Skip to main content
Log in

Attributionism and Moral Responsibility for Implicit Bias

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Implicit intergroup biases have been shown to impact social behavior in many unsettling ways, from disparities in decisions to “shoot” black and white men in a computer simulation to unequal gender-based evaluations of résumés and CVs. It is a difficult question whether, and in what way, agents are responsible for behaviors affected by implicit biases. I argue that in paradigmatic cases agents are responsible for these behaviors in the sense that the behavior is “attributable” to them. That is, behaviors affected by implicit biases reflect upon who one is as a moral agent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For review see Greenwald et al. (2009), Jost et al. (2009), and Nosek et al. (2007a). For a critique of measures of implicit bias, see Oswald et al. (2013); see Greenwald et al. (2015) for reply. For a more detailed introduction to implicit bias, see Brownstein (2015).

  2. See Valian (2004) on the “accumulation of advantage.” See also Greenwald et al. (2015).

  3. One possibility is that no one in particular—no individual—is responsible for implicit bias. By this I mean that implicit bias is an effect of legacies of historical inequality, patterns of residential and occupational segregation, discriminatory laws and political policies, and so on. There are multiple ways to render this “institutional” approach to understanding implicit bias. For examples, see Anderson (2010) and Haslanger (2015). I am sympathetic to these approaches, although I think there are significant reasons to examine implicit bias in terms of individuals too, at least alongside social-institutional considerations. For a response to the institutional critique of research on implicit bias, see Madva (ms a). One aim of this paper is to show why the question of individual moral responsibility for implicit bias matters.

  4. Tamar Gendler’s (2008a,b) influential account of implicit attitudes as “aliefs” argues that these mental states are responsible for the management of much of “moment-to-moment” behavior.

  5. See, for example, Hardin and Banaji (2013).

  6. As Levy (2014) and Mallon (forthcoming) put it, terms of moral assessment are connected to folk psychological concepts like “belief.” So one reason the question of moral responsibility for implicit bias is important is because of the way in which implicit biases are, and are not, belief-like. Levy (2014) argues that implicit biases are neither beliefs nor mere associations; because of this, neither blame nor excuse for them is appropriate. The view I develop here can be understood as (mostly) accepting Levy’s account of the psychological structure of implicit attitudes, but rejecting the claim that neither blame nor excuse is appropriate. For discussion of whether implicit biases are beliefs, see Brownstein (2015), Gendler (2008a,b), Levy (2012, 2014), Madva (2012, forthcoming), Mandelbaum (2015), and Schwitzgebel (2010).

  7. See Faucher (forthcoming), Glasgow (forthcoming); Holroyd (2012); Kelly and Roedder (2008); Levy (2012, 2014, forthcoming); Madva (2012, ms b); Saul (2013); Sie and Vorst Vader-Bours (forthcoming); Washington and Kelly (forthcoming); and Zheng (forthcoming).

  8. To my knowledge, those few are Zheng (forthcoming), Glasgow (forthcoming), and, briefly, Smith (2012). Faucher (forthcoming) discusses related issues. For key accounts of attributionism, see Arpaly (2004), Frankfurt (1971), Hieronymi (2008), Jaworska (2007), Scanlon (1998), Sher (2009), Shoemaker (2003), Smith (2005, 2008, 2012), Sripada (2010, 2015), and Watson (1975, 1996).

  9. Sripada (2010) quotes from Hume’s Treatise: “Actions are by their very nature temporary and perishing; and where they proceed not from some cause in the characters and disposition of the person, who perform’d them, they infix not themselves upon him, and can neither redound to his honour, if good, nor infamy, if evil, the action itself may be blameable; it may be contrary to all the rules of morality and religion: But the person is not responsible for it: and as it proceeded from nothing in him, that is durable or constant, and leaves nothing of that nature behind it, ‘tis impossible he can, upon its account, become the object of punishment or vengeance” (Treatise, bk. 11, Pt. 111, sec. 2).

