Skip to main content
Log in

Pluralistic ignorance in the bystander effect: informational dynamics of unresponsive witnesses in situations calling for intervention

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The goal of the present paper is to construct a formal explication of the pluralistic ignorance explanation of the bystander effect. The social dynamics leading to inaction is presented, decomposed, and modeled using dynamic epistemic logic augmented with ‘transition rules’ able to characterize agent behavior. Three agent types are defined: First Responders who intervene given belief of accident; City Dwellers, capturing ‘apathetic urban residents’ and Hesitators, who observe others when in doubt, basing subsequent decision on social proof. It is shown how groups of the latter may end in a state of pluralistic ignorance leading to inaction. Sequential models for each agent type are specified, and their results compared to empirical studies. It is concluded that only the Hesitator model produces reasonable results.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a comprehensive walk-through of this explanation and supportive data, refer to Latané and Darley (1970).

  2. Halbesleben and Buckley (2004) provides an illuminating overview of the history and development of the term.

  3. Technically, no logic is introduced; the dynamics are investigated using only model theory.

  4. Reflexive and transitive binary relation where every non-empty subset has a minimal element, cf. (Baltag and Smets 2008).

  5. The relation \(\le _{i}\) may therefore more appropriately be thought of as an implausibility relation, where \(s\le _{i}t\) is read ‘\(t\) is as implausible as \(s\), or more so’.

  6. A heuristic to aid recall is that \(s<t\) in form is similar to \(s\leftarrow t\) when looking at the arrowhead. When \(s\le _{i}t\) and \(t\le _{i}s\), arrowheads are omitted altogether.

  7. The notation for information and plausibility cells are adopted from Dégremont (2010).

  8. Parentheses will be omitted where no confusion should arise.

  9. The reason for using this atypical definition of propositions is that it allows us to speak about the same proposition across multiple models. This is practical as model transformations will play a large role in the latter. A Kripke model valuation may easily be extracted from set of doxastic atomic propositions; see (Baltag and Smets 2008) for details.

  10. As opposed to the terminology of Baltag and Smets (2008), Benthem (2007), Demey (2011) where epistemic plausibility models are Kripke models.

  11. Ontic facts are all non-doxastic facts, i.e. propositions that do not contain belief or knowledge operators.

  12. The postcondition \(\top \) leaves all atomic propositions as they were in the previous model. This is specified by the action priority update product below.

  13. \(\preceq _{i}\) is from \(\mathbf {E}\) and \(\le _{i}\) from \(\mathbf {S}\). \(\sigma \prec _{i}\tau \) denotes (\(\sigma \preceq _{i}\tau \) and not \(\sigma \succeq _{i}\tau \)), \(\sigma \backsimeq _{i}\tau \) denotes (\(\sigma \preceq _{i}\tau \) and \(\sigma \succeq _{i}\tau \)).

  14. The definition is based on Baltag and Smets (2008) for the anti-lexicographic order, adding postconditions from Ditmarsch and Kooi (2008), Bolander and Birkegaard (2011).

  15. Note the analogy with numerical equations; for both \(2+x=5\) and \(\{2+x=5,4+x=7\},\,x=3\) is the (unique) solution.

  16. The definition is altered to suit transition rules using \([X]_{i}\) “modalities” by suitable replacing \([X]\) with \([X]_{i}\) and \([\varGamma ]\) with \([\varGamma ]_{i}\) throughout.

  17. For a definition of system, see (Rendsvig 2013a).

  18. Unless evading entails leaving the scene or observation is performed in a non-discrete manner. Often this is not the case, though: “Among American males it is considered desirable to appear poised and collected in times of stress. ... If each member of a group is, at the same time, trying to appear calm and also looking around at the other members to gauge their reactions, all members may be led (or misled) by each other to define the situation as less critical than they would if alone. Until someone [intervenes], each person only sees other nonresponding bystanders, and ... is likely to be influenced not to act himself.” (Latané and Darley 1968, p. 216); “... Apparent passitivity and lack of concern on the part of other bystanders may indicate that they feel the emergency is not serious, but it may simply mean that they have not yet had time to work out their own own interpretation or even that they are assuming a bland exterior to hide their inner uncertainty and concern.” (Latané and Rodin 1969, p. 199).

