Skip to main content
Log in

Hybrid theories, psychological plausibility, and the human/animal divide

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A hybrid theory is any moral theory according to which different classes of individuals ought to be treated according to different principles. We argue that some hybrid theories are able to meet standards of psychological plausibility, by which we mean that it’s feasible for ordinary human beings to understand and act in accord with them. Insofar as psychological plausibility is a theoretical virtue, then, such hybrid theories deserve more serious consideration. To make the case for this view, we explain what psychological plausibility is and why we might value it, why the human/animal divide appears to be an entrenched feature of human psychology, and why Robert Nozick’s hybrid theory doesn’t go far enough. Finally, we make the case that a more promising psychologically plausible hybrid theory, with respect to humans and animals, will be (at least) at tribrid theory—that is, positing three domains rather than two.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As this definition suggests, hybrid theories are hybrid with respect to normative principles, not necessarily the values they recognize as fundamental. A form of consequentialism that says we ought to maximize both well-being and justice is committed to value pluralism, but it isn’t a hybrid theory in our sense of that term: there is only one normative principle. We’ll contrast hybrid theories with uniform theories (a single normative principle), rather than monist theories (a single fundamental value), to keep the theory / value distinction clear in what follows. Finally, we should note that some people also talk about hybrid theories in the context of role ethics, defending adoption of different normative principles based on the role you’re currently occupying; see, e.g., Stone (1988). We don’t discuss that conception here.

  2. Nozick may have recognized this in suggesting his hybrid view, but either way, and as we’ll discuss, we don’t think that Nozick’s hybrid view goes far enough in terms of psychological plausibility. This is no criticism of Nozick, as he didn’t actually endorse utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people. He dismissed the view as inadequate almost as soon as he introduced it.

  3. As Ingold (2000) and other anthropologists have argued, some cultures’ perceptions of animals diverge from the majority views expressed in the kinds of psychological studies discussed here. Though beliefs about human superiority can be found across a wide variety of cultures, there is also significant diversity in those beliefs. The results discussed here should be understood as being particularly pronounced in industrialized cultures.

  4. See: https://www.americanpetproducts.org/press_industrytrends.asp and https://data.worldbank.org/indicator/NY.GDP.MKTP.CD?year_high_desc=true.

  5. We won’t say much here about the grounds for moral ambition, other than that, in the cases we’re concerned about, it shouldn’t be terribly controversial. Practically all moral theories, including various contemporary forms of Kantianism and some kinds of contractarianism, agree that certain ways of treating animals are morally unacceptable; there is, for instance, no real debate about the moral merits of many of the practices that constitute intensive animal agriculture. Where we have that kind of agreement, we can plausibly say that the aim of moral ambition is theoretically neutral.

  6. It’s probably true, though, that people value consistency with respect to human beings much more than they value consistency with respect to animals. So, egalitarian views may be more psychologically plausible for humans than across species. Since we are able to stay more motivated to invest in change that makes the world more egalitarian for human beings, we can have more ambitious ideals for humans; since we are unable to stay as motivated to invest in in change that makes the world more egalitarian for animals, we can't have as ambitious ideals.

  7. https://www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2020/08/america-facing-monkey-shortage/615799/.

References

  • Angulo, E., & Courchamp, F. (2009). Rare species are valued big time. PLoS ONE, 4(4), e5215. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0005215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Radke, H. (2012). Don’t mind meat? The denial of mind to animals used for human consumption. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38, 247–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleske-Rechek, A., Nelson, L. A., Baker, J. P., & Brandt, S. J. (2010). Evolution and the trolley problem: People save five over one unless the one is young, genetically related, or a romantic partner. Journal of Social, Evolutionary, and Cultural Psychology, 4, 115–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caviola, L., Everett, J. A. C., & Faber, N. S. (2019). The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 116, 1011–1029.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2002). Can pets function as family members? Western Journal of Nursing, 24(6), 621–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costello, K., & Hodson, G. (2014). Lay beliefs about the causes of and solutions to dehumanization and prejudice: Do nonexperts recognize the role of human-animal relations? Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 44, 278–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courchamp, F., Angulo, E., Rivalan, P., et al. (2006). Rarity value and species extinction: The anthropogenic Allee effect. PLoS Biology, 4(12), e415. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.0040415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Groot, M., Drenthen, M., & de Groot, W. T. (2011). Public visions of the human/nature relationship and their implications for environmental ethics. Environmental Ethics, 33, 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dhont, K., & Hodson, G. (2014). Why do right-wing adherents engage in more animal exploitation and meat consumption? Personality and Individual Differences, 64, 12–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, S., & Kymlicka, W. (2011). Zoopolis: A political theory of animal rights. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1991). The science of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Gruen, L (Ed.). (2014). Dignity, captivity, and an ethics of sight. In L. Gruen (Ed.), The ethics of captivity (pp. 231–247). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hamlin, A., & Stemplowska, Z. (2012). Theory, ideal theory and the theory of ideals. Political Studies Review, 10, 48–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, N., & Loughnan, S. (2014). Dehumanization and infrahumanization. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 399–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hecht, J., & Horowitz, A. (2015). Seeing dogs: Human preferences for dog physical attributes. Anthrozoös, 28(1), 153–163.