  10. I entirely sidestep the question of whether this emerging picture of the mind threatens free will.

  11. I am indebted to Chandra Sripada (2015) for this way of dividing up the central questions facing attributionism.

  12. As will be clear, this is a different sense of caring than the more familiar one developed by Frankfurt (1988).

  13. I focus on responsibility for behavior rather than for attitudes simply because I find the former to be more tractable. In future work I hope to consider the question of responsibility for implicit bias itself. For discussion of responsibility for attitudes, see Smith (2005, 2008, 2012). Also see Zheng (forthcoming) for discussion of the conditions under which an implicit bias is implicated in behavior, as it relates to questions about moral responsibility.

  14. Perhaps deep down one can be fundamentally conflicted, as I briefly discuss in §7.1, but this possibility is not usually reflected in the experimental literature on the deep self. Thanks to Alex Madva and Susanna Siegel for pushing me to clarify this. An important question for future research is whether and how the account I develop here integrates with experimental approaches to folk conceptions of the deep self.

  15. In their influential 2008 paper, for example, Kelly and Roedder write, “the IAT requires subjects to make snap judgments that must be made quickly, and thus without moderating influence of introspection and deliberation and often without conscious intention. Biases revealed by an IAT are often thought to implicate relatively automatic processes” (525). Jennifer Saul (2012, 244) describes implicit biases as “unconscious tendencies to automatically associate concepts with one another.” And elsewhere I have called implicit biases “relatively unconscious and relatively automatic features of prejudiced judgment and social behavior” (Brownstein 2015).

  16. An immediate objection stems from the fact that a good number of our explicit attitudes—in the philosophical sense of attitudes—fail to be sensitive to what we think to be true or good. The large literature on belief perseverance is one testament to this (see Anderson and Lindsay (1998) for review). My view—discussed in more depth elsewhere (Brownstein, M. Manuscript, The Implicit Mind (Unpublished))—is that explicit attitudes like beliefs have the possibility of being irrational because part of their function is to respect certain basic rules of rationality (e.g., to be sensitive to logical operators like negation, to be “inferentially promiscuous,” and so). As I suggest below, implicit attitudes don’t have this function. They don’t play the game of rationality. Thus they are arational, not irrational. Thanks to Susanna Siegel for pushing me to clarify this point.

  17. The rest of this paragraph, as well as the paragraph following, are adapted from Brownstein (forthcoming).

  18. Of course, a person will have many associations with the name Malcolm X, just as they will with virtually any cue. APE offers a complex account of which associations will be activated in a given context. This account is largely in keeping with connectionist models of cognition.

  19. A note on potential terminological confusion: APE focuses on what it calls propositional processes, not propositional states (i.e., not mental states with propositional structure, the kind with which philosophers of mind are typically concerned). For more, see Brownstein (2015).

  20. But note that stereotypes such as “athletic” can be positive in some contexts but negative in others. “Athletic” is often associated with “unintelligent,” for example. On the relationship between implicit stereotypes and evaluation, see Amodio and Devine (2006), Holroyd and Sweetman (forthcoming), and Madva and Brownstein (ms).

  21. Notably, Bodenhausen and Gawronski (2014, 957) write that the “distinction between associative and propositional evaluations is analogous to the distinction between ‘alief’ and belief in recent philosophy of epistemology.”

  22. Although note that Levy (2014) does not endorse an associative picture of implicit attitudes. See Mandelbaum (2015) for a contrasting view.

  23. Indulge me in a brief bit of textual interpretation. The fact that the author says he gets angry about slut-shaming, stereotype threat, or “whatever is the affront du jour” strikes me as dismissive of gender prejudice, as if slut-shaming and stereotype threat are passing fads. This seems to be a nice example of unintended bias being expressed in writing. This is striking, since it’s in an essay about unintended biases.

  24. See, respectively, Frankfurt (1971), Watson (1975), and Scanlon (1998).

  25. In the same vein as what I said in §1 with respect to attributionism in general, my central aim is not to promote care-based approaches as such. So I will not offer arguments for the superiority of the care-based approach to these other attributionist theories. I do hope, however, to strengthen the case for a care-based account by showing how it can make sense of responsibility for BEIB.

  26. Different theorists place emphasis on these features in different ways. I draw largely upon Jaworska (1999, 2007), Shoemaker (2003, 2013), and Sripada (2010, 2015), although the synthesis I present in this section is my own.