  19. The second quote in the previous note seems to indicate the plausibility of this assumption.

  20. When constructing APU products, a state in the product model is an ordered pair \((s,\sigma )\) of a state \(s\) and and action \(\sigma \). In this pair, \(s\) may again be such a pair. Say that a predecessor of \(s'\) is any \(s\) that occurs in any of the ordered pairs of \(s'\), including \(s'\) itself.

  21. It is possible to give agents a choice of interpretation by invoking transition rules with interpretation rules as possible solutions. In the present, agents are given no choice of interpretation, and this construction is consequently skipped for simplicity.

  22. Each \({\mathbf {E}_{\mathbf{2}}}_{j}\) functions as a truthful public announcement of \(pre(\rho )\), for which the order of announcements does not matter (Baltag and Smets 2009): states are deleted, the remaining orderings staying as previous. Deleting simultaneously or in some sequence makes no difference.

  23. Though time has passed, beliefs have not changed, and this is known to all: \(\mathbf {S}_\mathbf{3}\models \bigwedge _{i\in \mathcal {A}}K_{i}(\bigwedge _{j\in \mathcal {A}}[\mathbf {S}_{\mathbf{1}}]B_{j}\varphi \rightarrow B_{j}\varphi )\) for \(\varphi \in \{A,\lnot A\}\).

  24. Strictly speaking, in the present model agents do not revise their beliefs. An additional operator is instead introduced to facilitate comparison with private beliefs. A belief revision policy may easily be defined using decision rules to the effect that agents update their beliefs under the suitable circumstances, see (Rendsvig 2013b).

  25. Concerning \(\mathbf {E}_{\mathbf{0}}\), it should be obvious how the APM must be altered to include further agents, while maintaining complete higher-order ignorance.

  26. Again, it should be obvious how \(\mathbb {E}_{\varGamma }\) may be altered to accommodate for a larger population.

  27. The shift was made to ease the exposition. Influenced agents require the notion of social beliefs, not necessary for Hesitators’ first choice.

  28. The requirement that \(i\) must have observed before acting on social beliefs ensures that agents do not intervene immediately after seeing the accident (a private belief that \(A\) would imply that \(SB_{i|G}A\), as agents then hold no beliefs regarding others’ beliefs).

  29. Cf. the tie-breaking rule used in the definition of social beliefs.

  30. See Latané and Darley (1968) for calculation of hypothetical baseline based on the alone condition.

  31. In a mixed population model, using City Dweller agents for the two confederates.

  32. Again in a mixed population model, using City Dweller agents for the two confederates.

  33. How well these individual studies conform to the pluralistic ignorance explanation of the bystander effect has not been checked.

  34. I.e., interchanging the \(\alpha ,\beta \) tie-breaking parameters. Alternatively, social beliefs could be defined by weighing others’ perceived beliefs higher than one’s own, or by moving to a threshold rule requiring e.g. perceived agreement with all peers as done in Seligman et al. (2013), Christoff and Hansen (2013).

References

  • Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. In G. Bonanno, W. van der Hoek, & M. Wooldridge (Eds.), Logic and the foundations of game and decision theory (LOFT 7), number Loft 7 in texts in logic and games (Vol. 3, pp. 9–58). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltag, A., Smets, S., et al. (2009). Talking your way into agreement: Belief merge by persuasive communication. In M. Baldoni (Ed.), Proceedings of the second multi-agent logics, languages, and organisations federated workshops, CEUR workshop proceedings (Vol. 494, pp. 129–141). Italy: Turin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benthem, J. V. (2007). Dynamic logic for belief revision. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 17(2), 129–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benthem, J. V. (2014). Logic in games. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benthem, J. V., Gerbrandy, J., & Pacuit, E. (2007). Merging frameworks for interaction: DEL and ETL. In D. Samet (Ed.), Proceedings of TARK 2007 (pp. 72–81).

  • Bicchieri, C., & Fukui, Y. (1999). The great illusion: Ignorance, informational cascades, and the persistence of unpopular norms. Business Ethics Quarterly, 9(1), 127–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., & Venema, Y. (2001). Modal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolander, T., & Birkegaard, M. (2011). Epistemic planning for single- and multi-agent systems. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 21(1), 9–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christoff, Z., & Hansen, J. U. (2013). A two-tiered formalization of social influence. In D. Grossi & O. Roy (Eds.), Logic, rationality, and interaction, lecture notes in computer science (pp. 68–81). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, R. (2007). Influence: The psychology of persuasion. UK: HarperCollins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dégremont, C. (2010). The temporal mind: Observations on the logic of belief change in interactive systems. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam.

