Skip to main content
Log in

On Continuity and Endurance

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to three-dimensionalism, objects persist in time by being wholly present at each time they exist; on the contrary, four-dimensionalism asserts that objects persist by having different temporal parts at different times or that they are instantaneous temporal parts of four-dimensional aggregates. Le Poidevin has argued that four-dimensionalism better accommodates two common assumptions concerning persistence and continuity; namely, that time itself is continuous and that objects persist in time in a continuous way. To this purpose, he has offered two independent arguments, each of which moves from a different understanding of continuity. In this paper, both of Le Poidevin’s arguments will be discussed and rejected.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Three-dimensionalists include, among others, Geach (1972), Wiggins (1980), Mellor (1981), Thomson (1983), Lowe (1988), Haslanger (1989), van Inwagen (1990).

  2. Perdurantists include, among others, Russell (1914), Quine (1963), Armstrong (1980), Heller (1984), Lewis (1986), and Le Poidevin (1991).

  3. Stage theorists include Hawley (2001) and Sider (2001).

  4. Properly speaking, the concept of an atomless gunk is a mereological one, not an ordinal one: in fact, it denotes an object all of whose parts have proper parts in their turn (Lewis 1991: 20). Stuchlik, however, employs it in relation to time as a synonym of the ordinal concept of a densely ordered set: in this sense, time is gunky just in case every finite interval of time can be subdivided into denumerably many proper subintervals. Stuchlik is accordingly claiming that the stage theory presupposes that time is either discrete or continuous but not dense.

  5. Still, this paper is not intended to provide a limited defence of three-dimensionalism. To see this, it is sufficient to notice that my rebuttal of Le Poidevin’s arguments can be subscribed to by those who deny that there is any metaphysical difference between three-dimensionalism and four-dimensionalism (see for example McCall and Lowe 2003, 2006). Rather, this paper is meant to be part of a more general investigation concerning the metaphysical implications of the idea of continuity.

  6. Le Poidevin’s own treatment of this problem can be found in 2003 (111–115).

  7. Le Poidevin does not clearly distinguish between perdurantism and the stage theory, so his argument might seem to get off the ground only if one does not take the latter into consideration. The stage theory, in fact, might seem to offer a rather easy solution to the problem of the moment of becoming: for any object there is unambiguously a first moment of existence and a last moment of existence, and both coincide with the one moment during which that object exists. On these grounds, one may conclude that the stage theory does not need to resort to any form of vagueness in order to make room for the hypothesis that time is continuous in the mathematical sense, and that as such it must be preferred to both three-dimensionalism and perdurantism, thus completely sidestepping Le Poidevin’s argumentation. (I am grateful to an anonymous referee for having pointed this out.) However, this conclusion would overlook a crucial aspect of the stage theory, namely that, as a theory of persistence, it aims to offer a consistent story about what we ordinarily think to be persisting objects. To this purpose, it needs to be able to tell unambiguously, for any instantaneous object x, which other instantaneous objects are its temporal counterparts. To the stage theorist, in consequence, the problem of the moment of becoming reappears in the fashion of the problem whether there is a last moment of time at which there is a temporal counterpart of x, or rather a first time at which there is no such counterpart.

  8. Considerations of this kind may also explain why Le Poidevin’s paper has received comparatively scarce attention from both three-dimensionalists and four-dimensionalists.

  9. This latter clause is meant to accommodate otherwise questionable cases, such as the one of a clock that is temporally taken apart and then reconstructed using its own pieces.

  10. This assumption has been interestingly called into question by Petkov (2005: 162–163), who suggests that quantum particles possibly persist by periodically going in and out of existence in a discontinuous fashion.

  11. Clearly, ‘spatiotemporal continuity’ is to be understood here in the non-technical sense. Notice that, in this sense, objects can persist continuously in time even if time is discrete (whether or not space is mathematically continuous). However, in that case, they could only be spatiotemporally continuous if at rest or, if space is discrete, if moving at the constant speed of one minimal unit of time per one minimal unit of space; else, they will have to move between non-adjacent places at subsequent times (Mazzola 2014).