  27. Sripada’s (2015) closely related view is that “cares involve a complex syndrome of motivational, commitmental, evaluative, and affective dispositions.”

  28. For a dissenting view on the role of consciousness in caring, see Levy (2011).

  29. A slightly stronger claim than that cares and explicit judgments are typically correlated is that caring about something disposes an agent to judge the thing to be good (Sripada 2015). Also, there is another potential point of disagreement between theorists about cares having to do with just how fundamental cares are. One possibility is that cares, alongside evaluative judgments, are inherently internal (Jaworska 2007, 559, fn 88). Another possibility is that cares are the source of all states that are internal in the relevant sense (Shoemaker 2003).

  30. Most researchers writing on attributionism accept that a causal connection between an agent’s identity-grounding states and her attitudes/actions is a necessary condition for reflection (e.g., Levy 2011; Scanlon 1998; Sripada 2015). Note also two points of clarification on Levy’s (2011) terminology. First, he identifies a set of propositional attitudes that play the same role in his discussion as what I have been calling cares. That is, he simply refers to an agent’s identity-grounding states as “attitudes.” Second, Levy distinguishes between an action “expressing,” “reflecting,” and “matching” at attitude (or, as I would put it, an action or attitude expressing, reflecting, and matching an agent’s cares). The crucial one of these relations is expression. It is analogous to what I will call “reflection.”

  31. I am grateful to Sripada (p.c.) for this illustration.

  32. To answer this question, Sripada (2015) proposes the “motivational support account of expression.” Roughly, an action is said to reflect upon one’s deep self, on this view, if and only if the motive expressed in the action is one of the agent’s cares. A motive is said to be expressed in an action if and only if the motive exerts influence of sufficient strength on the agent’s “action-directing psychological mechanisms.”

  33. Levy (2011, 252–253) makes a similar point in the case of omissions: “patterns of lapses are good evidence about agents’ attitudes for reasons to do with the nature of probability. From the fact that there is, say, a 50 % chance per hour of my recalling that it is my friend’s birthday if it is true that I care for him or her and if internal and external conditions are suitable for my recalling the information (if I am not tired, stressed, or distracted; my environment is such that I am likely to encounter cues that prompt me to think of my friend and of his or her birthday, and so on), and the fact that I failed to recall her birthday over, say, a 6-h stretch, we can conclude that one of the following is the case: either I failed during that stretch to care for him or her or my environment was not conductive to my thinking of him or her or I was tired, stressed, distracted, or what have you, or I was unlucky. But when the stretch of time is much longer, the probability that I failed to encounter relevant cues is much lower; if it is reasonable to think that during that stretch there were extended periods of time in which I was in a fit state to recall the information, then I would have had to have been much unluckier to have failed to recall the information if I genuinely cared for my friend (Levy 2011). The longer the period of time, and the more conducive the internal and external environment, the lower the probability that my failure to recall is a product of my bad luck rather than of my failure to care sufficiently. This is part of the reason why ordinary people care whether an action is out of character for an agent: character, as manifested in patterns of response over time, is good evidence of the agent’s evaluative commitments in a way that a single lapse cannot be.”

  34. See footnote #20.

  35. For some data, see Dunham et al. (2013) and Devine et al. (2012).

  36. See Redford & Ratliff (ms) for data suggesting that participant judgments about what agents have an obligation to foresee (rather than what they do in fact foresee) mediates their responsibility judgments for BEIB. Note also that Cameron and colleagues report that the 4 items on the scale had an “acceptable” internal consistency (Cronbach’s α = .65). This means that participants’ answers to the 4 items on the scale were somewhat, but not strongly, correlated with each other, and that the scale may in fact reflect multiple distinct concepts.

  37. Shoemaker (2003, 97) discusses why only nonwanton actions reflect cares. See also Lippert-Rasmussen (2003) for discussion of “whim” cases in which agents don’t seem to have any significant attitudes toward their actions.

  38. See also Shoemaker (2003, 93–94) and the distinction between pleasure and “central affective states” in Haybron (2013).

  39. For illuminating discussion of how attributionism can seem to collapse into voluntarism about moral responsibility, see Holly Smith (2011).

