Skip to main content
Log in

Exhaustive Interpretation of Complex Sentences

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In terms of Groenendijk and Stokhof’s (1984) formalization of exhaustive interpretation, many conversational implicatures can be accounted for. In this paper we justify and generalize this approach. Our justification proceeds by relating their account via Halpern and Moses’ (1984) non-monotonic theory of ‘only knowing’ to the Gricean maxims of Quality and the first sub-maxim of Quantity. The approach of Groenendijk and Stokhof (1984) is generalized such that it can also account for implicatures that are triggered in subclauses not entailed by the whole complex sentence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Atlas, J.D. and Levinson, S.C., 1981, “It-clefts, informativeness and logical form,” in Radical Pragmatics, P. Cole, ed., New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., “Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface,” Manuscript, University of Milan.

  • Gazdar, G., 1979, Pragmatics, London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M., 1995, “Quantity, volubility, and some varieties of discourse,” Linguistics and Philosophy 18: 83–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P., 1967, “Logic and Conversation,” typescript from the William James Lectures, Harvard University. Published in P. Grice (1989), Studies in the Way of Worlds, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J. and Stokhof, M., 1984, “Studies in the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers,” Ph.D. Thesis, University of Amsterdam.

  • Halpern, J.Y. and Moses, Y., 1984, “Towards a theory of knowledge and ignorance,” pp. 165–193 in Proceedings of 1984 Non-Monotonic Reasoning Workshop, American Association for Artificial Intelligence, New Paltz, NY.

  • Harnisch, R.M., 1976, “Logical form and implicature,” pp. 313–391 in An Integrated Theory of Linguistic Ability, T.G. Bever, eds., New York: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., 1982, “The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases,” Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Hirschberg, J., 1985, “A theory of scalar implicature,” Ph.D. Thesis, UPenn.

  • Horn, L., 1972, “The semantics of logical operators in English,” Ph.D. Thesis, UCLA.

  • Horn, L., 1989, A Natural History of Negation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., 1981, “A theory of truth and semantic representation,” pp. 277–322 in Formal Methods in the Study of Language, Groenendijk, eds., Amsterdam.

  • Landman, F., 2000, Events and Plurality: The Jeruzalem Lectures, Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leech, G.N., 1983, Principles of Pragmatics, London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S.C., 1983, Pragmatics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S.C., 2000, Presumptive Meanings. The Theory of Generalized Conversational Implicature, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matsumoto, Y., 1995, “The conversational condition on Horn scales,” Linguistics and Philosophy 18: 21–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J., 1980, “Circumscription – a form of non-monotonic reasoning,” Artificial Intelligence 13: 27–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merin, A., 1994, Decision–Theoretic Pragmatics, Lecture Notes read in Course BA 5, Copenhagen Business School, Denmark.

  • Sauerland, U., 2004, “Scalar implicatures of complex sentences,” Linguistics and Phiolosophy 27, 367–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, K., 2003, “You may read it now or later,” Master Thesis, University of Amsterdam.

  • Soames, S., 1982, “How presuppositions are inherited: A solution to the projection problem,” Linguistic Inquiry 13: 483–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spector, B., 2003, “Scalar implicatures: Exhaustivity and Gricean reasoning?,” in Proceedings of the ESSLLI 2003 Student session, B. ten Cate, ed., Vienna.

  • van Benthem, J., 1989, “Semantic parallels in natural language and computation,” pp. 331–375 in Logic Colloquium ‘87, H. D. Ebbinghaus, et al., eds., Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Hoek, W., Jaspers, J., and Thijsse, E., 1999, “Persistence and minimality in epistemic logic,” Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 27: 25–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van der Hoek, W., Jaspers J., and Thijsse, E., 2000, “A general approach to multiagent minimal knowledge,” pp. 254–268 in Proceedings JELIA 2000, M. Ojeda-Aciego, et al. eds., Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, R. and Schulz, K., “Pragmatic meaning and non-monotonic reasoning: The case of exhaustive interpretation,” submitted, University of Amsterdam.

  • von Stechow, A. and Zimmermann, T.E., 1984, “Term answers and contextual change,” Linguistics 22: 3–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wainer, J., 1991, “Uses of nonmonotonic logic in natural language understanding: Generalized implicatures,” Ph.D. Thesis, Pennsylvania State University.

  • Zimmermann, T.E., 2000, “Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility,” Natural Language Semantics 8: 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katrin Schulz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

van Rooij, R., Schulz, K. Exhaustive Interpretation of Complex Sentences. J Logic Lang Inf 13, 491–519 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-004-2118-6

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-004-2118-6

Key words

Navigation