Abstract
Some recent conservation proposals – including the Zoological Society of London’s (ZSL) EDGE of Existence programme – have focused on the value of protecting species with high evolutionary distinctiveness, a dimension of biodiversity conservation that’s not been much emphasized in conservation practice. In this paper we critically examine this strategy, investigating whether there are good reasons for prioritizing evolutionarily distinctive species, and the phylogenetic diversity to which they contribute, over other forms of biodiversity. We first discuss evolutionary distinctiveness, its relationship to phylogenetic diversity, how phylogenetic diversity can be measured, and intuitive thoughts about its value. Then we consider five kinds of arguments about the value of phylogenetic diversity that might be made to support prioritizing it, given its current lack of emphasis in conservation practice. These are: arguments based on protecting biodiversity, arguments based on option value, arguments based on ecological resilience, arguments based on historical value, and arguments based on aesthetic value. We maintain that these arguments, taken individually, offer varying degrees of fairly weak support for valuing species with high evolutionary distinctiveness. Taken together, however, these arguments seem sufficiently strong to justify programs such as EDGE, insofar as such programs are framed as correctives to a past lack of emphasis on the protection of phylogenetic diversity. We suggest, however, that these arguments are not sufficiently strong to support an absolute prioritization of phylogenetic diversity over protecting other forms of biodiversity.

Adapted from Isaac et al (2007)
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
Isaac et al (2007) proposed the technique for mammalian conservation priorities, but it’s been extended to include other classes.
We recognize that there will be disputes about these categories; hopefully the point makes general sense in any case.
Bennett et al., 2019 and Tucket et al. 2019 contend that we can predict future evolutionary potential, but that it isn’t strongly correlated with phylogenetic diversity.
With respect to the very long time span scenario, we’d also need to construct independent ethical arguments about why the earth’s ecology after thousands of years—potentially without human beings—should assume any particular kind of shape (though see Nolt, 2011). Since it seems highly unlikely that, in the next 100 years or so, the world will need species with high evolutionary distinctiveness for the purpose of ecological resilience, this version of the resilience argument is an extremely weak argument for prioritizing their protection over the species low in evolutionary distinctiveness that are successful today. Also, someone might object that as the timescale increases, the odds of a species with high evolutionary distinctiveness being important for ecological resilience increase. However, it’s also the case that as the timescale increases, the odds of a species with high evolutionary distinctiveness going extinct despite (or even more depressingly, because of) human efforts increases, which seems to balance out the (evolutionary) expected utility calculation.
References
Barker, G. (2002). Phylogenetic diversity: A quantitative framework for measurement of priority and achievement in biodiversity conservation. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 76(2), 165–194. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1095-8312.2002.tb02081.x
Bennett D. J., Sutton M. D. & Turvey S. T. (2019). How the past impacts the future: modelling the performance of evolutionarily distinct mammals through time. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B37420190210. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2019.0210
Brooks, T., Mittermeier, R., da Fonseca, G., Gerlach, J., Hoffman, M., Lamoreux, J., Mittermeier, C., Pilgrim, J., & Rodrigues, A. (2006). Global Biodiversity Conservation Priorities. Science, 313(5783), 58.
Brum, F., Graham, C., Costa, G., Hedges, S., & Penone, C. (2017). Global priorities for conservation across multiple dimensions of mammalian diversity. PNAS, 114(29), 7641–7646.
Cadotte, M. W., Dinnage, R., & Tilman, D. (2012). Phylogenetic diversity promotes ecosystem stability. Ecology, 93, S223–S233. https://doi.org/10.1890/11-0426.1
Cadotte, M. W., Davies, J., Peres-Neto, T., & Pedro, R. (2017). Why phylogenies do not always predict ecological differences. Ecological Monographs, 87, 535–551. https://doi.org/10.1002/ecm.1267
Carlson, A. (2020). Environmental Aesthetics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward N. Zalta (ed.) Retrieved July 24th 2021 from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/environmental-aesthetics/
Crandall, K. A., Bininda-Edmonds, O. R. P., Mace, G. M., & Wayne, R. K. (2000). Considering evolutionary processes in conservation biology. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 15, 290–295.
Collen, B., Turvey, S. T., Waterman, C., et al. (2011). Investing in evolutionary history: Implementing a phylogenetic approach for mammal conservation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series b, Biological Sciences, 366(1578), 2611–2622. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2011.0109
Davies, T. J., Urban, M. C., Rayfield, B., Cadotte, M. W., & Peres-Neto, P. R. (2016). Deconstructing the relationships between phylogenetic diversity and ecology: A case study on ecosystem functioning. Ecology, 97, 2212–2222. https://doi.org/10.1002/ecy.1507
Erwin, T. (1991). An Evolutionary Basis for Conservation Strategies. Science, 253(5021), 750–752.
Faith, D. P. (1992). Conservation evaluation and phylogenetic diversity. Biological Conservation, 61, 1–10.
Flynn, D. F. B., Mirotchnick, N., Jain, M., Palmer, M. I., & Naeem, S. (2011). Functional and phylogenetic diversity as predictors of biodiversity–ecosystem-function relationships. Ecology, 92, 1573–1581. https://doi.org/10.1890/10-1245.1
Fromm, O. (2000). Ecological structure and functions of biodiversity as elements of its total economic value. Environmental and Resource Economics, 16, 303–328.
