Skip to main content
Log in

Empathy as the Opposite of Egocentrism: Why the Simulation Theory and the Direct Perception Theory of Empathy Fail

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a new, third-personal account of empathy that characterizes empathy as being sensitive to others’ concerns as opposed to remaining stuck in one’s egocentric perspective on the world. The paper also demonstrates why this account is preferable to its two main rivals, namely the simulation theory of empathy, and the direct perception theory of empathy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Also Plantinga (2009).

  2. Other defenders of the participant view include: Smith (1995), Grodal (1997), Vaage (2010), Coplan (2004), and Eder (2008).

  3. For the debate about the direct perception theory as such see, e.g., Jacob (2011), Lavelle (2012), Gallagher (2012b, 2015), Newen et al. (2015), Spaulding (2015, 2017). For a discussion of phenomenological theories of empathy with regard to film see e.g., Vaage (2006), Schmetkamp (2017a, b), and D’Aloia (2012).

  4. There seem to be two reasons why Gallagher refrains from tying empathy to the direct perception theory: (1) Gallagher leans toward a conception of empathy as something that is more than standard mindreading, whereas the direct perception theory is a theory about standard mindreading; (2) Gallagher wants to avoid limiting empathy to the face-to-face encounter. I will return to the latter problem of the direct perception theory below. For a more recent characterization of empathy by Gallagher with regard to acting see (Gallagher and Gallagher 2019).

  5. In Fodor’s version of the theory-theory, for example, the knowledge and principles that we use to read other minds clearly includes our knowledge about “people whose psychology [we] know intimately: [our] closest friends, say, or the spouse of [our] bosom” (1987, p. 3). Fodor also stresses that what is relevant to his approach to mindreading is not the content of such exemplary truisms as “the burnt child fears the fire” but the “‘deductive structure’ that is so characteristic of explanation in real science” (1987, pp. 6–7).

  6. To be correct, Scheler (2008, p. 20) limits this congruent feeling element to “feelingly grasping the quality of the foreign feeling” (my translation). I don’t think too much hinges on this refinement, however, because Scheler’s account of empathy differs from my account irrespective of this element.

  7. I will elaborate on the appraisal theory of emotions in the last section of the paper.

  8. In line with Ortony et al. (1988) I reject the view that my outrage in such a case is a simulated response because for ordinary first-personal outrage, it is irrelevant whether the victim of an action that violates one of my normative principles is me or someone else. Likewise, I claim that it is irrelevant for ordinary first-personal disgust whether it is my action that violates one of my preferences in taste or someone else’s action. Hence it is a mistake to believe that my disgust at seeing another person eat a worm relies on putting myself in the other’s shoes. Moreover, I believe that there are good arguments for the view that other supposedly simulatory responses – such as vicarious embarrassment or even so-called empathy for pain – are actually sympathetic responses. For empirical evidence that supports the latter claim and questions large parts of previous neuroscientific studies on empathy for pain and empathy in general, see, e.g.: Iannetti et al (2013), Hu and Iannetti (2016), and Krishnan et al (2016). For a response to this criticism by leading empathy researchers, see, e.g.: Zaki et al. (2016) or De Vignemont and Jacob (2016). These are crucial elements for the defense of my theory, which, for reasons of space, I cannot elaborate here.

  9. One might object that I shouldn’t speak of an allocentric perspective if I do not mean by that the adoption of another person’s point of view. But I have deliberately chosen to stick with this metaphor because I want to stay as close as possible to our ordinary speech. My hope is that in this way readers will find it easier to consult their own intuitions about what we really mean by this expression in the relevant contexts.

  10. I will frequently switch between real world examples, “intrafictional” examples, and examples involving the film spectator because I believe that the patterns of empathizing and sympathizing are more or less analogical in all these cases. Of course, this is not to say that on a macro level there are great differences between our engagement with reality and film, because unlike in unmediated reality our empathy and sympathy are strongly influenced by the cinematic narration when we are watching a film. In addition, films can give us quick access to the biographies, traits and preferences of people who would be total strangers to us in the real world.

  11. The former is visibly the case in the scene where the mother comes to accept that she will not overcome her cancer.

  12. Arguably one of the reasons why we do this so readily in the cinema is because, unlike in reality, the fictional states of affairs cannot affect our goals, or at least only to a very limited degree. Contrast this with a case where an opponent beats me in a competition and where my feeling upset about this fact would make it considerably more difficult for me to focus my attention on what this fact means to him.

  13. For an introduction to the philosophy of well-being, see Crisp (2017). For a more detailed overview, see, e.g., Sumner (1996).

  14. I am here using the definition of empathy as something that we do in addition to mindreading, as has been proposed by De Vignemont and Jacob (2012), in part as a concession to the phenomenological criticism of the simulation theory of mindreading. I present my own arguments against the simulation theory of mindreading in my upcoming dissertation.

  15. For an alternative account of the relationship between empathy and sympathy that avoids the commitment to say that the father is not empathizing with his son, see Giovannelli (2009).