  • Demey, L. (2011). Some remarks on the model theory of epistemic plausibility models. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 21(3–4), 375–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ditmarsch, H. V., & Kooi, B. (2008). Semantic results for ontic and epistemic change. In G. Bonanno, W. van der Hoek & M. Wooldridge (Eds.), Logic and the foundations of game and decision theory (LOFT 7) (pp. 87–117), Amsterdam University Press.

  • Fagin, R., Halpern, J. Y., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. Y. (1995). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbesleben, J. R., & Buckley, M. R. (2004). Pluralistic ignorance: Historical development and organizational applications. Management Decision, 42(1), 126–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammack, R., Imrich, W., & Klavzar, S. (2011). Handbook of product graphs, discrete mathematics and its applications (2nd ed.). Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, J. U. (2011). A logic toolbox for modeling knowledge and information in multi-agent systems and social epistemology. PhD thesis, Roskilde University.

  • Hansen, P. G., Hendricks, V. F., & Rendsvig, R. K. (2013). Infostorms. Metaphilosophy, 44(3), 301–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks, V. F., & Rasmussen, J. L. (2012). Nedtur! Finanskrisen forstået filosofisk. Copenhagen: Gyldendal Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Darley, J. M. (1968). Group inhibition of bystander intervention in emergencies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 10(3), 215–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Darley, J. M. (1970). The unresponsive bystander: Why doesn’t he help?. New York: Appleten-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Nida, S. (1981). Ten years of research on group size and helping. Psychological Bulletin, 89(2), 308–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latané, B., & Rodin, J. (1969). A lady in distress: Inhibiting effects of friends and strangers on bystander intervention. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 5, 189–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D., & McFarland, C. (1987). Pluralistic ignorance: When similarity is interpreted as dissimilarity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 298–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers, D. G. (2012). Social psychology (11th ed.). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prentice, D., & Miller, D. (1993). Pluralistic ignorance and alcohol use on campus: Some consequences of misperceiving the social norm. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 243–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proietti, C., & Olsson, E. J. (2013). A DDL approach to pluralistic ignorance and collective belief. Journal of Philosophical Logic, March, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rendsvig, R. K. (2013a). Aggregated beliefs and informational cascades. In D. Grossi & O. Roy (Eds.), Logic, rationality, and interaction, lecture notes in computer science (pp. 337–341). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rendsvig R. K. (2013b) Look and learn: Extracting information from actions of others, http://staff.science.uva.nl/~ulle/esslli-workshop-2013/papers/rendsvig.pdf.

  • Rendsvig, R. K., & Hendricks, V. F. (2013). Social proof in extensive games. (under review).

  • Schroeder, C. M., & Prentice, D. A. (1998). Exposing pluralistic ignorance to reduce alcohol use among college students. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 28(23), 2150–2180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, J., Girard, P., & Liu, F. (2013). Logical dynamics of belief change in the community. Semantic results for ontic and epistemic change. In G. Bonanno, W. V. D. Hoek, & M. Wooldridge (Eds.), Logic and the foundations of game and decision theory (LOFT 7), number Loft 7 in texts in logic and games (Vol. 3, pp. 87–117). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

  • Westphal, J. D., & Bednar, M. K. (2005). Pluralisitc ignorance in corporate boards and firms’ strategic persistence in response to low firm performance. Administrative Science Quarterly, 50, 262–298.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank the editors for organizing the CPH-LU workshops on social epistemology, as well as the participants of said workshops for valuable comments and discussion. The work has benefited especially from discussions with Henrik Boensvang and Vincent F. Hendricks. Carlo Proietti is thanked for his corrections to the manuscript. Finally, a warm Thank You to the two anonymous reviewers: the comments, criticisms and correction provided by your thorough reading of the original submission have been invaluable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rasmus K. Rendsvig.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rendsvig, R.K. Pluralistic ignorance in the bystander effect: informational dynamics of unresponsive witnesses in situations calling for intervention. Synthese 191, 2471–2498 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0435-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0435-0

Keywords

Navigation