  12. In reality, condition (ii) is not mentioned in Le Poidevin’s formulation of (2). However, that omission is evidently due to a typo.

  13. Incidentally, the physical dimensions envisaged in (iv) are required to be continuous in the technical or mathematical sense. This surreptitiously makes the non-technical sense of continuity parasitic upon its technical counterpart. Notice, however, that every reference to the mathematical understanding of continuity can be dropped from (iv) by simply replacing the phrase ‘different positions along a continuous dimension’ with the phrase ‘different positions along the same dimension’. This will suffice to make (iv) compatible with the possibility that physical dimensions such as distance, mass, temperature, etc. be discontinuous or quantized.

  14. For the pedantic, for any s, x is not a temporal part of s or y is not a temporal part of s or s is not four-dimensional.

  15. I do not myself think that it is. However, what matters here is just that, in any case, (1) is not worse as an analysis of diachronic identity than (2), (3), and (4) are as principles for the unification of temporal parts.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1980). Identity through time. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause. Essays presented to Richard Taylor (pp. 67–78). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balashov, Y. (2005). On vagueness, four-dimensionalism and diachronic universalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83, 523–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (2000). Is time a continuum of instants? Philosophy, 75, 497–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1972). Logic matters. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1969). Starting and stopping. The Monist, 53, 410–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (1989). Endurance and temporary intrinsics. Analysis, 49, 119–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2001). How things persist. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1984). Temporal parts of four-dimensional objects. Philosophical Studies, 46, 323–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinchliff, M. (1996). The puzzle of change. Philosophical Perspectives, 30, 119–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2003). The crooked path from vagueness to four-dimensionalism. Philosophical Studies, 114, 107–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R. (1991). Change, cause and contradiction. Houndmills and London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R. (2000). Continuants and continuity. The Monist, 83, 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R. (2003). Travels in four dimensions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford and New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1988). The problem of intrinsic change. Rejoinder to Lewis. Analysis, 48, 72–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2004). Two Arguments from Sider’s “four-dimensionalism”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68, 665–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazzola, C. (2014). Can discrete time make continuous space look discrete? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 4, 19–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCall, S., & Lowe, E. J. (2003). 3D/4D equivalence, the twins paradox, and absolute time. Analysis, 63, 114–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCall, S., & Lowe, E. J. (2006). The 3D/4D controversy: a storm in a teacup. Noûs, 40, 570–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medlin, B. (1963). The origin of motion. Mind, 72, 155–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, H. D. (1981). Real time. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (1999). Persistence, parts and presentism. Noûs, 33, 421–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mortensen. (1985). The limits of change. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 63, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (2006). Vagueness, multiplicity and parts. Noûs, 40, 716–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H. (2010). A flaw in Sider’s vagueness argument for unrestricted mereological composition. Analysis, 70, 669–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petkov, V. (2005). Relativity and the nature of space-time. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1968). Time, existence and identity. In A. N. Prior (Ed.), Papers on time and tense (pp. 78–87). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1963). Identity, ostension, and hypostasis. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), From a logical point of view (2nd ed., pp. 65–79). Evanston: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1914). Our knowledge of the external world. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (1997). Four dimensionalism. Philosophical Review, 106, 197–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1983). Time, creation and the continuum. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strobach, N. (1998). The moment of change. A systematic history in the philosophy of space and time. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuchlik, J. (2003). Not all worlds are stages. Philosophical Studies, 116, 309–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. (1955). Spatial and temporal analogies and the concept of identity. Journal of Philosophy, 52, 599–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1983). Parthood and identity across time. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1990). Four-dimensional objects. Noûs, 24, 245–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1980). Sameness and substance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank an anonymous referee for her constructive comments. This research has been funded through a UQ Postdoctoral Research Fellowship granted by the University of Queensland.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudio Mazzola.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mazzola, C. On Continuity and Endurance. Acta Anal 30, 133–147 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-014-0236-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-014-0236-6

Keywords

Navigation