  16. Note that this would not be a case of schadenfreude as I define it below, but an ordinary self-oriented response.

  17. For this widely accepted definition of sympathetic and antipathetic emotions, see, e.g., Ortony et al. (1988).

References

  • Baron-Cohen S (1995) Mindblindness: an essay on autism and theory of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanchet R, Vaage MB (2012) Don, Peggy, and other fictional friends? engaging with characters in television series. Projections 6(2):18–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll N (2011) On some affective relations between audiences and characters in popular fictions. In: Coplan A, Goldie P (eds) Empathy: philosophical and psychological perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Coplan A (2004) Empathic engagement with narrative fictions. J Aesthet Art Critic 62(2):141–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2017) Well-being. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/well-being/

  • D’Aloia A (2012) Cinematic empathy: spectator involvement in the film experience. In: Reynolds D, Reason M (eds) Kinesthetic empathy in creative and cultural practices. Intelect, Bristol

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F, Jacob P (2012) What is it like to feel another’s pain? Philos Sci 79(2):295–316

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F, Jacob P (2016) Beyond empathy for pain. Philos Sci 83(3):434–445

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder J (2008) Die Figur im Film: Grundlagen der Figurenanalyse. Schüren, Marburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1987) Psychosemantics. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda NH (1986) The emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2001) The practice of mind: theory, simulation, or interaction? J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):83–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2007) Simulation trouble. Soc neurosci-uk 2(3–4):353–365

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2012a) Empathy, simulation, and narrative. Sci Context 25(3):355–381

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2012b) In defense of phenomenological approaches to social cognition: interacting with the critics. Rev Philos Psychol 3:187–212

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2015) The new hybrids: continuing debates on social perception. Conscious Cogn 36:452–465

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2017) Empathy and theories of direct perception. In: Maibom H (ed) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of empathy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Gallagher J (2019) Acting oneself as another: an actor’s empathy for her character. Topoi 36:452–465. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9624-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Hutto D (2008) Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In: Zlatev J, Racine TP, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. John Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaut B (2010) Empathy and identification in cinema. Midwest Stud Philos 34(1):136–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Giovannelli A (2008) In and out: the dynamics of imagination in the engagement with narratives. J Aesthet Art Critic 66(1):11–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Giovannelli A (2009) In sympathy with narrative characters. J Aesthet Art Critic 67(1):83–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AI (2006) Simulating minds: the philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik A, Meltzoff A (1997) Words, thoughts, and theories. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (1986) Well-being: its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Grodal T (1997) Moving pictures: a new theory of film genres, feelings, and cognition. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman ML (2000) Empathy and moral development: implications for caring and justice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hu L, Iannetti GD (2016) Painful issues in pain prediction. Trends Neurosci 39(4):212–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (2016) Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution und Wissenschaftstheorie. Fonfara D (Hrsg) Springer, Dordrecht

  • Hutto D (2008) Folk-psychological narratives. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Iannetti GD, Salomons TV, Moayedi M, Mouraux A, Davis KD (2013) Beyond metaphor: contrasting mechanisms of social and physical pain. Trends Cogn Sn 17(8):371–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob P (2011) The direct perception model of empathy: a critique. Rev Philos Psychol 2:519–540

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine J, Szanto T (2017) Empathy in the phenomenological tradition. In: Maibom H (ed) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of empathy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Krishnan A, Woo CW, Chang LJ, Ruzic L, Gu X, López-Solà M, Jackson PL, Pujol J, Fan J, Wager TD (2016) Somatic and vicarious pain are represented by dissociable multivariate brain patterns. eLife 5:1–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavelle JS (2012) Theory-theory and the direct perception of mental states. Rev Philos Psychol 3:213–230

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus RS (1991) Emotion and adaptation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen A (2015) Understanding others: the person model theory. In: Metzinger M, Windt JM (eds) Open MIND, MIND Group, Frankfurt am Main

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen A, Welpinghus A, Juckel G (2015) Emotion recognition as pattern recognition: the relevance of perception. Mind Lang 30:187–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortony A, Clore GL, Collins A (1988) The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga C (2009) Moving viewers: American film and the spectator’s experience. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton P (1986) Facts and values. Philos Topics 14(2):5–31

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler M (2008) Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. In: Frings M (Hrsg) Gesammelte Werke, Band 7. Bouvier, Bonn

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmetkamp S (2017a) Perspektive und empathische Resonanz: Vergegenwärtigung anderer Sichtweisen. In: Hagener M, Vendrell Ferran I (Hrsg) Empathie im Film: Perspektiven der Ästhetischen Theorie, Phänomenologie und Analytischen Philosophie. Transkript, Bielefeld

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmetkamp S (2017b) Gaining perspectives on our lives: moods and aesthetic experience. Philosophia 45(4):1681–1695

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith M (1995) Engaging characters: fiction, emotion, and the cinema. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding S (2010) Embodied cognition and mindreading. Mind Lang 25(1):119–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding S (2015) On direct social perception. Conscious Cogn 36:472–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding S (2017) On whether we can see intentions. Pac Philos Quart 98(2):150–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding S (2018) How we understand others: philosophy and social cognition. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein E (2008) Zum Problem der Einfühlung. In: Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Band 5. Herder, Freiburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Stueber KR (2006) Rediscovering empathy: agency, folk psychology, and the human sciences. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner LW (1996) Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tan ES (1996) Emotion and the structure of narrative film: film as emotion machine. Lawrence Erlbaum, Mahwah (New Jersey)

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaage MB (2006) The empathetic film spectator in analytic philosophy and naturalized phenomenology. Film Philosophy 10:21–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaage MB (2010) Fiction film and the varieties of empathic engagement. Midwest Stud Philos 34(1):158–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim R (1999) The thread of life. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2014) Self and other: exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2017) Phenomenology, empathy, and mindreading. In: Maibom H (ed) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of empathy. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D, Overgaard S (2011) Empathy without isomorphism: a phenomenological account. In: Decety J (ed) Empathy: from bench to bedside. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaki J, Wager TD, Singer T, Keysers C, Gazzola V (2016) The anatomy of suffering: understanding the relationship between nociceptive and empathic pain. Trends Cogn Sn 20(4):249–259

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Blanchet.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by the author.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blanchet, R. Empathy as the Opposite of Egocentrism: Why the Simulation Theory and the Direct Perception Theory of Empathy Fail. Topoi 39, 751–759 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-09630-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-09630-5

Keywords

Navigation