Grandcolas, p & Trewick, S. (2016) What Is the Meaning of Extreme Phylogenetic Diversity? The Case of Phylogenetic Relict Species. In Pelles and Grandcolas (Eds). Biodiversity Conservation and Phylogenetic Systematics - Preserving our evolutionary heritage in an extinction crisis Topics in Biodiversity and Conservation, vol 14 (pp. 99–115). Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22461-9_2
Hendry, A. P., et al. (2010). Evolutionary biology in biodiversity science, conservation, and policy: A call to action. Evolution, 64, 1517–1528.
Hettinger, N. (2017). Evaluating Positive Aesthetics. The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 51(3), 26–41.
IPCC (2014). Climate Change 2014: Synthesis Report. Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change [Core Writing Team, R.K. Pachauri and L.A. Meyer (eds.)]. IPCC, Geneva, Switzerland, 151pp.
Isaac, N. J., Turvey, S. T., Collen, B., Waterman, C., & Baillie, J. E. (2007). Mammals on the EDGE: conservation priorities based on threat and phylogeny. PLoS ONE, 2(3), e296.
Jenkins, C., Pimm, S., & Joppa, l. (2013). Global vertebrate diversity and conservation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110(28), E2602–E2610. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1302251110
Jono, C., & Pavoine, S. (2012). Threat Diversity Will Erode Mammalian Phylogenetic diversity in the Near Future. PLoS ONE, 7(9), e46235. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0046235
Lean C. & Maclaurin J. (2016) The Value of Phylogenetic Diversity. In: Pellens R. & Grandcolas P. (Eds.) Biodiversity Conservation and Phylogenetic Systematics - Preserving our evolutionary heritage in an extinction crisis. Topics in Biodiversity and Conservation, vol 14 (pp.19–38) Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22461-9_2
Mace, G. M., Gittleman, J. L., & Purvis, A. (2003). Preserving the tree of life. Science, 300, 1707–1709.
Manes, S., et al. (2021). Endemism increases species’ climate change risk in areas of global biodiversity importance. Biological Conservation, 257, 109070. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biocon.2021.109070
Marris, E. (2007). Conservation Priorities: What to let go. Nature, 450, 152–155.
Mazel, F., Pennell, M. W., Cadotte, M. W., et al. (2018). Prioritizing phylogenetic diversity captures functional diversity unreliably. Nature Communications, 9, 2888. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-018-05126-3
McCord, E. (2007). The Value of Species. Yale University Press.
Nolt, J. (2011). Nonanthropocentric climate ethics. WIRES. Climate Change, 2, 701–711.
Olden, J. D., Kennard, M. K., Lawler, J. J., & Poff, N. L. (2011). Challenges and opportunities for implementing managed relocation of species for freshwater conservation. Conservation Biology, 25, 40–47.
Owen, N. R., Gumbs, R., Gray, C. L., et al. (2019). Global conservation of phylogenetic diversity captures more than just functional diversity. Nature Communications, 10, 859.
Pearse, W. D., Pennell, M. W., Winter, M., & Mooers, A. O. (2019). Assessing the utility of conserving evolutionary history. Biological Reviews, 94, 1740–1760. https://doi.org/10.1111/brv.12526
Peel, E., Cheng, Y., Djordjevic, J., et al. (2016). Cathelicidins in the Tasmanian devil (Sarcophilus harrisii). Science Reports, 6, 35019. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep35019
Newman, J. A., Varner, G., & Linquist, S. (2017). Defending biodiversity: Environmental science and ethics. Cambridge University Press.
Rolston, H. (1988). Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the Natural World. Temple University Press.
Saito, Y. (1998). The Aesthetics of Unscenic Nature. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 56(2), 101–11.
Soulé, M. (1985). What Is Conservation Biology? BioScience, 35(11), 727–734. https://doi.org/10.2307/1310054
Stockwell, C. A., Hendry, A. P., & Kinnison, M. T. (2003). Contemporary evolution meets conservation biology. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 18, 94–101.
Tribot, A. S., Mouquet, N., Villéger, S., et al. (2016). Taxonomic and functional diversity increase the aesthetic value of coralligenous reefs. Science Reports, 6, 34229. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep34229
Tucker, C. M., Aze, T., Cadotte, M. W., Cantalapiedra, J. L., Chisholm, C., Díaz, S., Grenyer, R., Huang, D., Mazel, F. V., & S, Davies TJ, Cadotte MW, Clergeau P & Pavoine S. . (2017). Predicting loss of evolutionary history: Where are we? Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 92(1), 271–291. https://doi.org/10.1111/brv.12228
Veron, S., Haevermans, T., Govaerts, R., et al. (2019). Distribution and relative age of endemism across islands worldwide. Science Reports, 9, 11693.
Weisbrod, B. A. (1964). Collective Consumption Services of Individual Consumption Goods. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 77, 71–77.
Winter, M., Devictor, V., & Schweiger, O. (2013). Phylogenetic diversity and nature conservation: Where are we? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 28(4), 199–204. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2012.10.015
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Palmer, C., Fischer, B. Should Global Conservation Initiatives Prioritize Phylogenetic Diversity?. Philosophia 50, 2283–2302 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00422-7
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00422-7