  40. For views of emotions that fall in this “middle zone” between reflex-like and reason-like responses, see D’Arms and Jacobson (2000) and Prinz (2004). I am indebted to Madva (ms b) for the idea that one can be in a mood without noticing it.

  41. Although see Mandelbaum (2015) for argument that implicit attitudes are sometimes even susceptible to revision by reason alone. See also Holroyd (2012) for discussion of what makes a self-regulation strategy “indirect.”

  42. Or perhaps responsibility has multiple “faces,” as Watson (1996) and Shoemaker (2011) suggest.

  43. Whether phobic reactions, actions resulting from brainwashing, or addictive behaviors are attributable to agents depends on whether the empirical facts meet the conditions I discussed in §4 and §5.

  44. One might demand that I attend to or explain (in an etiological sense) why I seem to believe both p and not-p. But demanding that I justify these conflicting beliefs does not make sense. This is, on my view, a problem for Smith’s (2005, 2008) theory that moral responsibility just is answerability. This is relevant because Smith argues that agents are answerable for (what I would call) BEIB. She writes: “I think it is often the case . . . that we simply take or see certain things as counting in favor of certain attitudes without being fully aware of these reasons or the role they play in justifying our attitudes. And I think these normative ‘takings’ or ‘seemings’ can sometimes operate alongside more consciously formulated judgments to the effect that such considerations do not serve to justify our attitudes. So, for example, a person may hold consciously egalitarian views and yet still find herself taking the fact of a person’s race as a reason not to trust her or not to hire her. In these cases, I think an answerability demand directed toward her racist reactions still makes perfect sense—a person’s explicitly avowed beliefs do not settle the question of what she regards as a justifying consideration” (2012, 581, fn 10). I agree with Smith that “takings” and “seemings” may fall within the domain of moral responsibility, but I do not think this is because we are answerable for them, in the sense of being reasonably demanded to justify them. I address Smith’s view in Brownstein, M. Manuscript, The Implicit Mind (Unpublished).

  45. On the social nature of accountability, see, for instance, Watson (1996, 262): “Holding people responsible is not just a matter of the relation of an individual to her behavior; it also involves a social setting in which we demand (require) certain conduct from one another and respond adversely to one another’s failures to comply with these demands.”

  46. For discussion of holding-responsible for BEIB, see Banaji et al. (2015).

References

  • Amodio, D., and P. Devine. 2006. Stereotyping and evaluation in implicit race bias: Evidence for independent constructs and unique effects on behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 91(4): 652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, C.A., and J.J. Lindsay. 1998. The development, perseverance, and change of naïve theories. Social Cognition 16: 8–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. 2004. Unprincipled virtue: An inquiry into moral agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banaji, M., R. Bhaskar, and M. Brownstein. 2015. When bias is implicit, what should be the model for repairing harm? Current Opinion in Psychology 6: 183–188.

  • Bertrand, M. and Mullainathan, S. 2003. Are Emily and Greg more employable than Lakisha and Jamal? A field experiment on labor market. No. 9873, NBER Working Papers from National Bureau of Economic Research, Inc.

  • Bertrand, M., Chugh, D., and Mullainathan, S. 2005. Implicit discrimination. American Economic Review, 94–98.

  • Blair, I., C. Judd, M. Sadler, and C. Jenkins. 2002. The role of Afrocentric features in person perception: Judging by features and categories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83(1): 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bodenhausen, G., and B. Gawronski. 2014. Attitude Change. In The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Psychology, ed. D. Reisberg. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. 2000. Reflection, planning, and temporally extended agency. The Philosophical Review 109(1): 38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, M. 2015. Implicit Bias. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). Ed. E. Zalta. <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/implicit-bias/>. Accessed 1 April 2015.

  • Brownstein, M. Forthcoming. Implicit Bias and Race. In The routledge companion to the philosophy of race, eds. P. Taylor, L. Anderson, and L. Alcoff. New York: Routledge.

  • Cameron, C.D., B.K. Payne, and J. Knobe. 2010. Do theories of implicit race bias change moral judgments? Social Justice Research 23(4): 272–289.