  • Herrmann, P., Medin, D. L., & Waxman, S. R. (2012). When humans become animals: Development of the animal category in early childhood. Cognition, 122, 74–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, H. (2010). Some we love, some we hate, some we eat. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak, K. J., & Powell, D. (2016). Deontological coherence: A framework for commonsense moral reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 142, 1179–1203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, A. C., & Bekoff, M. (2007). Naturalizing anthropomorphism: Behavioral prompts to our humanizing of animals. Anthrozoös, 20(1), 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horta, O. (2016). Animal suffering in nature: The case for intervention. Environmental Ethics, 39(3), 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (2000). The perception of the environment. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ipsos MORI (2018). Public attitudes to animal research. Available at https://www.ipsos.com/sites/default/files/ct/news/documents/2019-05/18-040753-01_ols_public_attitudes_to_animal_research_report_v3_191118_public.pdf

  • Kasperbauer, T. J. (2017a). Mentalizing animals: Implications for moral psychology and animal ethics. Philosophical Studies, 174, 465–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kasperbauer, T. J. (2017b). Subhuman: The moral psychology of human attitudes to animals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Killoren, D., & Streiffer, R. (2020). Utilitarianism about animals and the moral significance of use. Philosophical Studies, 177(4), 1043–1063.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leddon, E., Waxman, S.R., Medin, D.L, Bang, M., & Washinawatok, K. (2012). One animal among many? Children’s understanding of the relation between humans and nonhuman animals. In G. Hayes & M. Bryant (Eds.), Psychology of culture (pp. 105–126). Hauppauge, NY: Nova Science Publishers.

  • Leyens, J.-P., Rodriguez-Torres, R., Rodriguez-Perez, A., Gaunt, R., Paladino, M., Vaes, J., & Demoulin, S. (2001). Psychological essentialism and the differential attribution of uniquely human emotions to ingroups and outgroups. European Journal of Social Psychology, 81, 395–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lew, D. K. (2015). Willingness to pay for threatened and endangered marine species: A review of the literature and prospects for policy use. Frontiers in Marine Science. https://doi.org/10.3389/fmars.2015.00096

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manfredo, M. J., et al. (2020). The changing sociocultural context of wildlife conservation. Conservation Biology, 34(6), 1549–1559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, C. J. C., & McCulloch, S. (2005). Student attitudes on animal sentience and use of animals in society. Journal of Biological Education, 40, 17–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, C. J. C., Izmirli, S., Aldavood, S. J., Alonso, M., Choe, B. I., Hanlon, A., Handziska, A., Illmann, G., Keeling, L., Kennedy, M., Lee, G. H., Lund, V., Mejdell, C., Pelagic, V. R., & Rehn, T. (2012). Students’ attitudes to animal welfare and rights in Europe and Asia. Animal Welfare, 21, 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Power, E. (2008). Furry families: Making a human-dog family through home. Social and Cultural Geography, 9(5), 535–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rottman, J. (2014). Breaking down biocentrism: Two distinct forms of moral concern for nature. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2015). Hindering harm and preserving purity: How can moral psychology save the planet? Philosophy Compass, 10, 134–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sevillano, V., & Fiske, S. T. (2016). Warmth and competence in animals. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 46, 276–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, C. (1988). Earth and other ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swann, W. B., Gómez, A., Dovidio, J. F., Hart, S., & Jetten, J. (2010). Dying and killing for one’s group: Identity fusion moderates responses to intergroup versions of the trolley problem. Psychological Science, 21, 1176–1183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentini, L. (2012). Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map. Philosophy Compass, 7, 654–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wainger, L. A., Helcoski, R., Farge, K. W., Espinola, B. A., & Green, G. T. (2018). Evidence of a shared value for nature. Ecological Economics, 154, 107–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallach, A. D., Bekoff, M., Nelson, M. P., & Ramp, D. (2015). Promoting predators and compassionate conservation. Conservation Biology, 29, 1481–1484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waytz, A., Iyer, R., Young, L., et al. (2019). Ideological differences in the expanse of the moral circle. Nature Communications, 10, 4389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallmo, K., & Lew, D. K. (2012). Public willingness to Pay for recovering and downlisting threatened and endangered marine species. Conservation Biology, 26(5), 830–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, D. (2013). Demands of justice, feasible alternatives, and the need for causal analysis. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice, 16, 325–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilks, M., Caviola, L., & Kahane, G. (2021). Children prioritize humans over animals less than adults do. Psychological Science, 32(1), 27–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bob Fischer.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fischer, B., Palmer, C. & Kasperbauer, T.J. Hybrid theories, psychological plausibility, and the human/animal divide. Philos Stud 180, 1105–1123 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01743-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01743-9

Keywords