Abstract
It is commonplace amongst epistemologists to note the importance of grasping or appreciating one’s evidence. The idea seems to be that agents cannot successfully utilize evidence without it. Despite the popularity of this claim, the nature of appreciating or grasping evidence is unclear. This paper develops an account of what it takes to appreciate the epistemic relevance of one’s evidence, such that it can be used for some specific conclusion. I propose a basing account on which appreciating evidence involves being able to correctly base. That is, the agent is disposed to base various conclusions on her evidence that are objectively supported by that evidence. She can also derive correct conclusions if her evidence were slightly different. This account is cognitively undemanding, and explains why appreciation is crucial for the core functions of using evidence, like excluding hypotheses and probabilistic reasoning. I contrast this view with possible rival accounts and argue that the rival accounts add nothing over and above the basing account.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The latter view also holds for Davidson. (Davidson, 1986)
That said, there is something plausible about demanding that having evidence means being able to use it for at least some conclusions. If that is right, it is a demand on having evidence that the agent appreciates its epistemic import for at least one conclusion.
For an overview on grasping, see (Baumberger et al., 2017, pp. 10–15).
An alternative starting point would have been the recent literature on the Taking Condition and inference. However, I take inference to be more demanding than merely using evidence. What follows will make it clear that introducing anything like a Taking Condition for appreciation would be too demanding, on most notions of Taking. See (Boghossian, 2014). Besides, as we shall see, taking grasping as a starting point allows for discussing some important elements potentially important for appreciation, that would not necessarily all appear in a discussion starting with theories of inference.
Pace Brandom. See (Brandom, 1994).
Schroeder is a rare opponent of this view. However, my account can be made compatible with his claims. See (Schroeder, 2011).
One can also think of this in Bayesian terms. See (Lin, 2024).
Valaris suggests something similar for reasoning. (Valaris, 2017)
It might be that appreciation is prior to something like proper basing, or successful basing. That would be fine, since neither are invoked to explain appreciation here. It is already granted that proper use of evidence would require appreciation. We could explain appreciation invoking basing, and then explain proper basing invoking appreciation. Another view is that successful or proper basing simply is basing plus appreciating the import of the base for the conclusion. Nothing about the basing view defended here blocks that move.
The problem with triviality is not so much that conclusions are entailed by the evidence, but rather that the conclusions are uninformative. Thus, drawing the conclusion that a complex theorem follows from a certain axiom can contribute to appreciation.
Novelty is also mentioned by Hills. See (Hills, 2015, p. 670).
This feature of coming in degrees can also be found in the literature on grasping. For example, (Hills, 2015)
Interestingly enough, Hills thinks that understanding why y entails believing that y, and also having a true belief about why y is the case. As is made clear here, nothing like that is required for appreciation. (Hills, 2015, p. 663).
Something similar is made explicit in (Baumberger et al., 2017, Sect. 4.2.2).
References
Andrews, K., & Beck, J. (2017). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal minds. Routledge.
Baumberger, C., Beisbart, C., & Brun, G. (2017). What is understanding? An overview of recent debates in Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. In S. G. C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from Epistemolgy and Philosophy of Science (pp. 1–34). Routledge.
Block, N. (1996). Conceptual role semantics. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Genealogy to Iqbal (pp. 242–256). Routledge.
Boghossian, P. (2014). What is inference? Philosophical Studies, 169(1), 1–18.
Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.
Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to Inferentialism. Harvard University Press.
Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford University Press.
Camp, E., & Shupe, E. (2017). Instrumental reasoning in Nonhuman animals. In K. Andrews, & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal minds (pp. 100–109). Routledge.
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2008). Evidence. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays. Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. (1986). A coherence theory of Truth and Knowledge. In E. LePore (Ed.), Truth and Interpretation. Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 307–319). Blackwell.
de Regt, H. W. (2009). The Epistemic Value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 585–597.
de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A Contextual Approach to Scientific understanding. Synthese, 144(1), 137–170. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-005-5000-4
Elgin, C. Z. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 33–42.
Emery, N., & Clayton, N. (2009). Tool use and physical cognition in birds and mammal. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 1, 27–33.
Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford University Press.
Grimm, S. R. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 515–535.
Grimm, S. R. (2014). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather, & O. Flanagan (Eds.), Virtue Epistemology Naturalized: Bridges between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science (pp. 329–345). Synthese Library.
Grimm, S. R. (2017). Making sense of the World: New essays on the philosophy of understanding. Oxford University Press.
Haack, S. (1993). Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. Wiley-Blackwell.
Hills, A. (2015). Understanding Why Noûs, 49(2), 661–688.
Hurley, S. L., & Nudds, M. (2006a). Rational animals? Oxford University Press.
Hurley, S. L., & Nudds, M. (2006b). The questions of animal rationality: Theory and evidence. In S. L. Hurley, & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals? Oxford University Press.
Kelly, T. (2016). Evidence. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/evidence/
Khalifa, K. (2012). Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation? Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 15–37.
Lin, H. (2024). Bayesian Epistemology. In E. N. Zalta & U. Nodelman (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2024). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2024/entries/epistemology-bayesian/
Littlejohn, C. (2013). No evidence is false. Acta Analytica, 28(2), 145–159. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-012-0167-z
Lyons, J. (2016). Experiential evidence? Philosophical Studies, 173(4), 1053–1079.
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Harvard University Press.
Neta, R. (2017). Your evidence is the set of facts that are manifest to you? In V. Mitova (Ed.), The factive turn in Epistemology. Cambridge University Press.
Neta, R. (2019). The basing relation. Philosophical Review, 128(2), 179–217. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-7374945
Newman, M. (2012). An Inferential Model of Scientific understanding. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26(1), 1–26.
Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. MIT Press.
Price, H. H. (1954). Belief and Will. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 28(1), 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristoteliansupp/28.1.1
Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and Epistemic Value. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 64, 19–43. https://doi.org/10.1017/s1358246109000046
Schroeder, M. (2011). What does it take to have a reason? In A. E. Reisner, & A. Steglich-Petersen (Eds.), Reasons for belief (pp. 201–222). Cambridge University Press.
Tolliver, J. (1982). Basing beliefs on reasons. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 15(1), 149–161.
Valaris, M. (2017). What reasoning might be. Synthese, 194(6). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1034-z
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. F. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Matt McGrath, Casey O’Callaghan, Allan Hazlett, Nic Koziolek, Harmen Ghijsen and Jon Kvanvig for their comments on earlier versions. I would also like to thank audiences at OZSW, Radboud and both the LOGOS and WashU WIPS. Finally, I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their comments.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing Interests
The author(s) declare none.
Additional information
Publisher’s note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Montessori, A. What is appreciation?. Philos Stud 182, 589–604 (2025). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-025-02284-1
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-025-02284-1