  • Carlsson, R., and F. Björklund. 2010. Implicit stereotype content: Mixed stereotypes can be measured with the implicit association test. Social Psychology 41(4): 213–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correll, J., B. Park, C. Judd, and B. Wittenbrink. 2002. The police officer’s dilemma: Using race to disambiguate potentially threatening individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83: 1314–1329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correll, J., G. Urland, and T. Ito. 2006. Event-related potentials and the decision to shoot: The role of threat perception and cognitive control. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 42: 120–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correll, J., B. Park, C.M. Judd, B. Wittenbrink, M.S. Sadler, and T. Keesee. 2007. Across the thin blue line: Police officers and racial bias in the decision to shoot. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 92(6): 1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dardenne, B., M. Dumont, and T. Bollier. 2007. Insidious dangers of benevolent sexism: Consequences for women’s performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93(5): 764–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’arms, J., and D. Jacobson. 2000. Sentiment and value. Ethics 110(4): 722–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, N., and A.G. Greenwald. 2001. On the malleability of automatic attitudes: Combating automatic prejudice with images of admired and disliked individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81: 800–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devine, P., P. Forscher, A. Austin, and W. Cox. 2012. Long-term reduction in implicit race bias; A prejudice habit-breaking intervention. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 48(6): 1267–1278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donders, N.C., J. Correll, and B. Wittenbrink. 2008. Danger stereotypes predict racially biased attentional allocation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44(5): 1328–1333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, Y., E.E. Chen, and M.R. Banaji. 2013. Two signatures of implicit intergroup attitudes developmental invariance and early enculturation. Psychological Science 24(6): 860–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eberhardt, J., P. Goff, V. Purdie, and P. Davies. 2004. Seeing black: Race, crime, and visual processing. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 87(6): 876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faucher, L. Forthcoming. Revisionism and Moral Responsibility for Attitudes. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, eds. Brownstein, M. and Saul, J. Oxford University Press.

  • Fisher, J.M., and M. Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S.T., A.J. Cuddy, P. Glick, and J. Xu. 2002. A model of (often mixed) stereotype content: competence and warmth respectively follow from perceived status and competition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 82(6): 878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1988. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gawronski, B., and Bodenhausen, G.V. 2006. Associative and Propositional Processes in Evaluation: Conceptual, Empirical, and Metatheoretical Issues: Reply to Albarracín, Hart, and McCulloch (2006), Kruglanski and Dechesne (2006), and Petty and Briñol, (2006). Psychological Bulletin 132:5, 745–750.

  • Gawronski, B., and G. Bodenhausen. 2011. The associative-propositional evaluation model: Theory, evidence, and open questions. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 44: 59–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gawronski, B., and R. Sritharan. 2010. Formation, change, and contextualization of mental associations: Determinants and principles of variations in implicit measures. In Handbook of implicit social cognition: Measurement, theory, and applications, ed. B. Gawronski and B.K. Payne. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gawronski, B., R. Deutsch, S. Mbirkou, B. Seibt, and F. Strack. 2008. When “Just Say No” is not enough: Affirmation versus negation training and the reduction of automatic stereotype activation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44: 370–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T.S. 2008a. Alief and belief. The Journal of Philosophy 105(10): 634–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T.S. 2008b. Alief in action (and reaction). Mind and Language 23(5): 552–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaser, J., and E. Knowles. 2008. Implicit motivation to control prejudice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44: 164–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glasgow, J. Forthcoming. Alienation and Responsibility. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, eds. Brownstein, M. and Saul, J. Oxford University Press.

  • Greenwald, A.G., T.A. Poehlman, E.L. Uhlmann, and M. Banaji. 2009. Understanding and using the implicit association test: III meta-analysis of predictive validity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 97(1): 17–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwald, A., M. Banaji, and B. Nosek. 2015. Statistically small effects of the implicit association test can have societally large effects. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 108(4): 553–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. and Banaji, M. 2013. The Nature of Implicit Prejudice: Implications for personal and public policy. The Behavioral Foundations of Public Policy, 13–30.

