Skip to main content
Log in

Dennett’s Strategy for Naturalizing Intentionality: an Innovative Play at Second Base

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I briefly review the three basic strategies for naturalizing intentionality discussed by Haugeland 4:383–427, 1990, and Hutto and Satne (2015), recounting their deficits. Then, I focus on Dennett’s version of what Haugeland calls the “second-base … neo-behaviorist” strategy. After briefly explaining Dennett’s proposal, I defend it against four common objections: circularity, relativity, under-specified rationality, and failure to track robustly natural facts. I conclude by recounting the advantages of Dennettian neo-behaviorism over the neo-Cartesian and neo-pragmatist alternatives, as well as Hutto and Satne’s proposal that intentionality comes in two distinct kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Fodor (1994) argues that this account of Frege cases is superior to appeals to so-called “narrow content”, which he regards as untenable.

  2. In some ways, Dennett’s proposal is similar to influential analyses of secondary properties, like color. On these views, colors and other secondary properties are objective yet response-dependent. A stop sign is red, for example, because it is disposed to trigger perceptions of red in normal human observers. This is an objective though relational/dispositional property of the stop sign. Similarly, on Dennett’s understanding of intentionality, it is an objective yet response-dependent property of some kinds of behavior, i.e., those that are disposed to trigger attributions of intentionality in normal human observers.

  3. To be sure, this is a departure from the naturalization project as classically conceived. Intentionality is in no way reduced to a natural relation like nomic dependence or teleology. But Dennett explicitly eschews such naturalization strategies, in favor of an alternative inspired by the theory of computation (1987, pp. 67–8). In Dennett’s view, Turing’s notion of computability does not involve reducing computability to some other, “more natural” phenomenon. Rather, it involves “legitimizing” the computational idiom, by providing a precise, formal framework for its systematic and useful application to observable phenomena. Dennett sees his project as doing the same for the intentional idiom. The point is not to reduce it, but to make it precise enough to systematically and usefully apply to observable phenomena, especially behavioral contexts that are systematically parsable into goals, efficient means, and available information, including higher-order goals, efficient means, and available information, as when one interprets an interpretive process.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (1997). Fodor’s asymmetric causal dependency theory and proximal projections. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35(4), 433–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.-L. (2003). Thinking without words. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. (2000). How children learn the meaning of words. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1999). Some pragmatist themes in Hegel’s idealism: negotiation and administration in Hegel’s account of the structure and content of conceptual norms. European Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 164–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., & Apperly, I. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind and Language, 28(5), 606–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1990). A neurocomputational perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 61, 441–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1998). Brainchildren. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1994). If you can’t make one, you don’t know how it works. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19(1), 468–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1994). The Elm and the expert. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A Shoppers’ guide. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Lepore, E. (1993). Is intentional ascription intrinsically normative? In B. Dahlbom (Ed.), Dennett and his critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G. (2011). Kinds of agents: the origins of understanding instrumental and communicative agency. In U. Goshwami (Ed.), Blackwell handbook of childhood cognitive development (2nd ed., pp. 76–105). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G., & Csibra, G. (2003). Teleological reasoning in infancy: the naive theory of rational action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(7), 287–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). The Intentionality all-stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 383–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia. This volume.

  • Lurz, R. (Ed.). (2009). Philosophy of animal minds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W., Stich, S., & Garon, J. (1990). Eliminativism and the future of folk psychology. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 499–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1981). Dennett on intentional systems. Philosophical Topics, 12(1), 39–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2003). Mythological content: a problem for Millikan’s teleosemantics. Philosophical Psychology, 16(4), 535–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tadeusz Wieslaw Zawidzki.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zawidzki, T.W. Dennett’s Strategy for Naturalizing Intentionality: an Innovative Play at Second Base. Philosophia 43, 593–609 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9630-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9630-6

Keywords

Navigation