772–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1992. Altruism and economics. Eastern Economic Journal 18(1): 73–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skapinker, M. 2005. It is time to knock shareholder value off its pedestal. Financial Times, Business Life: 16.

  • Smith, C. 2014. Review of Jack Russell Weinstein’s Adam Smith’s pluralism: rationality, education, and the moral sentiments. New Haven : Yale University Press, 2013. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 7(2): 162–169. http://ejpe.org/pdf/7-2-br-4.pdf

  • Sonenshein, S. 2007. The role of construction, intuition, and justification in responding to ethical issues at work: The sensemaking-intuition model. Academy of Management Review 32(4): 1022–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. 1677. Ethics, demonstrated in geometrical order (Ethica, ordine geometrico demonstrata).

  • Stout, L.A. 2008. Why we should stop teaching Dodge v. Ford. Virginia Law & Business Review 3(1): 164–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strine Jr., L.E. 2012. Our continuing struggle with the idea that for-profit corporations seek profit. Wake Forest Law Review 47: 135–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strine Jr., L.E. 2014. Making it easier for directors to “do the right thing? Harvard Business Law Review 4(2): 235–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teuke, M. R. 2004. Teach the right thing: Debating the place of ethics in the business curriculum. Continental: 57–59.

  • Thomas, H., P. Lorange, and J. Sheth. 2013. The business school in the twenty-first century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Vanberg, V. J. 2006. Rationality, rule-following and emotions: On the economics of moral preferences. http://www.indiana.edu/~workshop/colloquia/materials/papers/vanberg_paper.pdf

  • Vanberg, V. J. 2012. Rational choice, preferences over actions and rule-following behavior. In Philosophy of economics, eds. U. Mäki, D.M. Gabbay, P. Thagard, and J. Woods : 505–530. Volume in Handbook of the philosophy of science. Amsterdam: Elsevier BV.

  • Viner, J. 1938. Book review: Economists and the Public: A Study of Competition and Opinion by W. H. Hutt. Journal of Political Economy 46(4): 571–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walker, L.J. 2002. Moral exemplarity. In Bringing in a new era in character education, ed. W. Damon, 65–83. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warmack, L. 2003. Emphasizing ethics: Colleges and Universities are revisiting the fundamentals of ethics in business courses. St. Paul Pioneer Press, C1 (Business).

  • Weinstein, J.R. 2015. Adam Smith (1723–1790). Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/smith/ (accessed 20 March 2015).

  • Wellman, C. 1963. The ethical implications of cultural relativity. The Journal of Philosophy 60(7): 169–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, C. 1975. Ethical disagreement and objective truth. American Philosophical Quarterly 12(3): 211–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wempe, B. 2008. Integrative social contract theory (ISCT). In R.W. Kolb (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Business Ethics and Society 3: 1140–1141.

  • Werhane, P. 1999. Moral imagination and management decision making. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A.N. 1933. Foresight. Adventure of ideas: Ch. VI, 110–126. London: Macmillan. Originally a 1931 lecture by Whitehead at the Harvard Business School, published as preface to W. B. Donham, Business Adrift, New York: McGraw Hill, 1931.

  • Wilk, R. 1993. Altruism and self-interest: Towards an anthropological theory of decision making. Research in Economic Anthropology 14: 191–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J.Q. 1989. Adam Smith on business ethics. California Management Review 32(1): 59–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, D. 2013a. A typology of moral exemplars in business. In Moral saints and moral exemplars, research in ethical issues in organizations, eds. M. Schwartz and H. Harris, Vol. 10: 63–95. Bingley: Emerald Group Publishing.

  • Windsor, D. 2013b. Corporate social responsibility and irresponsibility: A positive theory approach. Journal of Business Research 66(10): 1937–1944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, D. 2015. Philosophy for managers and philosophy of managers: Turf, reputation, coalition. Philosophy of Management 14(1): 17–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, I.C., and S. Shaffakat. 2014. The values of “insightfully aware” leaders. http://knowledge.insead.edu/leadership-management/the-values-of-insightfully-aware-leaders-3591?utm_source=INSEAD+Knowledge&utm_campaign=0b5f3e2f5f-2_Oct_mailer10_2_2014&utm_medium=email&utm_term=0_e079141ebb-0b5f3e2f5f-249961417

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Duane Windsor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Windsor, D. Economic Rationality and a Moral Science of Business Ethics. Philosophy of Management 15, 135–149 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-015-0021-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40926-015-0021-7

Keywords