  • Haslanger, S. 2015. Social structure, narrative, and explanation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1080/00455091.2015.1019176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. 2013. Happiness: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi, P. 2008. Responsibility for believing. Synthese 161: 357–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinds, A. 30 May 2013. “Heel.” <http://www.slate.com/articles/double_x/doublex/2013/05/stay_at_home_dad_sexual_fantasies_why_i_d_like_to_stop.html>

  • Holroyd, J. 2012. Responsibility for implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy 43(3): 274–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holroyd, J. and J. Sweetman. Forthcoming. The Heterogeneity of Implicit Biases. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 1, Metaphysics and Epistemology, eds. M. Brownstein and J. Saul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hursthouse, R. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ito, T., and G. Urland. 2005. The influence of processing objectives on the perception of faces: An ERP study of race and gender perception. Cognitive, Affective and Behavioral Neuroscience 5: 21–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska, A. 1999. Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value. Philosophy and Public Affairs 28(2): 105–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska, A. 2007. Caring and internality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(3): 529–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J.T., L.A. Rudman, I.V. Blair, D.R. Carney, N. Dasgupta, J. Glaser, and C.D. Hardin. 2009. The existence of implicit bias is beyond reasonable doubt: A refutation of ideological and methodological objections and executive summary of ten studies that no manager should ignore. Research in Organizational Behavior 29: 39–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawakami, K., J.F. Dovidio, and S. van Kamp. 2007. The impact of counterstereotypic training and related correction processes on the application of stereotypes. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations 10(2): 139–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawakami, K., J. Steele, C. Cifa, C. Phills, and J. Dovidio. 2008. Approaching math increases math=me, math=pleasant. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44: 818–825.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, D., and E. Roedder. 2008. Racial cognition and the ethics of implicit bias. Philosophy Compass 3(3): 522–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. 2011. Expressing who we are: Moral responsibility and awareness of our reasons for action. Analytical Philosophy 52(4): 243–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. 2012. Consciousness, implicit attitudes, and moral responsibility. Noûs 48: 21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. 2014. Neither fish nor fowl: Implicit attitudes as patchy endorsements. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12074.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. Forthcoming. Implicit Bias and Moral Responsibility: Probing the Data. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2003. Identification and responsibility. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6: 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madva, A. 2012. The hidden mechanisms of prejudice: Implicit bias and interpersonal fluency. PhD dissertation. Columbia University.

  • Madva, A. Manuscript a, Biased Against De-Biasing: On the Role of (Institutionally Sponsored) Self-Transformation in the Struggle Against Prejudice.

  • Madva, A. Manuscript b, Implicit Bias, Moods, and Moral Responsibility.

  • Madva, A. and M. Brownstein, Manuscript, The Blurry Boundary Between Stereotyping and Evaluation in Implicit Cognition.

  • Madva, A. Forthcoming. Why Implicit Attitudes are (Probably) Not Beliefs. Synthese.

  • Mandelbaum, E. 2015. Attitude, association, and inference: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12089.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mekawi, Y., and K. Bresin. 2015. Is the evidence from racial bias shooting task studies a smoking gun? Results From a Meta-Analysis. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2015.08.002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss-Racusin, C., J. Dovidio, V. Brescoll, M. Graham, and J. Handelsman. 2012. Science faculty’s subtle gender biases favor male students. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences. doi:10.1073/pnas.1211286109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, G.De., J. Freitas, and J. Knobe. 2014. Beliefs about the true self explain asymmetries based on moral judgment. Cognitive Science. doi:10.1111/cogs.12134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nosek, B. A. and Banaji, M. R. 2009. Implicit attitude. Oxford Companion to Consciousness, 84–85.

  • Nosek, B.A., A.G. Greenwald, and M.R. Banaji. 2007a. The implicit association test at age 7: A methodological and conceptual review. In Automatic Processes in Social Thinking and Behavior, ed. J.A. Bargh. Philadelphia: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nosek, B.A., F.L. Smyth, J.J. Hansen, T. Devos, N.M. Lindner, K.A. Ranganath, C.T. Smith, K. Olson, D. Chugh, A.G. Greenwald, and M.R. Banaji. 2007b. Pervasiveness and correlates of implicit attitudes and stereotypes. European Review of Social Psychology 18(1): 36–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M., and R. Fazio. 2006. Reducing automatically activated racial prejudice through implicit evaluative conditioning. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 32: 421–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oswald, F.L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., & Tetlock, P.E. 2013. Predicting Ethnic and Racial Discrimination: A Meta-Analysis of IAT Criterion Studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. doi: 10.1037/a0032734.

  • Phills, C., K. Kawakami, E. Tabi, D. Nadolny, and M. Inzlicht. 2011. Mind the Gap: Increasing the associations between the self and blacks with approach behaviors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 100: 197–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2004. Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quereshi, M.Y., and J.P. Kay. 1986. Physical attractiveness, age, and sex as determinants of reactions to resumes. Social Behavior and Personality: An International Journal 14(1): 103–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rudman, L.A., and R.D. Ashmore. 2007. Discrimination and the implicit association test. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations 10(3): 359–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rudman, L.A., and P. Glick. 2001. Prescriptive gender stereotypes and backlash toward agentic women. Journal of Social Issues 57(4): 743–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rudman, L.A., and S.E. Kilianski. 2000. Implicit and explicit attitudes toward female authority. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 26(11): 1315–1328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. 2012. Skepticism and implicit bias. Disputatio Lecture 5(37): 243–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. 2013. Unconscious influences and women in philosophy. In Women in philosophy: What needs to change? ed. F. Jenkins and K. Hutchison. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1998. What we owe each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. 2010. Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 91: 531–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. 2009. Who Knew? Responsibility without Awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. 2003. Caring, identification, and agency. Ethics 118: 88–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. 2011. Attributability, answerability, and accountability: Towards a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics 121: 602–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sie, M. and Vorst Vader-Bours, N. Forthcoming. Personal Responsibility vis-à-vis Prejudice Resulting from Implicit Bias. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, eds. Brownstein, M. and Saul, J. Oxford University Press.

  • Smart, J. J. C. 1961. Free-will, praise and blame. Mind, 291–306.

  • Smith, A. 2005. Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics 115(2): 236–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 2008. Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies 138: 367–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. 2011. Non-tracing cases of culpable ignorance. Criminal Law and Philosophy 5: 115–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 2012. Attributability, answerability, and accountability: In defense of a unified account. Ethics 122(3): 575–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C.S. 2010. The deep self model and asymmetries in folk judgments about intentional action. Philosophical Studies 151(2): 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C. 2015. Self-expression: A deep self theory of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-015-0527-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, B., and B. Payne. 2008. Bringing automatic stereotyping under control: Implementation intentions as efficient means of thought control. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 34: 1332–1345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strohminger, N., and S. Nichols. 2014. The essential moral self. Cognition 131(1): 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valian, V. 2004. Beyond gender schemas: Improving the advancement of women in academia. NWSA Journal 16(1): 207–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valian, V. 2005. Beyond gender schemas: Improving the advancement of women in academia. Hypatia 20: 198–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Washington, N. and Kelly, D. Forthcoming. Who’s responsible for this? Implicit bias and the knowledge condition. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, eds. Brownstein, M. and Saul, J. Oxford University Press.

  • Watson, G. 1975. Free agency. Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. 1996. Two faces of responsibility. Philosophical Topics 24(2): 227–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittenbrink, B., C.M. Judd, and B. Park. 2001. Spontaneous prejudice in context: Variability in automatically activated attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81(5): 815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zheng, R. Forthcoming. Attributability, Accountability and Implicit Attitudes. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy: Volume 2, Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics, eds. Brownstein, M. and Saul, J. Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

For invaluable suggestions and discussion, I am grateful to Jules Holroyd, Daniel Kelly, W. John Koolage, Joshua Knobe, Alex Madva, Mytro Mylopoulos, Jeremy Pober, Eric Schwitzgebel, David Shoemaker, Susanna Siegel, Holly Smith, Chandra Sripada, Natalia Washington, Robin Zheng, an anonymous reviewer for The Review of Philosophy and Psychology, and audiences at the fall 2012 Wittgenstein Workshop, the 2013 meeting of the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology, and the 2013 Pacific Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association. Thanks also to the Leverhulme Trust for funding the “Implicit Bias and Philosophy” workshops at the University of Sheffield from 2011–2013, out of which this work grew.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Brownstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brownstein, M. Attributionism and Moral Responsibility for Implicit Bias. Rev.Phil.Psych. 7, 765–786 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0287-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0287-7

Keywords

Navigation